The behavioral revolution of the 1950s and 1960s consciously minimized the importance of formal rules in social interaction.
In light of that, probably the most innovative and far-reaching idea that came out of Arrovian social choice was neoinstitutionalism
– the claim that rules can have an independent and sometimes counterintuitive effect on legislative outcomes.
Once again, natural legislative settings did not supply much definitive evidence one way or the other. Even if scholars could
point to a significant rule change – for example, the change in the Senate cloture rule in 1975 – and even if that change
coincided with a change in the pattern of legislation, it was impossible to sort out whether the rule change was causal, spurious,
or incidental to the policy change. One research agenda that followed from Arrovian social choice was to examine the effect
of rules themselves, while holding preferences constant.
Procedural Rules: Structure-Induced Equilibrium
The institutional approach was kicked off by
Shepsle (
1979), who initiated a florescence of theory about institutions as constraints on majority rule instability. For example, Shepsle
argues that germaneness rules, which limited voting to one dimension at a time, would induce a structure-induced equilibrium
located at the issue-by-issue median.
McKelvey
and Ordeshook (
1984) ran experiments showing that issue-by-issue voting does not seem to constrain outcomes to the proposed structure-induced equilibrium, as long as subjects can communicate openly.
In Figure 25.2, player 5 is the median voter in the X dimension, as is player 4 in the Y dimension. The results indicate a
good deal of logrolling, for instance, by the 1, 2, and 5
coalition, that pulls outcomes away from the structure-induced equilibrium. They conclude that theorists who “seek to uncover
the effects of procedural rules and institutional constraints must take cognizance of incentives and opportunities for people
to disregard those rules and constraints” (201). The germaneness rule does not seem a sturdy source of majority rule stability.
Figure 25.2. Majority Rule with Issue-by-Issue Voting
Source: McKelvey and Ordeshook (
1984)
Forward and Backward Agendas
Wilson
(
1986, 2008b) ran experiments on a different procedural variation – forward-moving agendas versus backward-moving agendas. A forward-moving
agenda considers the first proposal against the status quo, the second alternative against the winner of the first vote, and
so on. Each new proposal is voted on against the most recent winner. Presumably, the first successful proposal will be in
the
winset of the status quo, where the winset of X is the set of alternatives that defeat X
by majority rule. A core has an empty winset, but when there is no core, every alternative has a nonempty winset. The winset
of the status quo is the propeller-shaped figure shown in
Figure 25.3.
Figure 25.3. Effect of Backward and Forward Agendas
Source: Wilson (2008b)
An alternative is a backward-moving agenda, in which alternatives are voted on in backward order from the order in which they
were proposed. If alternatives 1, 2, and 3 are proposed in that order, then the first vote is between 2 and 3, with the winner
against 1, and the winner of that against the status quo. With this agenda, the final outcome should be either the status
quo or an alternative in the winset of the status quo. Theoretically, a backward-moving agenda is more constrained – more
predictable – than a forward-moving agenda.
Figure 25.3 shows one typical voting trajectory for each treatment. The soft gray line shows a typical forward-moving agenda. The first
proposal was in the winset of the status quo, backed by voters 2, 3, and 4. Subsequent moves were supported by coalitions
3, 4, and 5; then 1, 2, and 5; and then 2, 3, and 4 to restore the first successful proposal and complete a cycle. A forward-moving
agenda did nothing to constrain majority rule instability.
The dark line shows that the first alternative introduced was not in the winset of the status quo, so the final vote resulted
in the imposition of the status quo. This could have been avoided with strategic voting by player 5 on the penultimate step,
leaving the committee with an outcome closer to 5's ideal point than the status quo.
Overall, Wilson (
2008b, 886) reports that eight of twelve experiments run with the backward-moving agenda treatment were at the initial status quo,
and the other four trials were in the winset of the status quo. This contrasted sharply with the forward-moving agenda, which
never ended at the original status quo and frequently cycled through the policy space.
The conclusion is that forward-moving agendas do not constrain majority rule instability or provide the leverage necessary
for accurate prediction. However, the backward-moving agenda is an institution that does effectively constrain majority rule.
