1 Introduction
The Affect Program Theory of Emotions
Abstract: The chapter develops a taxonomy of emotions and other affects and introduces and defends a version of the affect program theory. A general and primitive notion of affect as a motivational state is introduced. Affects are defined as real, occurrent states, functionally identified, and not well characterized by such bivalent features as positive/negative. Some of the states typically called "emotions," such as fear and anger, are found to be special kinds of affects, characterized primarily by the actions they cause or are associated with. These basic emotions are explained by a version of the affect program theory that takes many emotions to be evolved from action programs.
Craig Delancey
There probably is no scientifically appropriate class of things referred to by our term emotion. Such disparate phenomena—fear, guilt, shame, melancholy, and so on—are grouped under this term that it is dubious that they share anything but a family resemblance. But particular emotions are another matter altogether. There is good reason to believe that different sciences can make quite compelling sense of a more fine-grained differentiation of affects. My task in this book is to reveal some of the important and neglected lessons of some of the emotions for the philosophy and sciences of mind, and this task can be accomplished with just a working characterization of a few of these. More important, there is a compelling theory of some emotions that has far-reaching implications for the philosophy and sciences of mind. This is the affect program theory. Using a version of this theory as a guide to what phenomena we will be concerned with and to the nature of these phenomena will allow us to avoid fundamental confusions and to provide richer results.
The affect program theory is the view that some emotions are pancultural syndromes enabled by inherited biological capabilities. By calling them "syndromes," we mean to point out that they are coordinated collections of complex biological responses that occur together. These emotions will be characterized by several features, including at least physiological responses, such as autonomic body responses, and stereotypical associated behaviors, such as facial expressions but also relational behaviors. I will call the emotions that are taken to fall under the affect program theory "basic emotions," just so that we have some way to refer to them.
1 This is a very general formulation of the affect program theory; however, with some small elaboration in this chapter, it will be sufficient to allow me to draw some very important lessons about the nature of mind.
This theory is meant to describe only some of the things that we might call an emotion. In part as a result of this, there is plenty of room for controversy regarding whether this is a proper theory of emotion. For example, some theorists have argued that conscious experience is a necessary element of an emotion (Clore,
1994), whereas this is not the case on the affect
end p.3
program theory. Thus, one might argue that the affect program theory does not properly describe the emotions as the normal speaker means to refer to them. The affect program theory is an empirical theory; it is not beholden to fit exactly our folk use of affect terms, or our folk theory about affects (see Griffiths,
1997). Ultimately, the defense of the affect program theory must rest on how well it (1) usefully defines and distinguishes the various affects, and (2) explains and predicts the relevant phenomena. Defending the theory's utility to explain and predict the relevant phenomena is done throughout this book, by way of applying the theory and showing how it can offer powerful new ways to think about some of the problems of mind. Defending the theory as a useful way to categorize the affects is something I will do in this chapter and the next. My approach will be to examine some of the features of affects that other scholars have singled out as necessary or sufficient or perhaps even just important to emotions and other affects. Our best scientific understanding of these features reveals that they are either consistent with the affect program theory, or are not appropriate ways to ground a theory of affect. This will also allow me to review the scientific evidence and theoretical reasons that lay the foundations for a view of mind that is quite different from most of those that characterize contemporary philosophy of mind.
Although scientists have tended to be more careful, and usually provide sufficient operational notions of the emotions and other affective states they study, until recently (e.g., Griffiths,
1997) there has been scandalously little concern among philosophers (even philosophers of emotion) for clarifying their taxonomic presuppositions. This oversight is not innocuous, since it fosters both an extremely error-prone armchair theorizing, sometimes even armchair neuropsychology, and also vagueness and confusions that can result in question-begging and pernicious ambiguities.
