2 Formalism and realism in fifteenth-century English law: Bodies corporate and bodies natural
David J. Seipp
Thomas Reed Powell, a US law professor, said seventy years ago or more, ‘if you think you can think about a thing, inextricably
attached to something else, without thinking of the thing it is attached to, then you have a legal mind’.
1 Though many lawyers claim they have this legal mind as a matter of pride, Professor Powell, I am sure, did not mean this
as a compliment. The Legal Realism movement that swept through US law schools in the 1920s and 1930s taught, among other things,
that lawyers must see the real attachments between things, attachments that Legal Formalism had been so good at ignoring.
I was reminded of things inextricably attached to each other and of the legal mind that could so completely separate them
as I worked my way through the Year Book reports of the end of the reign of Edward IV. In about a dozen reports from 1478
to 1482, many of them extending over several folios, English lawyers and judges made arguments that reminded me of formalist
and realist positions. Let me say at once that I am not trying to claim that American Legal Realism was invented in 1478 in
Westminster Hall. All Year Book discourse took place within a decidedly formalist framework. But in cases about what late
fifteenth-century English lawyers and judges called corporations and bodies politic, some of these lawyers and judges argued
that these collective entities were entirely separate from the real human beings who composed them, arguments that I will
label formalist here, and others broke down that separation and argued that the legal positions of the
individuals inside these collective entities could affect the collective entities themselves, arguments that I will label
realist.
2
Frederic William Maitland took up many of these same cases in his classic
History of English Law in 1898 and found one of them at least to be among ‘the most interesting cases in all the Year Books’.
3 Maitland had asked whether the theoretical basis of medieval English corporations was a canonist legal fiction idea or a
more Germanic organic unity of groups. Here is a passage from his discussion of these late-fifteenth-century cases:
The corporation is invisible, incorporeal, immortal; it can not be assaulted, or beaten or imprisoned; it can not commit treason;
a doubt has occurred as to whether it can commit a trespass, but this doubt (though it will give trouble so late as the year
1842) has been rejected by practice, if not removed by any consistent theory. We even find it said that the corporation is
but a name. On the other hand, it is a person. It is at once a person and yet but a name; in short it is
persona ficta.
4
After Maitland set the topic in 1893,
Cecil Carr, Frederick Pollock, Harold Laski, William Holdsworth, H. Ke Chin Wang and Heinz Lubasz rang the changes on Maitland’s
thesis down through 1964.
5 I will review some of
these same arguments from the corporation cases, but with a different question in mind.
What I expected to find when I worked on each of these cases in isolation, as they came up in Year Book order, was that arguments that a corporate entity was entirely separate from the real individuals who comprised
it and opposing arguments that the court should see through the corporate entity to consider the people inside of it would
be made by two opposing groups of lawyers and judges. I wanted to find formalist serjeants and justices regularly making the
first type of argument in opposition to realist serjeants and justices regularly making the second type of argument. If lawyers
as advocates couldn’t differentiate themselves in this way, because they had to take their clients and their clients’ best
arguments as they found them, I expected that then at least judges would be consistent along this formalist–realist divide.
What I found instead was that these lawyers and judges switched sides regularly, making arguments that seemed to me not only
inconsistent, but having entirely different theoretical orientations.
First, a few words about terminology. The term ‘body politic’ (
corps politique) was introduced in the Year Books in Michaelmas 1478, when
Serjeant Starkey said that there was a distinction between bodies politic and natural bodies.
6 Ten more reports used the term in the next four years, and a steady stream thereafter. Body politic did not mean the whole
realm of England, but meant a mayor and commonalty of a city or town, a dean and chapter of a cathedral, a master and scholars
of a college, or an abbot and convent of an abbey. Two abridgers of Year Book reports interpolated the term body politic into
entries for cases from 1429 and 1388 but these are later additions to the original text.
7 I did not find a Parliament roll referring to a body politic until 1484, though then it was to
‘the body politic of
England’,
8 and a statute first used the term in 1523.
9 The Oxford English Dictionary has no earlier references to a body politic
.
The term corporation is older than body politic in the Year Books, appearing from 1429, the word corporate from 1408, incorporate
from 1439, and the rather redundant ‘body corporate’ (
corps corporate) in a 1481 report
10 as well as in a statute of 1461, which has also the first occurrence of the word corporation in any statute.
11 When distinguished from these collective bodies, we ordinary human beings were called bodies natural, private persons, singular
persons, sole persons, natural persons, single persons, common persons, natural men and material men.
