Digital divides, just like IP, constitute a huge field which has attracted much research from a range of disciplines which
a section in a chapter cannot address comprehensively. This section will therefore attempt to tease out the ethically and
philosophically interesting aspects of digital divides which will allow us to develop the argument that digital divides share
relevant aspects with other social issues of computer ethics.
Scholarly attention has been paid to digital divides since the middle of the 1990s (Hacker and Mason
2003). It has been pointed out, however, that the underlying concept is unclear. Warschauer (
2003) highlights that the term implies a bipolar division between those who have access and those who do not, which is misleading
as connectivity falls along a continuum. Walsham (2005, p. 9) has called the term ‘somewhat ambiguous and hard to define’
but points to the underlying problem of the gap between rich and poor, which may be exacerbated by technology. In the US,
the National Telecommunications and Information Administration has published a number of reports, some of which share the
title
‘Falling through the Net’ (see
www.ntia.doc.gov), which focus on digital divides within the country. Dewan and Riggins (
2005) suggest five different categories of digital divides. The different viewpoints explain why it is more suitable to use the
term digital divides in the plural form. They also indicate why some scholars have suggested dropping the term altogether
in favour of a more telling one, such as
‘digital exclusion’ (Cushman and Klecun
2006, p. 348). In the rest of this chapter we shall use the plural ‘digital divides’ to denote instances where a difference in
access or usability of ICT between groups or individuals leads to injustice or consequences that are widely perceived to be
problematic.
Digital divides have an intuitive moral quality, which often seems to preclude explicit moral reasoning about them (Hacker
and Mason,
2003). Part of the reason for this is that they seem to link with divides in the distribution of other goods or morally relevant
items, such as chances to develop oneself. The fact that there is huge inequality in the world is undisputed and the disparity
on a worldwide scale is staggering (UNDP
1998). Digital divides seem to be linked to such inequalities and they are sometimes perceived to be mutually reinforcing (Moss
2002). The perception that the gulf between haves and have-nots could be lessened but is often in fact deepened by ICT is a basic
starting assumption of discussions of ethics and digital divides (Walsham
2001). It is not immediately clear, however, whether and why digital divides are really linked to offline inequalities and why
this is an ethical problem. This is why philosophical investigations are called for (Rookby and Weckert
2007).
Digital divides have several links to
inequality, apart from the association with inequality of distribution of goods and life chances. First, there is the issue
of access. When it became apparent that new ICTs had the potential to overcome traditional inequalities but can equally well
have the opposite effect, governments across the world decided that a necessary condition of more equality was widely spread
access to such technology (Couldry
2003). As a consequence, governments and other organizations have spent considerable efforts in most parts of the world to improve
the accessibility of new ICTs, in particular the Internet.
Digital divides raise a number of interrelated questions. These include conceptual, epistemological, methodological, but also
practical ones.
There are several conceptual issues that render much of the debate on digital divides problematic. One has to do with the
concept of information. The already-mentioned ‘haves’ and ‘have-nots’ are often also called
‘information rich’ and ‘information poor’. This terminology suggests that more information is always better than less information,
which is patently false. There are many types of information not all of which are equally worth having access to. Being rich
in some kind of information can include or even presuppose being poor in others (Hongladarom
2004). There is also a case to be made that in modern Western societies information overflow is more often a problem than lack
of information. While, for some time, it may have been a status symbol to have technical access to information (e.g. via a
mobile telephone), it is increasingly a status symbol to be able to disconnect. In addition, it is perfectly conceivable that
individuals could consciously decide to remove
themselves from information flow (e.g. by deciding no longer to watch TV or by having no email access at home), which would
not necessarily impoverish their lives. Such views turn the traditional view of digital divides upside down
.
A different question concerns epistemological issues of our knowledge of digital divides and research concerning them. Hacker
and Mason (
2003) argue that ethical concerns would have to be included more explicitly in digital divides research in order to come to a
better understanding of relevant issues. At the same time, there is a dominance of positivist and quantitative research that
focuses on demographic aspects, which can narrow the understanding of the problems and make them appear more static than they
are (McSorley
2003). Couldry (
2003) therefore suggests moving away from the concept of digital divides in empirical research and concentrate on issues, which
have a stronger influence on the discursive design of ICTs.
These epistemological concerns are directly linked to the ontological framing of the concept of digital divides and their
possible solutions. As already indicated, much work in the area of digital divides concentrates on issues of
technology. A lack of access to technology is perceived as the (or at least one of the) root cause(s) of digital divides.
This renders them a technical problem that calls for a technical solution. The simplest way of doing this is to provide people
with access to technology. Indeed, this is an approach taken by many governments, whose main focus is the provision of infrastructure
or in many cases even the provision of computers in households with the aim of allowing people to connect (cf. Stahl
2008a). Providing access to technology is nothing bad per se but it betrays an underlying technological determinism that renders
the probability of success of such measures doubtful (Warschauer
2003). While lip service is often paid to the fact that access requires more than the opportunity to use a piece of technology,
the fundamental difficulties this raises are often ignored in favour of a relatively straightforward provision of technology.
High-profile projects like the MIT-sponsored ‘one laptop per child’ initiative that aims to provide a laptop for US$100 to
every one of the world's poorest children are in constant danger of overemphasizing technology. Useful access which can overcome
digital divides requires individuals to have education, high levels of literacy, and the ability to evaluate information gained
through technology. These are conditions which are less often met by those without technical access. In order to overcome
digital divides, these conditions would have to be fulfilled. In many cases, for example in countries with underdeveloped
educational infrastructures, this would be an enormous task.
Another problem of digital divides linked to their ontological framing and the epistemological issues concerning research
on such divides concerns their relevance in different social realities. The attention paid to digital divides can lead to
a
definition of normality that includes access to information via digital technologies, which then renders lifestyles that do
not conform to this
normality problematic. In this way, digital divides can become self-fulfilling prophecies, which come true because of the
attention paid to them. The definition of normality can also be an expression of cultural imperialism. Whether and in what
way technology can and should be used to address problems in different countries and cultures cannot easily be established
a priori. The risk is that discussions of digital divides can become ways of extending unequal power structures of promoting
particular technologies and processes in environments where they may not be appropriate (Walsham
2001)
.
A further problem worth mentioning concerns the question of how digital divides are to be addressed. Solutions, in order to
be measurably successful, would need to be based on clearly defined problems, which are not given. However, even if one follows
the dominant argument that the provision of access to technical means is at least an important part of the solution, then
it is unclear how this is to be achieved. On an international level, ICT is seen as an important means of development but,
at the same time, the recommendations to acquire ICT, develop market structures and engage in market competition may be unrealistic
due to the contingencies of path-dependent development processes (Avgerou
2003). This means that particular problems or solutions may have arisen due to specific circumstances and are therefore not necessarily
transferable to similar situations. Furthermore, it is unclear how technical provisions are to be implemented. The discussion
concerning appropriate mechanisms of providing access is based on metaphysical convictions of what markets are and how they
work (Stahl
2007). They are thus part of greater political and economic discourses, which render it unlikely that solutions to the problem
of digital divides will be found soon
.