Most philosophy of emotion has proceeded in one of three ways. In recent years it has been most common for emotions to be investigated through the use of emotion terms. This is an approach which is sometimes taken to an extreme by those who endorse the position that the conceptual analysis of ordinary language is all that is needed to understand emotions, or by the social constructionists, who see culture—of which they take language to be the most important and revealing element—as the creator of emotions. Paul Griffiths (
1997, 21ff.) has effectively criticized the former, pointing out that ordinary language analysis approach to emotion studies has been based upon philosophical presuppositions that are now largely debunked. I will criticize a strong social constructionist approach in chapter
4. A second method for philosophizing about emotions, more revealed in the lack of an explicit method, is to take emotions as primitives open to reliable introspection; not surprisingly, this approach usually yields the view that emotions are fundamentally cognitive. But taking emotions as having properties that are somehow obvious inevitably leads to begging all the important questions; emotions are introspected to have just the qualities needed to support whatever theory is at hand. I shall review some cases that show
end p.4
how psychologists and neural scientists have discovered some very surprising things about our everyday emotions, things which would certainly fail to be noticed by introspection. Introspection also results in subjective characterizations that are hard or impossible to pin down. Without some, even if rough, prior and objective (that is, third-person, open to observation) characterization of the things we are discussing, much of this work on emotions can be useless. A third approach is to simply define emotions and work with these definitions; this also has traditionally yielded cognitive approaches. Defining emotions up front in some cognitive form would be, of course, quite acceptable if this were not usually followed by sweeping generalizations that reach beyond the scope of the class of phenomena picked out by the definition. As it stands, all too often we find that a theorist starts with a definition of emotions that is strongly cognitive, then makes claims about all emotions, surreptitiously slipping in the assumption that all of what others call "emotions" fall under the definition of emotions as cognitive. We therefore either need to be extremely careful not to erroneously generalize from our definition, or we need to characterize (at least some) emotions in some sense that is guided by empirical data and allows us to formulate the core questions about emotions. I will take the latter route, beginning with a broad characterization of affects that is not by definition cognitive, and then exploring how we can build our way to a characterization of some emotions which will let us learn some lessons from them.
A General Notion of Affect
It will be useful to start with a more general characterization of affect. This will give us a chance to place the relevant emotions in relation to things like pleasure or mood. There is little agreement upon terminology for emotions and other affects in philosophy, psychology, or any other of the cognitive sciences. In general, terms like emotion and affect are used synonymously. However, for most of us (at least in the English-speaking world), paradigm emotions include fear, anger, joy, sadness, and disgust. At the same time, some people consider moods to be emotions, including thus long-term states that have motivational features very different from those of, say, terror. And philosophers will talk about the importance of emotions to rationality, seemingly grouping desire and other more general conative states together under the term "emotion." Given that such a disparate group of things can be labeled as emotions, we need to draw some distinctions among these phenomena. Here I shall try to avoid confusions by using "affect" as a general term, and desires, emotions, moods, and other states will classify as types of affects.
I still need to characterize affect in some positive way. The working definition I propose is: Affects are body states that are motivational. (Throughout this book, I will take body states to include neural states; when I want
end p.5
to draw attention to the body independent of the central nervous system, I will use the term "extended body.") This is not in itself very enlightening, since motivation is not a little mysterious. But the principal feature of these motivations is that they are internal physical states of an organism that cause it to perform an action if the organism is not inhibited by different motivations or otherwise constrained. The relation of inhibition by other motivations, and also the notion of constraint, although both intuitively clear, are very hard to specify. Without a better account of what it is to inhibit or constrain a motivation, this characterization might be too vague if we meant to explore the nature of affect
per se. But the claim that the affects are types of body states is sufficient to distinguish this notion of affect from many of the competing notions; in particular, it commits us to a realist theory of motivations (in contrast to, for example, ascriptivist notions of desire, such as I discuss below and in chapter
3). Furthermore, this is a claim for type-identity: the body states that motivate are instances of a recognizable type. Since it will be sufficient to have a working notion of just a certain class of emotions, I will take motivation as a primitive; however, this notion, as it is involved with the basic emotions that will be my concern here, will be developed at more length in the coming chapters. In the meantime, this definition makes it clear that I link affects to actions.
Affect Is Characterized in a Functional Way
Affects include desires, pleasures, emotions, and moods. We should note that these things are quite distinct in the physiological and, in particular, neural structures that underlie their function; we should not expect to find a single brain system for all motivation. Furthermore, when they are cognitive, affects can include significant input from not only subcortical brain areas but also from cortical polymodal and supramodal areas. More simply put: a lot of the brain, including areas seemingly dedicated to more abstract thought, can (but need not) become involved in the affect. Thus, as occurs with many biological functions, we should expect some of the brain and body substrates of affects to be distributed. All of these distinctions reveal that this notion of affects is a functional characterization that may not in any simple way reduce to a physical one.
2 We may indeed find that the neural underpinnings, for example, of some particular affects can be quite clearly mapped out; but the concept of affects in general is unlikely to have such a common characterization.