12
Now, to start with, two earlier cases led into the sort
of disputes that raised these arguments around 1480. In 1372, a plaintiff prosecuted a nuisance action against the Dean and
Chapter of St Peter of Exeter and against a clerk named John Weliot. Counsel for the defendants pleaded that the named clerk
was also a member of the chapter, and was thus sued twice. We have two reports of the case, but both just say that this plea
‘was not allowed’.
13
The same issue came up again in 1429, and the reports show a much more interesting argument. (Maitland liked this case too.)
The mayor, bailiffs and commonalty of Ipswich were sued for trespass, along with one J. Jabe as an individual defendant.
Serjeant Rolf for the defendants pleaded that the individual defendant was one of the commonalty, and so was sued twice as
a defendant.
Martin J agreed with Rolf that if this writ were allowed the individual defendant could be charged twice for the same wrong
or there could be inconsistent verdicts, and so the writ should be thrown out.
Babington CJ and Paston J disagreed with Martin. Martin had argued that if judgments were given against both
the collective entity and the individual defendant then that individual’s goods could be put in execution twice. Babington
and Paston insisted that when judgment is given against a collective entity, damages are only collected from goods that were
collectively owned. Martin pointed out that when the king fined or amerced a collective entity, the king levied the fine on
goods of the individual members, not just collectively owned goods. The reports differ on whether Babington conceded this
point about fines to the king, as he should have, because Martin
was right, but if there was one sure rule of the early common law it was, as Babington remarked in one of these reports,
that there was a big difference between the king and everybody else.
Maitland saw here the first stirrings of limited liability, the separation of corporate assets from individual assets for
some purposes. Strangeways J joined with Babington and Paston
on the formalist side saying that ‘no individual person is the commonalty’, calling it an aggregate and at the same time
a body. Like so many Year Book cases, this one has no judgment reported, but the weight of judicial authority seems to line
up with the 1372 case on the formalist
side.
14
In 1478, an abbot and convent of an abbey brought a writ of
trespass for trees cut down in the time of the abbot’s predecessor. The defendant pleaded the legal maxim that personal actions
die with the person, so it was too late to sue about what happened in the time of the previous abbot. Before the case went
off on the application of the
Statute of Marlborough (1267) as to standing trees, Serjeant Humfrey
Starkey explained that the abbot and convent as a corporation, a body politic, unlike a natural body, could not die, could
not be dead, and so its personal actions would always survive.
15 This point that corporations could not die had been made in 1465, and would be made again in four different cases in 1481
and 1482
.
16
The two principal cases that best contrast formalist and realist arguments, one with five reports from 1478 to 1482 and the
other with four reports all from 1481, were about a jury challenge and a duress defence.
Both were ‘serjeants’ cases’ in which every one of the serjeants spoke. The
jury challenge case can be called the ‘
Dean and Chapter of Lincoln v.
Prat’. A party, presumably Prat, challenged one of the prospective jurors on the grounds that the juror was a brother of one of
the canons or prebendaries of Lincoln Cathedral, thus a brother of one member of the chapter.
17
In the Lincoln case, the formalist position, argued by four serjeants, one apprentice, and one justice, said that the canon’s
brother should not be struck off the jury. Some of the arguments were that the dean and chapter together as a collective entity
could not have a brother or any other relative; that the canon himself was a stranger to the action and not a party or privy
to it; that the canon’s death or excommunication or a release from the canon would not affect the lawsuit; that if the collective
body lost a judgment the canon’s own goods would not be executed upon, as was said in 1429; and finally that the canon had
no advantage or individual benefit or interest if the collective body won. The collective entity of dean and chapter was completely
separate, completely estranged from the canons who made up the chapter.
The realist position in this Lincoln case, argued by four serjeants, four justices, and one serjeant who became a justice
while argument continued, was that the challenge was good and the canon’s brother should be struck from the jury for presumed
bias. Some of the arguments were that the canon was a party or privy to the action and not a stranger; that he had advantage
by the collective body’s recovery to their common use; and that the canon’s brother would be permitted to appear in court
and give evidence (if he had any), as a family member not barred by the law of maintenance, so that as to the dean and chapter
he was family. Most often, those arguing the realist position said simply that the brother of one of the canons could be presumed
to be biased when the dean and chapter were a party.
Though the justices said during argument that this question was evenly poised,
aequedubium, all but one of the justices whose speeches were recorded argued the realist position, and it prevailed, striking the canon’s
brother from the jury. Older Year Book cases struck from juries brothers or other relatives of monks or nuns when the abbot
and convent were on trial,
18 but the formalist position tried to distinguish these cases because
monks, unlike cathedral canons, were dead in law, had no separate possessions, and depended for their entire sustenance on
the abbot’s gain or loss. In the same way, a wife’s brother could not be a juror when the husband was on trial, because husband
and wife were one person in law.