Monopoly Agenda Control
In simple majority rule, every majority coalition has the power and motivation to move an outcome from outside its Pareto-preferred
set to some point inside. No point outside the Pareto set of every majority coalition can be in equilibrium. When the Plott
symmetry conditions hold, a single internal voter's ideal point is included in every majority coalition's Pareto set. Because
there is no point that is internal to the Pareto sets of all decisive coalitions, there is no core. Instability is the result
of too many decisive majority coalitions.
The rules can create stability by mandating that some majority coalitions are not decisive. For example, the rules may specify
that every proposal to be considered must be approved by a single actor – the agenda monopolist. In other words, every majority
coalition that does not include the agenda monopolist is not decisive.
This greatly reduces the number of decisive majority coalitions. In particular, the intersection of the Pareto sets for all
decisive coalitions is guaranteed to include only one point – the agenda setter's ideal point. As a result, the core of a
game with an agenda monopolist necessarily includes the agenda setter's ideal point.
To test the effect of this institutional feature on majority rule instability,
Wilson (
2008b) ran experiments with constant preferences and no simple majority rule core. In one treatment, there was an open agenda,
and in the other, a monopoly agenda setter. In this latter case, the agenda setter's ideal point was the unique core. Wilson
showed that the outcomes in the open agenda had high variance; the outcomes with an agenda setter had lower variance and were
significantly biased toward the agenda setter's ideal
point.
Figure 25.4 shows the trajectory for a typical agenda setter experiment. The agenda setter, player 5, consistently plays off the coalition
with 1 and 2 against the coalition with 3 and 4. The power to do so means, of course, that majority rule instability can be
replaced by coherence – at the cost of making one player a dictator.
Figure 25.4. Effect of Monopoly Agenda Setting
Source: Wilson (2008b)
Shepsle's (1979) original hypothesis – that institutional variations of majority rule can sharply constrain majority rule
instability and allow prediction of experimental outcomes – has proven both true and of the utmost significance for studying
democracy. Rules defining control over the agenda, the size of the majority, or bicameralism have all been shown to lead to
an improvement in prediction accuracy.
However, the patterning of outcomes in simple majority rule experiments, as illustrated in
Figure 25.1, reveals that institutional rules are a sufficient, but not necessary, condition for constraint. Experimental outcomes cluster
with simple majority rule – even without monopoly agenda control, germaneness rules, or a backward-moving agenda.
Despite the fact that McKelvey (
1976) was the author of what came to be known as the “chaos” theorem, he himself was an early advocate of finding a preference-based
solution concept. That is, he believed that the actions of rational voters, negotiating alternative majority coalitions to
advance their own preferences, would somehow constrain majority rule to a reasonable subset of the entire policy space – without
requiring the constraint of rules other than simple majority rule. McKelvey, Ordeshook, and Winer (
1978) advanced the solution concept known
as the “competitive solution” for simple majority rule games. By understanding coalition formation as a kind of market that
established the appropriate “price” for coalitional pivots,
McKelvey et al. generated predictions that worked rather well for five-person spatial games. However, the authors gave up
on the competitive solution when other experimental results, using discrete alternatives, proved to be sensitive to cardinal
payoffs (McKelvey and Ordeshook
1983).
The Uncovered Set
An alternative preference-based solution concept was the uncovered set, developed in the context of discrete alternatives
by
Miller (
1980). It is a solution concept that identifies a set of moderate outcomes in the “center” of the space of
ideal points as the likely outcome of strategic voting and the coalition formation process.
Outcomes that are far from the “center” of the ideal points are certain to be
covered, where a covered alternative B is one such that there is some alternative A that beats B, and every alternative X that beats
A also beats B. If A covers B, then it implies that B is a relatively unattractive alternative with a large enough winset
to encompass the winset of A.
2An alternative is in the uncovered set if it is not covered by any other alternative. If D is uncovered, then, for every C that beats D, then there is some alternative
X such that D beats X and X beats C. This means that an uncovered alternative can either defeat every other alternative directly
or via an intermediate alternative. The uncovered set is the set of centrist outcomes that constitute the (unstable) center
of the policy space.
Early theoretical results showed that the uncovered set had several striking characteristics. For one thing, the uncovered
set was shown to be a subset of the Pareto set. For another, it shrank in size as preference profiles approximated those producing
a core, and it collapsed to the core when the core existed
(Cox
1987).
The uncovered set has proven to be of interest to both noncooperative game theory and cooperative game theory. The reason
is that, as McKelvey (
1986) argues, the uncovered set contains the noncooperative equilibria arising under a variety of institutional rules.