Two other things should be noted about this characterization of affects. First, although I believe that they are necessarily motivational, pains are often understood in neuroscience as somatosensory phenomena that activate a motivational system. We could use "pain" in a broader sense to include the activation of the motivational systems that neuroscientists take the somatosensory aspects of pain to activate; but, given that nothing here depends on it, I will instead avoid expending effort on what could be a contentious issue. I will not require that pains be counted as affects. Second,
end p.6
moods pose special difficulties; since moods will only be a passing concern here, I will not try to characterize them at more length. As a working notion, we can think of moods as long-term affective states, perhaps even long-term emotions; as such, their motivational aspect is revealed more as a long-term and consistent alteration in motivation (relative to the subject when not in that mood).
Affects Are not All Bivalent/monodimensional States
Many have suggested that affects are states that are either negative or positive appraisals (of something, such as the organism's situation). It is extremely common in psychology to group emotions into groups with "negative" and "positive" valence. Similarly, some philosophers have defined emotions as belief states coupled with some bivalent feature or one-dimensional magnitude meant to capture the affective aspect of the emotion; Patricia Greenspan (
1988) uses comfort/discomfort as this feature, while many others (e.g., Marks,
1982) assume desire is this feature. I will not respect these uses of the term "affect" because they are ultimately unhelpful; although they may be valuable when used to describe some affects, they fail as broad characterizations of all affects. For example, the notion that an appraisal or state is "positive" is too vague. What makes an appraisal positive? Ultimately, if the notion of a positive or negative appraisal is not to be vacuous, it must either yield some measurable feature of the body, or, better yet, it must reveal something about the kind of behavior that such an appraisal results in (such as approach or avoidance). One supposes that joy, for example, is positive (as per colloquial usage of "positive") and that it leads to approach (in some sense). But what about anger and fear? Colloquial usage would make them negative; but one can lead to approach of the emotion's object (in attack), the other to retreat from it (in flight). Given such distinct behaviors, the categories just do not explain anything. Similarly for comfort and discomfort. Suppose anger and fear are uncomfortable. What does this tell us about the behaviors that would result? That we seek to avoid them? But it seems, at least prima facie, that we sometimes seek these emotions, through art (revenge films include bad guys who are there specifically to raise our ire, and frightening movies garner audiences because they are frightening) or activities (like seeking fights or riding a roller coaster). Or does it mean that once we have the emotion we seek to get out of it? But, again, if a movie-goer or a mountain climber is even partly motivated by the thrill of fear, their behavior is inconsistent with such a supposition (they stay in the theater, or they keep climbing). Pleasure/displeasure, comfort/discomfort, positive/negative, and various degrees of satisfaction of a desire are all too crude to tell us anything interesting about many of the emotions and the behaviors that typify them.
Note that I am not arguing here against the use, by neuroscientists and others, of activation and inhibition (and cognate notions) of behaviors as
end p.7
general explanatory posits (e.g., Gray
1991); I am rejecting the use of (usually far more general) one-dimensional measures for taxonomizing emotions and other affects into, say, the positive group or the negative group. Another way of making the same point is to note that such monodimensional categorizing threatens to be far too impoverished for explaining data. It can result in such a reductive simplification that effects of the phenomena involved can be lost as they are pressed onto a single measure.
3 One solution to this kind of simplification is to introduce a host of bivalent appraisals for each emotion; this is a strategy taken by Andrew Ortony, Gerald Clore, and Allan Collins (
1988) in their discussion of the cognitive origins or causes of emotions. They argue (18) that emotions are bivalent reactions concerned with three aspects of the world: events, agents, or objects. But, of course, multiplying the number of dimensions in a model can distinguish any number of states; so before we accept a complex of bivalent appraisals or monodimensional features, we need some independent reason to accept the dimensions that are being offered. Here, we shall see that dropping the very notion of bivalent appraisals and related notions loses us nothing. The term
affect will be used in a way that does not presuppose bivalent or monodimensional measures of this sort.
Affects Are Occurrent States, not Dispositions
Affect terms can all be used in a dispositional sense. If we say that Tony desires chocolate, or that Eric is angry at his landlord, we could mean at least two things in each case. We could mean that the person in question is in a particular body state, or we could mean that he tends to be in that body state, given the right conditions. The former I will call an
occurrent affect, and the latter a
disposition to affect.