What I find so exasperatingly unrealistic about the losing arguments, the formalist arguments in this Lincoln case, is the
premise that just because the lawyers could completely separate the collective entity from its members, that the members themselves
and their relatives should be presumed to make the same separation and to feel also no interest, no benefit, no advantage
from the collective entity’s victory. If my brother’s corporation were on trial, I would want it to win.
The second case, the duress defence, arose in
Norwich. The abbot of St Benet of Hulme sued the mayor, sheriffs, and commonalty of Norwich on a sealed obligation, a bond
stating that Norwich owed the abbey £100. The Norwich defendants pleaded that when the obligation was made the mayor of Norwich
had been in prison, so the bond was void for duress.
19 Local historians recount that a Norwich mayor actually was imprisoned in the Fleet prison by a group including the abbot
of Hulme and the earl of Suffolk in 1442, thirty-nine years before this case was argued, and that a bond for that amount was
sealed by the city’s common seal during the mayor’s imprisonment.
20 If you
doubt that abbots went around imprisoning others in order to enter into bond obligations, six earlier Year Book reports show
pleadings that abbots had imprisoned priors, imprisoned monks, threatened imprisonment, or had been imprisoned themselves.
21
The formalist position, argued by five serjeants and one justice, took the abbot’s side and contended that imprisoning the
mayor was not duress, so the city had to pay the abbot on the bond. Some of the arguments were that it was impossible to imprison
a collective entity, just as it could not be beaten or wounded; that a collective entity likewise could not commit treason
or felony or any corporal wrong for which it could be imprisoned; that the mayor was a stranger to the collective body; that
the mayor was not imprisoned ‘as mayor’; that if the mayor had been insane, an infant, excommunicated, outlawed, or a villein,
or had given a release, none of these would have voided the collective entity’s bond; and that the collective body had no
cause of action for its mayor’s imprisonment. As with the jury challenge case, there were earlier Year Book cases on the duress
defense establishing that imprisonment of an abbot would invalidate the abbot and convent’s deed. The formalist position again
distinguished these old cases in the same way, arguing that the monks of the abbot’s convent were dead in law, while all of
the commonalty were fully capable at law.
The realist position, argued by five serjeants and two justices, took the Norwich side and argued that the city’s bond was
void for duress. Some of the arguments were that without the mayor’s free and willing personal agreement the collective entity’s
bond was void; that thus not all of the collective body had made the bond and it was not their bond; that the mayor was imprisoned
as mayor; that the mayor was not a stranger to the collective body, but was its principal member and head; that if the head
be imprisoned the rest of the body can do nothing; and that the collective entity could sue a writ of false imprisonment when
their mayor was imprisoned. No judgment is reported in this case. Two justices of Common Pleas, including the chief justice,
favoured the realist side and the defendant city. One justice and a serjeant who was appointed justice in the same term the
case was reported favoured the formalist side.
Again I find the formalist arguments odd and unpersuasive. The extreme formalist position seemed to be that every single member
of
the collective body could be imprisoned, and yet the collective body itself was somehow distinct from and a stranger to all
of them, could not be imprisoned and thus could never have a duress defence. The same chief justice who took the realist side
in this case made that very formalist argument in 1475.
22 This again supposes that real human beings experience their role in a collective entity as entirely disconnected from their
individual personal situations. I doubt the mayor of Norwich in Fleet prison would have had much consolation if he had known
that half the serjeants and justices of England thought that he was not imprisoned ‘as mayor’. If my dean were imprisoned
to force us as a dean and faculty to enter into a promissory note, I think we should have a duress defence
.
In both cases, those arguing the realist position tended to concede many of the narrow points made by the formalists but then
disputed that those points did not lead to the formalist result. Those arguing the formalist position, perhaps ironically,
made the most pragmatic arguments. Thus, no jury could ever be sworn when the mayor and commonalty of London were on trial,
if relatives of every Londoner were excluded, to which
Huse CJ on the opposing realist side said that such a particular point would not change the law.
23 And if imprisonment of any one member of the commonalty would void an obligation for duress, then the mayor and commonalty
of no city could ever make a valid bond when any of the commonalty was in prison.
Bryan CJ, to refute this argument, announced that to enter into a bond or to take any other action a commonalty required only
majority agreement, not unanimous consent.
