4 Freud’s and Jung’s twentieth-century view of myth
The psychologizing of myth
In Paradise Lost (1667) Milton combines riveting descriptions of hell and paradise as places “out there” in the world with characterizations of them as states of mind. On the one hand hell, into which Satan and his retinue land after their fall from heaven, is a lake of fire, the light from which only makes the place darker. The beach is itself on fire and offers no respite from the heat:
On the other hand hell is a state of mind. Satan, upon awakening in hell, actually boasts that both heaven and hell are the product of mind and can therefore be established anywhere at will:
Later, Satan says the same, but now in self-doubt rather than arrogance, because he recognizes what he has lost and recognizes that, as evil, he turns everything into hell:
It is not just Satan the character who makes hell and paradise mental states. As author, Milton writes of Satan that
What for Milton is true of hell is also true of paradise. On the one hand it is a place “out there,” lovingly and lushly described:
On the other hand the archangel Michael, having consoled Adam with knowledge of the virtues that human beings can acquire only in the wake of the fall—faith, patience, temperance, love, and charity—concludes the following:
The psychologizing of the world is to be found even earlier than Milton, perhaps most famously in the description of hell by Mephistopheles in Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus:
Among modern theorists of myth, Jung is especially eager to trace the psychologizing of the world all the way back to ancient Gnostics and in turn to medieval alchemists. But for him, as for Freud, the twentieth century is distinctive in its separation of the psychological from the physical: the separation of the mind from the world, of the inner from the outer. By contrast, Milton somehow combines the two. Rather than reducing hell and paradise to states of mind, he somehow makes them at once physical places and states of mind. That position, as we shall see, is distinct from at once the nineteenth-century position, where myth is just about the physical world, and the twentieth-century one, where myth, at least for Freud and Jung, is just about the mind.
For Freud and Jung, the psychologizing of the world has not meant the reduction of the world to the mind, as in idealism. Nor has it meant the reduction of the world to a human creation, as in constructionism. On the contrary, it has meant the differentiation of the world “out there”—a world independent of humans—from the imposition upon it of elements belonging to humans rather than the world. Projections onto the outer world, which had taken the form of gods, have by now largely been withdrawn. The outer world has come to be recognized as a natural rather than a supernatural domain, to be explained by impersonal scientific laws rather than by the decisions of gods.
For both Freud and Jung, the rise of science has spelled the fall of religion. Unlike Freud, Jung laments that the loss of religion as an explanation of the world has simultaneously meant the loss of an effective means of tending to the unconscious. But Jung no less than Freud praises the triumph of the scientific explanation over the religious one.
Both Freud and Jung disentangle myth from religion, to which it had been tied. Religion minus myth had provided the gods. Myth had provided the biographies of the gods: stories of how the gods were born, how they grew up, and how they acquired and used their powers. Once myth had been psychologized, it was no longer about the physical world but was instead about the human world, specifically about the mind. Myth was no longer in competition with science and so could survive the demise of religion. Furthermore, there could now be secular myths, which were not even literally about gods—myths about nationalism, for example. In short, Freud and Jung, as twentieth-century theorists of myth, made myth safe, not for science but from science.
For Freud and Jung, the subject matter of myth is not, as for Milton, both the world and the mind but the mind, and not the conscious mind, as for Milton, but the unconscious one. For Freud, the function of myth is to vent the unconscious. For Jung, the function is to encounter the unconscious. For neither Freud nor Jung does myth make the unconscious conscious. On the contrary, myth ordinarily operates unconsciously and, at least for Freud, must operate unconsciously. Freud and Jung differ sharply over the nature of the unconscious and in turn over the reason that myth is needed to express it.
Freudians against nineteenth-century theorists of myth
It is conventionally assumed that, in the case of myth as in general, Jung is arguing against Freud. It is also commonly assumed that Freud or at least Freudians on myth are arguing against Jung and Jungians. But in fact both are arguing at least as much against nineteenth-century theorists like Tylor and Frazer as against each other. Before they can argue with each other over what psychologically myth is about, Freudians and Jungians must first show that myth is not about the physical world. Before they can argue with each other over how symbolically myth is to be read, Freudians and Jungians must first show that myth is not to be read literally.
In “The Theme of the Three Caskets” (1913) Freud comments on an interpretation made by nature mythologist E. Stucken of the choice of the caskets in The Merchant of Venice:
Along with Rank’s 1909 The Myth of the Birth of the Hero, to which Freud is referring, the other classic Freudian analysis of myth is Karl Abraham’s Dreams and Myths, also originally published in 1909. Both Abraham and Rank dismiss those theorists, called nature mythologists, who either take myth to be about the physical world rather than about the human mind or, worse, turn myths about humans into myths about the physical world. Rank is especially disdainful of theorists who turn myths about family life into symbols of natural processes—turning the story of Oedipus, for example, into a symbol of the triumph of light over darkness: “as given by a representative of the natural mythological mode of interpretation, Oedipus, who kills his father, marries his mother, and dies old and blind, is the solar hero who murders his procreator, the darkness; shares his couch with the mother, the gloaming, from whose lap, the dawn, he has been born, and dies blinded, as the setting sun” (Rank 1914, pp. 9–10). Rather than originating in the experience of the physical world, myth for Rank originates in the experience of the family and is then projected onto the world.