4 Thus, in ordinary discourse a sentence like "Eric is an angry person" can be ambiguous; it could mean that Eric is angry right now, or that Eric is the kind of person who is often angry. Similarly, one might say that Eric has been angry at his landlord for years, but of course it is not the case that anyone can be in an occurrent state of anger for that long a period of time. Instead, we mean that when reminded of his landlord or confronted with his landlord, Eric usually becomes angry. We might also mean that the beliefs and values Eric holds that cause him to be angry at his landlord—say, the belief that his landlord is charging him too much money, and the high value he places on being treated justly, and so on—are still held by Eric, which should have as a consequence that when he attends to these things he has an occurrent state of anger as a result. Or Tony can be said to have a disposition to desire chocolate if he desires chocolate often, or if he desires chocolate whenever he sees it. But Tony has only an occurrent desire for chocolate if he is actually in a state of desiring chocolate. Disposition to emotions and other affects are of particular importance to our normal discourse because we use them in attributions of temperament
5 and other affective personality traits: a sybaritic person may be someone who has a disposition to desire to ingest chocolates and to
end p.8
pursue the experience of various other pleasures; a choleric person is someone who has a disposition to be angry. However, the concept of disposition to affects is (at least as I am using the term here) derived from the concept of occurrent affect, and does not admit of many of the features that occurrent emotions have (for example, there is no sense in arguing whether a disposition to affect is a propositional attitude—this could at best mean that the occurrent affect for which one has a disposition is itself a propositional attitude). I shall hereafter mean an occurrent affect by any affect term.
Affects Are Real Physical States, not Ascribed Explanations
There is a related notion of affect which can be held by someone who denies that there are occurrent affects, and holds that talk about affects and about disposition to affects are both just a convenient gloss for dispositions to behavior. On such a view, attributions of affects may not correspond to an actual body state but rather might just be a kind of logical construction relating actions and beliefs.
6 Say, Adam always ascend the steps to his front door in a single leap. It may be that there is no significant sense in which Adam has a kind of body state that corresponds to the desire to leap up to the door; rather, he may just do it out of habit, without any need to choose between this option and the option of taking the steps one at a time. However, one might still say that Adam "desires" to leap the three steps in a single bound and simply mean by this that Adam believes (if he were queried) that he can get to the door that way, and furthermore he does get to the door that way. We then might understand the "desire" as a kind of relation between the relevant belief or beliefs and the relevant action. One who is very skeptical about affects being actual body states in any significant sense might advocate the view that all or many such affects are just kinds of logical attributions. There are measurable occurrent states that seem to correspond to instances of desirelike states (though it is dubious that there is any generic motivational state like the philosopher's notion of desire), but I need not defend this claim here, since my goal is to develop a theory of some of the emotions—emotions for which it is uncontroversial that there are strongly related physiological and brain states. We need only note, then, that affect terms as they are used here will not be meant as mere logical relations between belief and action or between any other mental states or actions; what they stand for must necessarily include actual (in principle measurable) body states that are best identified as states resulting from or constituting the affect.
Distinguishing Features of Affects
Ultimately, we shall do best to fix a theory of basic emotions and other affects on a developed scientific understanding of the neural systems that
end p.9
enable those affects. Thus, our best criteria to identify affects will include those such as Jaak Panksepp (
1998) uses. He writes: "The most compelling evidence for the existence of such systems is our ability to evoke discrete emotional behaviors and states using localized electrical and chemical stimulation of the brain" (52). Such evidence often reveals quite definite neural structures, some of which offer very compelling neuroanatomical evidence in favor of the affect program theory. I shall refer to some of the relevant neuroscientific evidence throughout my discussions of the basic emotions and other affects. However, since my task here is in part to relate the affect program theory to commonsense notions of emotion, including the kinds of features that have traditionally come in for much conceptual analysis and therefore have been of concern to philosophers, I will begin with a number of observable or introspectable features; these features are also a good starting place because some of them are likely essentially linked to the functional role of the relevant affects.
Such possible distinguishing features of occurrent affects that have interested scientists and philosophers are their physiological state, conscious experience, associated actions, and relations to cognitive content.
7 We might also add to this list the relative temporal duration of the affect: Generally, it seems that affects that are not moods or emotions do not last as long as emotions, and that emotions last less long than moods. One might hold that two affects can be indistinguishable as to their physiology, but can be distinguished according to duration (sadness and depression, for example, might be such a case). There is a significant body of literature on stress that is concerned with duration of some affects. For my purposes here, however, this research will not be taken to be sufficient to characterize the emotions.