24 His is a rare judicial endorsement of majority rule in the Year Books.
25
The form of most Year Book argument from the
thirteenth century onward was argument by analogy. Serjeants and justices would put hypothetical cases that were meant to
seem obvious to both sides or would assert what had often been adjudged, and then the similarity of the hypothetical
case to the actual litigated case was supposed to persuade the rest of the court and bar. These analogies tended to be far
broader, far more distant than we would use today. Many of the formalist and realist arguments in these cases followed this
form, reasoning from dean and chapter to mayor and commonalty to husband and wife to one’s hand and one’s head. But what seem
new to me in these corporation cases from the early 1480s are the arguments that pursue and extend this concept, the collective
entity, its separate existence, and thereby its estrangement from the real people who made it up. So I suppose what I am calling
formalism here could more precisely be called conceptualism
.
When Serjeant Humfrey
Starkey first said, in 1478, that there was a distinction between a natural body and a body politic, which is ordained by
the policy of a man (or of one man), this suggests that the body politic and the arguments associated with it were consciously
invented.
26 Many of the arguments pursue and elaborate the metaphor of a disembodied incorporeal yet corporate body composed of many
natural bodies. The most obvious and proximate source of this talk in Westminster Hall about bodies politic, their heads and
their members was the ‘conciliarist’ writing earlier in the fifteenth century by theologians and canonist lawyers, mostly
in Paris, about the ‘mystical body’ (
corpus mysticum) of the church, based on 1
Corinthians
chapter 12, and the church’s
corpus politicum.
27 These church reformers had an immediate, practical need to differentiate the church as an ideal entity from the individual
popes and prelates who led it at the time. Their writings clearly influenced English constitutional writers of later centuries.
Fairfax J, in a case in 1481 about charging a successor abbot for his predecessor’s act, actually called an abbacy a ‘mystical
body’ that never died.
28 There are hints as well of other religious models for these arguments.
Bryan CJ and two serjeants all said in various ways that in the body politic of Norwich there were ‘three separate persons’
– mayor, sheriffs and commonalty – ‘this body is in three parts’, three ‘distinct
members’. This recalls the theologians’ mystery of the Trinity preached every Trinity Sunday. Serjeant
Pygot, whose formalist arguments were the most detailed, said that ‘the corporation . . . is only a name that cannot be seen
and does not have substance’.
29 Choke J said that a body politic is made up of natural men and yet when it is made it is a dead person in law, which could
not be arrested, a body dead in law
.
30
Ernst Kantorowicz in his masterful
The King’s Two Bodies of 1957 joined other scholars in attempting to show that these Year Book lawyers in 1478 and afterwards were transplanting
Pope
Alexander III’s late twelfth-century decretal
Quoniam abbas,
31 and its accompanying glosses and elaborations from
Innocent IV in the mid thirteenth century, translating the canonist
dignitas now for some reason as body politic and corporation in the late fifteenth century.
32 Some of the arguments these lawyers made, that the body politic never died and that a legal act taken in one’s personal name
had completely different consequences from the same act taken in the name of one’s role in a collective entity, do support
that link. In many other contexts, Year Book lawyers stated much more clearly that they were drawing on the law of holy church
or were talking to doctors of the canon-law side.
33 I’m not convinced
.
Kantorowicz and others have also suggested an origin for these arguments in the high politics of the realm, linked to the
decision supposed to have been made by
Edward IV’s legal counsellors changing the Duchy of Lancaster from a personal possession of the Lancastrian kings to a corporation
held by the House of York.
34 Successors of these Year Book lawyers were to build upon these body politic arguments eighty years later in 1561 in Plowden’s
report of the case of the Duchy of Lancaster, a great matter of state, in which it was resolved that the nine-year-old
Edward VI had in him two bodies, to wit a body natural and a body politic.
35 It is hard to imagine that these 1481 arguments about the canon’s brother’s jury duty or the mayor’s imprisonment were dictated
by crown policy or eight decades’ foresight. King’s serjeants
were about as likely to make realist arguments as formalist ones, as was
Humfrey Starkey, former Recorder of London.
I suspect that in a broader sense the appeal of these formalist arguments was simply the lawyers’ love of the counterintuitive result. For legal reasoning to be different from
and better than ordinary common sense, there seems to be a need for legal reasoning to reach unlikely, surprising, tricky,
paradoxical outcomes. So we have lawyers’ loopholes, technicalities and traps for the unwary. Guilty defendants go free. Bequests
to grandchildren at their christening are void as perpetuities. And we have collective entities that have nothing to do with
the people collected within them. We have brothers who are not brothers, mayors who are not mayors and imprisonment that is
not imprisonment.