Shepsle
and Weingast (
1984) propose that “the main conclusion is that institutional arrangements, specifically mechanisms of agenda construction, impose
constraints on majority outcomes” (49). McKelvey (
1986) took away a quite different interpretation. In an article provocatively titled “Covering, Dominance and Institution-Free
Properties of Social Choice,”
McKelvey (
1986) argues that if a single solution concept encompasses the equilibrium results of a variety of institutions, then the choice
process is “institution free.” That is, “the actual social choice may be rather insensitive to the choice of institutional
rules” (McKelvey
1986, 283).
In the article, McKelvey (
1986) demonstrates that various distinct institutions theoretically lead to equilibrium outcomes inside the uncovered set. He
confirmed the result that legislative voting under a known, fixed agenda should lead inside the uncovered set. Cooperative
coalition formation should lead to outcomes in the uncovered set, as should two-candidate elections. Hence, McKelvey could
argue, constraint on simple majority rule instability seemed to be “institution-free” – the ideal points of voters provide
enough information to predict where outcomes should end up, even without knowing exactly which of the three institutions would
be used to select the outcome.
The problem was that neither McKelvey nor anyone else knew exactly how much the uncovered set constrained majority rule decision
making because no one had a way to characterize the uncovered set for a given set of preferences.
Looking Backward with the Uncovered Set
The recent invention of an algorithm for precise estimation of the uncovered set
(Bianco, Jeliazkov, and Sened
2004) has allowed the testing of that solution concept against previously reported experimental results
(Bianco et al.
2006) and with new data (Bianco et al. 2008).
Figure 25.1 is a case in point because it shows the Fiorina-Plott (
1978) noncore experiments. The uncovered set for their experimental configuration of preferences is shown as the small shaded
region. In
Figure 25.1, the uncovered set is a relatively precise and promising predictor of the noncore experiments. The same is true for the uncovered
set shown (as a gray shaded region) for the McKelvey-Ordeshook experiments on germaneness and communication – nearly all outcomes
were in the uncovered set (
Figure 25.2). For the McKelvey-Ordeshook experiments, with different proposal rules and different degrees of constraint on communication,
the uncovered set performs equally well.
We can do the same with other majority rule experiments run in two-dimensional policy space with simple majority rule. The
results for a series of simple majority rule experiments are shown in
Table 25.1. Out of 272 total majority rule experiments administered by eight different teams of experimentalists, ninety-three percent
were in the uncovered set.
Table 25.1. Testing the Uncovered Set with Previous Majority Rule Experiments
Testing the Uncovered Set
Although the results in
Table 25.1 are noteworthy, the experiments reported there were
not designed to test the uncovered set. In particular, several of these experiments typically imposed maximal dispersion of
ideal points, resulting in quite large uncovered sets – perhaps an “easy test” of the uncovered set. Consequently,
Bianco et al. (2008) designed computer-mediated, five-person, majority rule experiments with two treatments creating relatively
small and nonoverlapping uncovered sets – designed to be a difficult case for the uncovered case.
The two treatments were based on two configurations of preferences shown in
Figures 25.5a and 25.5b. In each case, the preferences were “clustered” rather than maximally dispersed; this had the effect of producing smaller
uncovered sets. Configurations 1 and 2 are identical except for the location of player 1's ideal point. In configuration 1,
player 1 was clustered with players 4 and 5; in configuration 2, player 1 was in an even tighter majority cluster with players
2 and 3. The change in player 1's ideal point shifted the uncovered set dramatically.
The alternative hypothesis is what may be called the partisan hypothesis, based on the obvious clustering of ideal points.
Poole and Rosenthal (
1997), Bianco and Sened (
2005), and others have estimated the preferences of real-world legislatures – finding that they are organized in two partisan
clusters. So, the differences between the two configurations could be thought of as a shift of majority party control with
a change in representation of district 1. The members of the majority cluster in either configuration could easily and quickly
pick an alternative within the convex hull of their three ideal points and, resisting the attempts by the members of the minority
cluster, vote to adjourn.
Figure 25.5. Sample Majority Rule Trajectory for Configuration 1
Source: Bianco et al. (2008), used with permission of The Society for Political Methodology.