8 Here I will remain agnostic about all the possible meanings of differences in duration. Instead, I will turn next to the first three of these four features. Since in the next chapter I will discuss the cognitivist theories of emotion (the view that emotions are in some part constituted by, or at least require, beliefs or other propositional attitudes), I will leave a discussion about cognitive content for that chapter.
Physiological State
Affects, especially some emotions, have noticeable and measurable physiological correlates. For example, a large body of research reveals that some forms of decision making (and thus, presumably, very basic forms of affects) result in often very subtle autonomic changes measurable by electrodermal recordings of skin conductance (e.g., Damasio,
1994). For emotions, many more measurable physiological changes occur. Depending upon the intensity of the emotion, these can include changes in autonomic functions, such as heart rate, blood pressure, respiration, sweating, trembling, and other features; hormonal changes; changes in body temperature; and of course changes in neural function as measurable by EEG (Frijda,
1986, pp. 124-175).
end p.10
For a long time, it has been controversial to suppose that some of these changes were distinct for particular emotions. It has often been seen as an important element of a cognitive theory of emotion to hold that the physiological changes accompanying an emotion amount to a kind of undifferentiated excitation, and that cognitive contents were needed to distinguish anger from fear, happiness from sadness, and so on (a source often cited in support of this view is Schachter & Singer,
1962).
9 However, much of the previous failure to clearly establish distinguishing physiological profiles for emotions or other affects appear now to largely have arisen because of the inadequacy of past measuring techniques. Although the claim remains controversial, evidence is growing for the view that autonomic activity distinguishes among at least some emotions. Paul Ekman, Robert Levenson, and Wallace Friesen have found, for example, that discrimination of a number of emotions (fear, anger, sadness, disgust, surprise, and happiness) was possible just by observing temperature and heart rate changes from baseline measurements (that is, measurements of the subject when presumably not experiencing the emotion). Since these are measurements from a baseline, this study (
1983) does not establish that we can actually identify one of these emotions in a subject on first observation, but it does at least show that we can distinguish the emotion from some others when several measurements are available. These experiments were done with actors, but later found to work with normal subjects (Levenson, Ekman, & Friesen
1990). They also worked not only for directed facial action (asking subjects to form the expression of an emotion) but for reliving (that is, recalling, thinking through) an emotional experience; and results from many other researchers is consistent with these findings (see Levenson
1992 and
1994 for a review). More research is needed in this area as some outstanding questions remain,
10 and the experimental difficulties are great (generating fear, sadness, joy and so on in laboratory conditions is not easy), but these results are substantial and encouraging: they show that a significant number of the emotions may be distinguishable from each other by these autonomic features alone.
These results do not yet allow us to identify emotions by their physiological effects or constituents. But these kinds of investigations at least provide compelling evidence that there are reliable physiological changes that accompany some affects. For the emotions that we will be concerned with here, there is sufficient evidence that these affects necessarily include physiological responses such as changes in temperature, heart rate, and other features—even when the subject is having a relatively weak emotional experience, and even when the subject may be unaware of any such changes. Many cognitivists will deny that emotions necessarily have these correlates. In such a case, we can just be disagreeing about the semantics of our terms: these cognitivists take emotions to be mental contents, perhaps social relations, and these other features are incidental. But, as I will show in the next chapter, such a position is inconsistent with the scientific evidence, and it leaves us unable to distinguish emotions from other kinds of
end p.11
mental states. The claim that measurable physiological changes are necessary—leaving open whether they are sufficient to identify the relevant emotions—is important because such changes are sufficient to distinguish emotions from some other states with which some like to conflate emotion, such as belief. Furthermore, the autonomic patterns and related physiological changes are surely part of the phenomenal experience of some emotions. And these physiological responses are probably also essentially connected to relational actions and other affective behaviors. At the very least, we must explain or take into consideration these physiological features if we are to have a satisfactory theory of emotions.
If the physiological changes accompanying an emotion are necessary but perhaps not sufficient to identify that emotion, we must turn next to the three features of conscious experience, associated actions, and relations to content in order to get a more complete understanding.
Conscious Experience of Affects
Affects like anger, fear, despair, pleasure, and many others can have distinct conscious experiences. It might then seem that affects all are necessarily accompanied by a conscious experience; and many scientists and philosophers assert that emotions must be conscious. There is ambiguity in the term
conscious here, one that has recently come under much analysis by philosophers (I will return to this in chapter
9). However, in this section I am concerned with the notions of consciousness that scientists tend to use; intuitively, a process is conscious if the subject is aware of it, in some sense reflecting upon it, and can use that awareness in directing or performing some action. I will call this sense of consciousness
working consciousness whenever there is a threat of ambiguity.