As I said already, I did not find a consistent group of formalists to deplore nor a consistent group of realists to admire
among the bench and bar of 1481. In Michaelmas 1481, there were nine serjeants at law, four justices of Common Pleas, and
three justices of King’s Bench. Between the two cases that I have studied most closely, the Lincoln jury challenge and the
Norwich duress defence, two serjeants (
Catesby and Pygot) stayed formalist, two (
Tremayle and Townshend) switched from formalist to realist, two (
Starkey and Bridges) switched from realist to formalist, and one (Vavasour) stayed realist. Both serjeants who remained formalist
in these two cases (across nine different reports), Catesby and Pygot, took the realist position against Starkey in 1478,
refusing to find a body politic separate from the dead abbot.
36 The one consistent realist in the Lincoln and Norwich cases, Vavasour, took formalist positions in cases involving interpretation
of a jury exemption in 1481 and disseisin of rent from a dean and chapter in 1483.
37 I found no consistently formalist nor consistently realist serjeants.
These serjeants were advocates, of course, who pleaded for the clients they had, so their inconsistency is perhaps to be expected.
But my two principal cases were so-called serjeants’ cases, in which every serjeant at the bar took part, and it seems unlikely
that the two parties would have paid counsel fees to all of the serjeants who spoke, when in one case the dispute was merely
a challenge of one juror in an assize. There has sometimes been an assumption that in civil cases every lawyer who spoke in
support of one side’s position or another’s was paid a fee by
the litigant, and an opposite assumption in criminal cases. The truth probably lies somewhere in between. I still find it
puzzling that the serjeants who might be expected to argue their own opinions as if they were judges showed so little consistency
in this regard.
We can and should expect more consistency from the judges. Justices of Common Pleas spoke in both cases. Two of them,
Nele and
Bryan CJ, stayed on the realist side, and one, Choke, switched from realist to formalist. Bryan, a consistent realist in the
Lincoln and Norwich cases, made some very formalist arguments in cases before and since. Bryan argued in 1475 that it was
impossible to imprison an abbot and convent even if the abbot and all the monks were imprisoned, and in 1488 he argued that
a collective entity could not hire or command a servant without writing, though he did not use quite as formalist an argument
as
Serjeant Wode employed in 1492 on the same issue, that a corporate body had no mouth, so it was reduced to writing, although
somehow then it did have hands.
38 The other consistent realist,
Nele J, was not reported in any other case raising these issues.
All these serjeants and justices, so renowned for finding distinctions between seemingly identical situations, did not make
a distinction between the Lincoln jury-challenge dispute and the Norwich duress defence. They did not distinguish between
the corporate identity of the dean and chapter as a religious group and that of the mayor and commonalty as civic group. The
jury challenge and duress defence situations are analytically similar as instances of sworn obligations overcome by presumed
human frailties: a juror’s oath to give a true and impartial verdict overcome by family loyalty (presumed bias), and a contractual
obligation to pay money overcome by imprisonment (presumed lack of consent). Consistency of approach across these two and
other similar cases is not too much to expect.
So I find distinct, persistent patterns of two types of opposing arguments, but not two distinct, consistent groups of lawyers
or judges who make these opposing arguments. I find formalism and realism, but no formalists, no realists. Year Book reports
carefully name the speakers in almost every case, but the content of the named lawyers’ and judges’ speeches does not differentiate
them well at all. Any judge’s speech could have been made by any other judge, and any serjeant’s speech by any other serjeant.
I have not found any speaker in the late fifteenth century Year Books as distinctive as
Thomas Rolf, who in the 1420s and 1430s barked animal noises, sang snatches of
ballads, reported a seven-year pregnancy, introduced Latin grammar and logic terminology, and made arguments from etymology.
39
Thomas Littleton, the author of the famous treatise on tenures, stands out in the years before his death in August 1481 because
his pronouncements often seem didactic. Littleton conveniently died just months before these arguments took place about bodies
politic and their separation from the people inside them, but when he did speak in prior cases raising similar issues he tended
to split the difference between formalist and realist positions in oddly modern-sounding ways.
40
In this examination of formalist and realist arguments I intended to find heroes and villains, but in failing to find them,
I find another lesson about fifteenth-century English judges and lawyers. They did not seem to invest their personalities
in the performance of their professional duties. They seemed to appreciate that the full range of the legal profession’s stockpile
of arguments needed to be preserved, and a serjeant or judge would take up an argument in one case, inconsistent with what
he had just said in another case, simply because no one else was making that argument, or no one else was making that argument
well enough. I suspect that these judges and lawyers were not interested in driving one or another type of argument out of
existence, but were consciously preserving modes of argument because the next generation’s clients might need them. These
fifteenth-century judges did not view the opposing arguments the way I read them (and Maitland read them), as so fundamentally opposed to one another that no single person could seriously make both sorts of arguments
in different cases. Each side did not think the other side’s arguments were silly or not worth making, though Maitland would
say that Edward Coke and Robert Brooke made an awful nonsense of those arguments in later centuries.