It is worth noting that the uncovered set in this setting is primarily located between the Pareto sets for the majority and
minority parties, and thus will only occur if there is a
significant amount of cross-partisan coalition formation and no party solidarity. In other words, in configuration 1, if players
4 and 5 can offer player 3 an outcome that is more attractive than that offered by players 1 and 2, then the uncovered set
has a chance of being realized. But if player 3, for example, refuses offers especially made to move him or her away from
his or her “natural” allies, then the outcome should be well within the Pareto set of the partisan coalition, rather than
in the uncovered set.
Figure 25.5a shows a sample committee trajectory for configuration 1. As can be seen, there was a great deal of majority rule instability.
A variety of coalitions formed, including coalitions across clusters. However, the instability was constrained by the borders
of the uncovered set. Despite frequent successful moves to outcomes close to the contract curve between players 1 and 3, players
4 and 5 were repeatedly able to pull the outcome modestly in their direction by offering player 3 more than player 1 had offered.
Configuration 2 is more difficult; any outcome in the Pareto set of the tight cluster of 1, 4, and 5 is very attractive to
these three voters – making it hard for 2 and 3 to offer proposals that will break up the 1-4-5 coalition. Yet, even here,
players 2 and 3 occasionally make proposals that attract support from members of the majority cluster. This tends to pull
outcomes out of the 1-2-3 Pareto triangle toward the minority cluster. The result is cycling within the smaller uncovered
set.
Twenty-eight experiments were done with each treatment.
Figure 25.6a shows the final outcome in the twenty-eight configuration 1 experiments. The percentage of final outcomes in the uncovered
set was 100 percent.
Figure 25.6b shows the final outcomes in the twenty-eight configuration 2 experiments. In four committees, the outcome seemed to be influenced
by fairness considerations.
Figure 25.6. (a) Uncovered Set and Outcomes for Configuration 1
(b) Uncovered Set and Outcomes for Configuration 2
Source: Bianco et al. (2008), used with permission of The Society for Political Methodology.
In seven of the committees, the opposite occurred – the partisan 1-4-5 coalition formed and imposed an outcome in their Pareto
triangle but outside the uncovered set. In either case, the presence of an extremely tight cluster of three ideal points seemed
to decrease the likelihood of the kind of multilateral coalition formation that could pull outcomes into the uncovered set.
Overall, the proportion of configuration 2 outcomes in the uncovered set was still 60.7 percent.
Although fairness considerations or partisan solidarity can result in outcomes outside the uncovered set, it seems fair to
say that, as long as the coalition formation process is cross-partisan and vigorous, the outcome will likely be within the
uncovered set. Overall, the uncovered set experiments suggest that the majority rule coalition formation process does constrain
outcomes, as argued by
McKelvey (
1986). Even more important, outcomes tend to converge to centrist, compromise
outcomes.
Baron, David, and John Ferejohn. 1989. “Bargaining in Legislatures.” American Political Science Review 83: 1181–206.
Bianco, William T., Ivan Jeliazkov, and Itai Sened. 2004. “The Uncovered Set and the Limits of Legislative Action.” Political Analysis 12: 256–76.
Bianco, William T., Michael S. Lynch, Gary J. Miller, and Itai Sened. 2006. “‘Theory Waiting To Be Discovered and Used’: A Reanalysis of Canonical Experiments on Majority Rule Decision-Making.” Journal of Politics 68: 837–50.
Bianco, William T., Michael S. Lynch, Gary Miller, and Itai Sened. 2008. “The Constrained Instability of Majority Rule: Experiments on the Robustness of the Uncovered Set.” Political Analysis 16: 115–37.
Bianco, William T., and
Itai Sened.
2005. “
Uncovering Conditional Party Government: Reassessing the Evidence for Party Influence in Congress and State Legislatures.”
American Political Science Review 99:
361–72.
Bottom, William, Cheryl Eavey, and Gary Miller. 1996. “Getting to the Core: Coalitional Integrity as a Constraint on the Power of Agenda Setters.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 40: 298–319.
Clinton, Joshua D., and Adam Meirowitz. 2001. “Agenda Constrained Legislator Ideal Points and the Spatial Voting Model.” Political Analysis 9: 242–59.
Cox, Gary W. 1987. “The Uncovered Set and the Core.” American Journal of Political Science 31: 408–22.
Druckman, James N., Donald Green, James Kuklinski, and Arthur Lupia. 2006. “The Growth and Development of Experimental Research in Political Science.” American Political Science Review 100: 627–36.