At times both Rank and Abraham less dismiss the view that myth is a depiction of the natural world than account psychoanalytically for the depiction. According to Rank, “We also hope to demonstrate that myths are … structures of the human faculty of imagination which may be secondarily transferred to the heavenly bodies with their baffling phenomena” (Rank 2003, p. 9). According to Abraham, “Creation is nothing but procreation divested of the sexual” (Abraham 1913, p. 41). Rank goes beyond Abraham in attributing the failure of nature mythologists to acknowledge the true subject or source of nature myths to resistance.1
Jung against nineteenth-century theorists of myth
Scorn for hapless nature mythologists is scarcely limited to Freudians. Jung is at least as dismissive. For example, Frazer, who epitomizes the nineteenth-century approach to myth, deems the subject matter of myth physical processes. For Frazer, the chief myths of all religions describe the death and rebirth of vegetation, a process symbolized by the myth of the death and rebirth of the god of vegetation. Thus “the story that Adonis spent half, or according to others a third, of the year in the lower world and the rest of it in the upper world, is explained most simply and naturally by supposing that he represented vegetation, especially the corn, which lies buried in the earth half the year and reappears above ground the other half” (Frazer 1922, p. 392).
Like Tylor, the other exemplar of the nineteenth-century approach, Frazer assumes that primitives themselves take their myths literally and must do so for their myths to explain events in the world. But Frazer breaks with Tylor in contending that myths about the decisions or actions of gods are in fact, albeit unrecognized by “primitives,” symbolic descriptions of natural processes themselves.
By contrast to Frazer, Jung interprets the myth of the death and rebirth of a god as a symbolic expression of a process that takes place not in the world but in the mind. That process is the return of the ego to the unconscious—a kind of temporary death of the ego—and its re-emergence, or rebirth, from the unconscious: “I need only mention the whole mythological complex of the dying and resurgent god and its primitive precursors all the way down to the re-charging of fetishes and churingas with magical force. It expresses a transformation of attitude by means of which a new potential, a new manifestation of life, a new fruitfulness, is created” (Jung 1971, p. 193).
Jung does not deny that the psychological process of the death and rebirth of the ego parallels the physical process of the death and rebirth of vegetation. He denies that the physical process accounts for the psychological one, let alone for the mythic one. For Frazer, the leap from vegetation to god is the product of logic and imagination: “primitives” observe the course of vegetation and hypothesize the existence of a god to account for it—even if, again, for Frazer, the god is a mere symbol of vegetation. For Jung, the leap is too great for the human imagination to make. Humans generally, not merely “primitives,” lack the creativity required to concoct consciously the notion of the sacred out of the profane. They can only transform the profane into a sacred that already exists for them. Humans must already have the idea of god in their minds and can only be projecting that idea onto vegetation and the other natural phenomena that they observe:
Even early Jung, who, perhaps under the influence of Freud, was prepared to give more weight to experience than later Jung was, distinguishes between the experience of the sun itself and the experience of the sun as a god. The experience of the sun provides the occasion for the manifestation of the sun archetype but does not cause that archetype:
It is not only allegories of physical processes that Jung rejects as the real subject matter of myth. It is also literal interpretations of myth like Tylor’s, which still make the subject matter outer rather than inner. For Tylor, myths are actual explanations of natural phenomena and not merely, as for Frazer, colorful descriptions of them. As indeed Tylor writes in exasperation at those who would interpret myths allegorically, “When the Apache Indian pointed to the sky and asked the white man, ‘Do you not believe that God, the Sun, … sees what we do and punishes us when it is evil?’ it is impossible to say that this savage was talking in rhetorical simile” (Tylor 1871, vol. 1, p. 262).
Jung conflates Tylor’s theory with Frazer’s, such as when he writes that “People are very loath to give up the idea that the myth is some kind of explanatory allegory of astronomical, meteorological, or vegetative processes” (Jung 1969 [“On Psychic Energy”], pp. 37–38). The phrase “explanatory allegory” conflates Tylor’s theory—myth as explanation—with Frazer’s—myth as allegory. Jung asks rhetorically “why,” if myth is really about the sun, do “the sun and its apparent motions … not appear direct and undisguised as a content of the myths” (Jung 1971, p. 444)? But the question is not in fact rhetorical. Tylor, even if not Frazer, would answer that a myth describes a sun god and not merely the sun exactly because the myth is about the sun god and not merely about the sun. Yet even if Jung were to distinguish Tylor’s view from Frazer’s, in reply to Tylor he would still invoke his fundamental claim that human beings cannot consciously invent gods. Humans can only project onto the world gods already in their minds. But why should he so limit human creativity, whether through reasoning, as for Tylor, or through sheer imagination? We are not told.