Looking for distinctive, consistent individual judicial philosophies, what I find instead is a consistent collective judicial
commitment to preservation of conflicting philosophies and conflicting approaches. What I find is a corporate, collective
personality separable from the individuals who comprised the judiciary and bar of fifteenth-century England.
1 Thomas Reed Powell, quoted in T. W. Arnold, The Symbols of Government (New Haven, CT, 1935), p. 101.
2 For a similar application of this twentieth-century terminology to medieval legal materials, see
M. T. Clanchy, ‘A medieval realist: Interpreting the rules at Barnewell Priory, Cambridge’ in E. A. G. Attwool (ed.), Perspectives in Jurisprudence (Glasgow, 1977), pp. 176–94. The notion of ‘realism’ as a pragmatic approach to law sceptical of formal legal distinctions has a contested modern history
familiar to American lawyers, reviewed in
William Twining, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement (London, 1985), pp. 70–83.
3 F. Pollock and F. W. Maitland, A History of English Law, 2nd edn, 2 vols. (Cambridge, 1898), I, p. 491. Maitland took
Otto von Gierke’s Das Deutsche Genossenschaftsrecht (Berlin, 1873) with him on his first winter spent in the Canary Islands. He was strangely attracted to Gierke’s idea of the organic reality
of groups in German law.
H. A. L. Fisher, Frederick William Maitland: A biographical sketch (Cambridge, 1910), pp. 157–9. The German influence on English and American corporation law is well examined in
R. Harris, ‘The transplantation of the legal discourse on corporate personality theories’ (2006) 63 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1421–78.
4 Pollock and Maitland,
History of English Law, pp. 490–1. Maitland based this passage on a lecture he delivered to Liverpool law students on 25 May 1893.
F. W. Maitland, The Corporation Aggregate: The history of a legal idea (Liverpool, 1893), p. 6.
5 C. T. Carr, The General Principles of the Law of Corporations (Cambridge, 1905), pp. 150–3 (‘Anthropomorphism’);
F. Pollock, ‘Has the common law received the fiction theory of corporations?’ (1911) 27 L.Q.R. 219–35;
H. J. Laski, ‘The early history of the corporation in England’ (1917) 30 Harv. L. Rev. 561–88; W. S. Holdsworth, ‘English corporation law in the 16th and 17th centuries’ (1922) 31 Yale L. J. 382–407;
W. S. Holdsworth, A History of English Law, 3rd edn, 9 vols. (London, 1923–1931), III, pp. 482–7;
J. Dewey, ‘The historical background of corporate legal personality’ (1926) 35 Yale L. J. 655–73;
H. K. C. Wang, ‘The corporate entity concept (or fiction theory) in the Year Book period’ (1942) 58 L.Q.R. 498–511, and
(1943) 59 L.Q.R. 72–86;
H. Lubasz, ‘The corporate borough in the common law of the late Year-Book period’ (1964) 80 L.Q.R. 228–43. And see now
J. H. Baker, The Oxford History of the Laws of England (Oxford, 2003), VI, pp. 622–7, and
S. Reynolds, ‘The history of the idea of incorporation or legal personality: A case of fallacious teleology’ in S. Reynolds, Ideas and Solidarities of the Medieval Laity (Aldershot, 1995), sec. VI, pp. 12–14.
6 Mich. 18 Edw. 4, pl. 17, ff. 15b–16a (1478.088). Parenthetical references in Year Book citations are to the author’s index
and paraphrase of printed Year Book reports,
www.bu.edu/law/seipp.
7 R. Brooke, La Graunde Abridgement (London, 1573), tit. Corporations, pl. 24, f. 188v (London, 1573), excerpting Mich. 8 Hen. 6, pl. 2, ff. 1a–1b (1429.086) and adding words,
‘to wit, a body politic and a natural body’;
D. Jenkins, Eight Centuries (London, 1661), p. 64 (2nd century, case 21), 145 E.R. 46, a version of Trin. 12 Ric. 2, pl. 10, Ames 19–20 (1388.058am).