Eavey, Cheryl L. 1991. “Patterns of Distribution in Spatial Games.” Rationality and Society 3: 450–74.
Endersby, James W. 1993. “Rules of Method and Rules of Conduct: An Experimental Study on Two Types of Procedure and Committee Behavior.” Journal of Politics 55: 218–36.
Fiorina, Morris P., and Charles R. Plott. 1978. “Committee Decisions under Majority Rule: An Experimental Study.” American Political Science Review 72: 575–98.
Grelak, Eric, and Kenneth Koford. 1997. “A Re-Examination of the Fiorina-Plott and Eavey Voting Experiments.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 32: 571–89.
Jeong, Gyung-Ho. 2008. “Testing the Predictions of the Multidimensional Spatial Voting Model with Roll Call Data.” Political Analysis 16: 179–96.
Jeong, Gyung-Ho, Gary Miller, and Itai Sened. 2009. “Closing the Deal: Negotiating Civil Rights Legislation.” American Political Science Review 103: 588–606.
King, Ronald R. 1994. “An Experimental Investigation of Super Majority Voting Rules: Implications for the Financial Accounting Standards Board.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 25: 197–217.
Laing, James D., and Scott Olmstead. 1978. “An Experimental and Game-Theoretic Study of Committees.” In Game Theory and Political Science, ed. Peter C. Ordeshook. New York: New York University Press, 215–81.
McKelvey, Richard D. 1976. “Intransitivities in Multidimensional Voting Models and Some Implications for Agenda Control.” Journal of Economic Theory 12: 472–82.
McKelvey, Richard D. 1986. “Covering, Dominance and Institution Free Properties of Social Choice.” American Journal of Political Science 30: 283–314.
McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook. 1983. “Some Experimental Results That Fail to Support the Competitive Solution.” Public Choice 40: 281–91.
McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook. 1984. “An Experimental Study of the Effects of Procedural Rules on Committee Behavior.” Journal of Politics 46: 182–205.
McKelvey, Richard D., and Peter C. Ordeshook. 1990. “A Decade of Experimental Research in Spatial Models of Elections and Committees.” In Advances in the Spatial Theory of Voting, eds. James M. Enelow and Melvin J. Hinich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 99–149.
McKelvey, Richard D., Peter C. Ordeshook, and Mark D. Winer. 1978. “The Competitive Solution for N-Person Games without Transferable Utility, with an Application to Committee Games.” American Political Science Review 72: 599–615.
Miller, Nicholas. 1980. “A New Solution Set for Tournament and Majority Voting.” American Journal of Political Science 24: 68–96.
Poole, Keith T., and Howard Rosenthal. 1997. Congress: A Political-Economic History of Roll-Call Voting. New York: Oxford University Press.
Riker, William H. 1982. Liberalism against Populism. San Francisco: Freeman.
Riker, William H. 1986. The Art of Political Manipulation. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Shepsle, Kenneth A. 1979. “Institutional Arrangements and Equilibria in Multidimensional Voting Models.” American Journal of Political Science 23: 27–59.
Shepsle, Kenneth A., and Barry R. Weingast. 1984. “Uncovered Sets and Sophisticated Voting Outcomes with Implications for Agenda Institutions.” American Journal of Political Science 28: 49–74.
Wilkerson, John. 1999. “‘Killer’ Amendments in Congress.” American Political Science Review 93: 535–52.
Wilson, Rick K. 1986. “Forward and Backward Agenda Procedures: Committee Experiments on Structurally Induced Equilibrium.” Journal of Politics 48: 390–409.
Wilson, Rick K. 2008a. “Endogenous Properties of Equilibrium and Disequilibrium in Spatial Committee Games.” In Handbook of Experimental Economics Results, eds. Charles R. Plott and Vernon Smith. Amsterdam: North Holland, 872–9.
Wilson, Rick K. 2008b. “Structure-Induced Equilibrium in Spatial Committee Games.” In Handbook of Experimental Economics Results, eds. Charles R. Plott and Vernon Smith. Amsterdam: North Holland, 880–8.
Wilson, Rick K., and Roberta Herzberg. 1987. “Negative Decision Powers and Institutional Equilibrium: Experiments on Blocking Coalitions.” Western Political Quarterly 40: 593–609.