In any event myth for Jung is no more about gods than about the physical world. It is about the human mind. Myth must be read symbolically, as for Frazer, and the symbolized subject is a process, as likewise for Frazer, but the process is an inner rather than outer one. If on the one hand Jung would prefer Frazer’s interpretation over Tylor’s for reading myth symbolically rather than literally, on the other hand he would likely prefer Tylor’s interpretation over Frazer’s for appreciating the divine rather than merely natural referent of myth.
Jung interprets as projections not only nature myths but all other kinds of myths as well. He declares that “in fact, the whole of mythology could be taken as a sort of projection of the collective unconscious… . Just as the constellations were projected into the heavens, similar figures were projected into legends and fairytales or upon historical persons” (Jung 1969 [“The Structure of the Psyche”], p. 152).2
Hero myths, of which Jungians are especially enamored, are projections onto mere human beings of a divine or quasi-divine status: “the hero myth is an unconscious drama seen only in projection, like the happenings in Plato’s parable of the cave. The hero himself appears as a being of more than human stature” (Jung 1967, p. 391). Moderns, while often professing atheism, still create myths by projecting onto their fellow human beings exaggerated qualities that turn them into superhuman figures:
Once Jung differentiates a psychological interpretation of myth from a nonpsychological one, he must differentiate his particular psychological interpretation from Freud’s. But he cannot take on Freud until he has taken on the natural mythologists. He cannot confront his twentieth-century rival until he has, to his satisfaction, defeated his nineteenth-century ones. So ingrained was the nineteenth-century view that it took at least as much effort on the part of Freudians and Jungians alike to defeat it as it did to defeat each other’s twentieth-century view.
Yet Jung, for all his insistence on rejecting the physical world as relevant to myth, does return to the world through the concept of synchronicity, developed with the physicist Wolfgang Pauli. Synchronicity restores a link between humanity and the world that the withdrawal of projections still insisted on by Jung removes. Synchronicity refers to the coincidence between our thoughts and the behavior of the world, between what is inner and what is outer. Synchronicity is not itself myth, which would be an account of a synchronistic experience. Whether synchronicity succeeds in bringing myth back to the physical world is another issue. But Jung’s fascination with the concept shows that even he, who psychologizes myth (and everything else) more relentlessly than even Freud does, cannot resist the allure of the external world.
Bibliography
Abraham, Karl. 1913. Dreams and Myths [1909 in German], tr. William A. White. Nervous and Mental Disease Monograph Series, no. 15. New York: Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease Publishing.
Frazer, J. G. (James George). 1922. The Golden Bough. Abridged ed. London: Macmillan [1st unabridged ed. 1890].
Freud, Sigmund. 1953 [1913]. The Interpretation of Dreams [1900 in German], in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (SE), eds. and trs. James Strachey et al. SE 4–5, pp. 339–627. London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analysis.
Freud, Sigmund. 1958 [1925]. “The Theme of the Three Caskets” [1913 in German]. SE 12, pp. 289–301.
Freud, Sigmund. 1961 [1953]. The Future of an Illusion [1927 in German]. SE 21, pp. 3–58.
Jung, C. G. 1966 [1953]. Two Essays on Analytical Psychology. The Collected Works of C. G. Jung (CW), eds. Sir Herbert Read et al., trs. R. F. C. Hull et al., vol. 7. 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Jung, C. G. 1967 [1956]. Symbols of Transformation. CW 5. 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Jung, C. G. 1968 [1959]. The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious. CW 9, part 1. 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Jung, C. G. 1969 [1960]. The Structure and Dynamics of the Psyche. CW 8. 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Jung, C. G. 1971. Psychological Types. CW 6. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Jung, C. G. 1973–1974. Letters, eds. Gerhard Adler and Aniela Jaffé, tr. R. F. C. Hull. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Raglan, Lord. 1936. The Hero. London: Methuen.
Rank, Otto. 1914. The Myth of the Birth of the Hero [1909 in German], 1st ed., trs. F. Robbins and Smith Ely Jelliffe. Nervous and Mental Disease Monograph Series, no. 18. New York: Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease Publishing.
Rank, Otto. 1932. Art and Artist [unpublished in German], tr. Charles Francis Atkinson. New York: Knopf.
Rank, Otto. 1992. The Incest Theme in Literature and Legend [1912 in German], 1st ed., tr. Gregory C. Richter. Introduction by Peter L. Rudnytsky. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 2nd ed. 1926 [in German].
Rank, Otto. 2003. The Myth of the Birth of the Hero [1922 in German], 2nd ed., trs. E. James Lieberman and Gregory C. Richter. Introduction by Robert A. Segal. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Rank, Otto, and Hanns Sachs. 1916. The Significance of Psychoanalysis for the Mental Sciences [1913 in German], tr. Charles R. Payne. Nervous and Mental Disease Monograph Series, no. 23. New York: Nervous and Mental Disease Publishing.
Tylor, E. B. (Edward Burnett). 1871. Primitive Culture. 2 vols. 1st ed. London: Murray.