8 A roll of Parliament referred to ‘the body politic of England’ in 1484, 6 Rot. Parl. 237a (23 Jan. 1484). A Year Book report
of 1522 had the statement that the King, Lords, and Commons in Parliament were a corporation. Mich. 14 Hen. 8, pl. 2, 119
SS 98, 101 (Fyneux CJ (KB)) (1522.011ss).
9 14 & 15 Hen. 8,
ch. 6, sec. 5 (1523).
10 Mich. 8 Hen. 6, pl. 2, ff. 1a–1b (1429.086) (corporation); Mich. 10 Hen. 4, pl. 5, f. 3b (1408.005) (corporate); Mich. 18
Hen. 6, pl. 6, ff. 21a–22a (1439.006) (incorporate); Pasch. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 21, ff. 7a–7b (1481.029) (body corporate).
12 Most of these terms can be found in the
Lincoln and
Norwich cases cited below; natural body in Mich. 18 Edw. 4, pl. 17, ff. 15b–16a (1478.088); material man in Hil. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 9,
ff. 16a–16b (1482.009) (Sjt Sulyard); and common person in Hil. 10 Hen. 7, pl. 15, ff. 16a–6b (1495.015) (Sjt Wode).
13 Mich. 46 Edw. 3, pl. 7, ff. 23b–24a (1372.075); 46 Edw. 3, Lib. Ass. 9, ff. 306b–307a (1372.123ass).
14 Mich. 8 Hen. 6, pl. 2, ff. 1a–1b (1429.086); Mich. 8 Hen. 6, pl. 34, ff. 14b–15a (1429.118); Mich. 9 Hen. 6, pl. 9, f. 36b
(1430.056).
15 Mich. 18 Edw. 4, pl. 17, ff. 15b–16a (1478.088).
16 Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 3, f. [38]b (1481.071) (per Fairfax J (KB)); Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 4, ff. 12b–15a (1481.068) (per Sjt
Townshend); Hil. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 3, ff. 15a–15b (1482.003) (per Catesby J (CP)); Hil. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 9, ff. 75b–77b (1482.038)
(per Sjt Pygot, ‘a crabbish case’). The practical difficulty that these religious entities did not die had been realised at
least as early as the mortmain legislation in 1279.
17 Dean and Chapter of Lincoln v.
Prat (1478–1482) was reported in Hil. 17 Edw. 4, pl. 1, f. 7a (1478.001); Pasch. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 28, ff. 31a–33b (1481.059); Mich.
21 Edw. 4, pl. 3, ff. 11b–12b (1481.067); Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 33, ff. 63a–63b (1481.101); and Hil. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 29, ff.
20b–21a (1482.029).
18 e.g. Trin. 28 Hen. 6, pl. 17, f. 10a (1450.007); 34 Edw. 3, Lib. Ass. pl. 6, ff. 203b–204b (1360.006ass).
19 Abbot of St. Benet (Benedict) of Hulme v.
Mayor and Commonalty of Norwich (1481) Pasch. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 21, ff. 7a–7b (1481.029); Pasch. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 22, ff. 27a–28b (1481.053); Mich. 21 Edw. 4,
pl. 4, ff. 12b–15a (1481.068); and Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 53, ff. 67b–70b (1481.121).
20 After a disputed mayoral election in 1433, former mayor Thomas Wetherby feuded with a succession of mayors, aldermen, and
commons. Wetherby enlisted the earl of Suffolk and the abbot of Hulme on his side. Norwich enlisted the duke of Gloucester
on their side. In 1441, Wetherby instigated the abbot to prosecute Norwich for erecting new mills on the river Wensum. A commission
under the earl of Suffolk awarded that Norwich destroy their mills and enter into a bond for £100 with the abbot to be forfeited
if they ever erected the mills again. When the parties were ordered to appear before the king’s council, the mayor was committed
to Fleet Prison from 13 Feb. to 26 Mar. 1443. On 10 Mar. 1443, while the mayor was in the Fleet, Wetherby took the Norwich
common seal and, according to the earl’s award, sealed the bond for £100 to the abbot of Hulme.
W. Hudson and J. C. Tingey, The Records of the City of Norwich, 2 vols. (Norwich, 1906), I, pp. lxxxiiii–xciii, 348–55 (I thank Ben McRee for this reference);
F. Blomefield, An Essay Towards a Topographical History of the County of Norfolk, 5 vols. (London, 1806), III, pp. 144–9. Blomefield recorded that a successor abbot’s lawsuit in 1481 to recover on the bond was unsuccessful, as was a commission
subsequently brought to destroy the new mills.
Ibid., p. 149,
n. 7. See also
J. R. Green, Town Life in the Fifteenth Century, 2 vols. (London, 1907), I, pp. 387 at
n. 1, 391–3;
H. A. Doubleday, The Victoria History of the County of Norfolk, ed. W. Page, 6 vols. (London, 1906), II, p. 334.
21 Trin. 28 Hen. 6, pl. 7, f. 8b (1450.017); Mich. 35 Hen. 6, pl. 26, ff. 17b–18a (1456.080); Pasch. 38 Hen. 6, pl. 7, f. 27a
(1460.015); Mich. 39 Hen. 6, pl. 48, ff. 35b–36a (1460.076); Hil. 39 Hen. 6, pl. 16, ff. 50b–51b (1461.016); Mich. 15 Edw.
4, pl. 2, ff. 1b–2a (1475.034).
22 Mich. 15 Edw. 4, pl. 2, ff. 1b–2a (1475.034).
23 Pasch. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 28, ff. 31a–33b (1481.059) (Fairfax J (KB) and Huse CJ (KB)).
24 If the greater part of the commonalty agrees, it is as if all agree (Bryan CJ (CP)), in Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 4, ff. 12b–15a
(1481.068). In the greater part their body resides (Choke J (CP)) and if the greater part agree, it is good; perhaps they
will never all agree, and where the majority are, there are all (Bryan CJ (CP)), in Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 53, ff. 67b–70b (1481.121).
25 Notable earlier examples are 1281–1284 Lincolnshire Eyre pl. 2, 122 SS 89–92 (1282.003) (Saham J or Spigurnel J); Mich. 9
Hen. 6, pl. 3, ff. 32b–34b (1430.050); Pasch. 19 Hen. 6, pl. 1, ff. 62a–65a (1441.028) (Hody CJ (KB)); Mich. 20 Hen. 6, pl.
25, ff. 12b–13b (1441.080) (Fray CB (Ex.)). I thank Dr Paul Brand for the earliest citation.
26 ‘il [est] diversity enter un corps natural & un corps politick, le quel est ordeine per le policy d’ un home’ (Sjt Starkey),
in Mich. 18 Edw. 4, pl. 17, ff. 15b–16a (1478.088).
27 F. Oakley, ‘Natural law, the corpus mysticum, and consent in conciliar thought from John of Paris to Matthias Ugonius’ (1981) 56 Speculum 786, 794–5, 800–6, citing particularly Pierre d’ Ailly and Jean Gerson. See also
H. de Lubac, Corpus Mysticum: The Eucharist and the Church in the Middle Ages, tr. G. Simmonds (London, 2006), pp. 101–19 (pp. 116–35 of Paris, 1949 edn).
28 ‘cest mystical corps del Abbe ne unques morust’, in Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 3, f. [38]b (1481.071).
29 All in Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 4, ff. 12b–15a (1481.068).
30 Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 53, ff. 67b–70b (1481.121).
31 X. 1.29.14 (Decretals of Gregory IX), in
E. Friedberg, Corpus Juris Canonici, 2 vols. (Graz, 1879), II, col. 162.
32 E. H. Kantorowicz, The King’s Two Bodies: A study in medieval political theology (Princeton, 1957), pp. 385–401.
33 D. J. Seipp, ‘The reception of canon law and civil law in the common law courts before 1600’ (1993) 13 O.J.L.S. 388–420.
34 Kantorowicz, The King’s Two Bodies, pp. 7–20, 403–9.
35 Dutchy of Lancaster Case (1561) 1 Plowden 212, 213; 75 E.R. 325, 326.
36 Mich. 18 Edw. 4, pl. 17, ff. 15b–16a (1478.088).
37 Mich. 21 Edw. 4, pl. 28, ff. 55b–59b (1481.096); Trin. 1 Edw. 5, pl. 10, ff. 4b–5b (1483.028).
38 Mich. 15 Edw. 4, pl. 2, ff. 1b–2a (1475.034); Mich. 4 Hen. 7, pl. 7, ff. 17b–18a (1488.042); Hil. 7 Hen. 7, pl. 2, ff. 9a–10a
(1492.002).
39 e.g. ‘bawwaw for thy reason’, in Hil. 8 Hen. 6, pl. 7, ff. 21b–23a (1430.007); Robin Hode en Barnesdale stode, in Pasch. 7
Hen. 6, pl. 45, f. 37b (1429.051); seven-year pregnancy, in Mich. 1 Hen. 6, pl. 8, ff. 3a–3b (1422.042).
40 e.g. in some respects the abbot and convent are one person in law and in other respects not (Littleton J (CP)), in Mich. 15
Edw. 4, pl. 2, ff. 1b–2a (1475.034).