11 What it is to be aware of a state is not clear, and there certainly are mental states of which the subject is not aware but which influence working-conscious action. This lack of clarity alone casts grave doubts upon the idea that we can gain any definitive understanding of emotions by asserting that they are conscious, or by otherwise finding a role for consciousness in them. Thus, in order to try to ground my discussion of consciousness and emotions, I will have to find some criteria for something's being conscious. One sign of working consciousness is that the agent can, barring any deficiencies (such as brain damage that makes speech impossible, etc.), report on the state. This criterion is too-strong, and it does not get to what the notion of working consciousness seems to be aiming for (that is, I grant that the ability to report on a state is not the same as being aware of it). However, it is at least relatively clear. Furthermore, it comes close to capturing what I believe is really motivating many who insist that emotions must be working conscious: a notion that emotions play a part in our rational and deliberative control of our activities. So for the sake of clarity, I shall use in this section the very strong criterion that a process is working conscious if a subject can report upon that process (I am leaving vague what counts as a report; this should
end p.12
complex and flexible and the wellspring of autonomy. I will return to this point several times.
The view that some emotions can be identified through the actions with which they are associated is perhaps merely a consequence of my definition: since affects are motivations, then the principal method we have for discerning and distinguishing them is through the behavior they motivate. We can always keep in mind, however, a realist (as a philosopher would call it) criterion: when we identify an affect, we are identifying a genuine physical state of an individual organism, and if it later turns out that there is no such significant (that is, measurable) state, or the behavior was best explained in some other way, then we were wrong to so identify the state. In the cases of things like preferences, the motivation is very general (let us assume, for a moment, that there is a state corresponding to "preference"). If a subject S prefers to do some action A, then we are saying little more than that S is in a motivational state which has as an effect that she will A,
ceteris paribus (when it is possible, when she is not constrained, and when there is no stronger motivation to do something inconsistent with A). But other affective states are much more structured. We can understand fear by supposing that if subject S fears some object O, then S will flee from O—with the same
ceteris paribus clause. Some emotions, it seems, are characterized specifically by the complex behavior that they have as a consequence—what psychologists sometimes call "relational actions," since they are explicitly concerned with relations to other things (Frijda
1986, 14-24).
The Affect Program Theory
Some of the things that we call emotions appear to be a collection of things: physiological responses, stereotypical actions, and perhaps even normal cognitive roles. Instead of reductively explaining these emotions in terms of one of these features, I will adopt the naturalistic theory that tries to respect all of them: the affect program theory. This theory is not favored by philosophers or by psychologists who work on the social end of their discipline, but in various forms it is quite common to psychobiologists, neuropsychologists, and others who concern themselves with the biology of emotion. I adapt the notion from Ekman, who took the term from Silvan Tomkins:
For there to be such complexity and organization in various response systems, there must be some central direction. The term affect program refers to a mechanism that stores the patterns for these complex organized responses, and which when set off directs their occurrence. . . . The organization of response systems dictated by the affect program has a genetic basis but is influenced also by experience. The skeletal, facial, vocal, autonomic, and central nervous system changes that occur
end p.23
initially and quickly for one or another emotion, we presume to be in largest part given, not acquired. (Ekman
1980; 82)
By "affect program," Ekman means to refer to only some aspects of the emotions in question. He argues that an emotion is made of an affect program along with a response system, an appraiser, and elicitors (86-87). In a sense, this is of course correct, and a weak form of cognitivism about emotions is tantamount to the view that all of these things are normally present in emotions but they need not all be. I will therefore here just use the term "affect program theory" to refer to the whole syndrome, recognizing that the cognitive elements are in humans quite common, but unnecessary, and that the physiological and behavioral consequences are necessary.
The idea of emotions as affect programs best explained by reference to our evolutionary heritage is perhaps most indebted to the research of Paul MacLean. MacLean introduced the "triune brain" hypothesis (
1990), in which the brain is seen as having three systems, hierarchically arranged, each of which is to some degree independent of the others and which corresponds to a definite stage of evolutionary development. These systems are the "reptilian brain," the paleomammalian or limbic brain, and the neomammalian neocortex. On this model, many affects are reptilian or limbic system adaptive programs that in humans can operate to varying degrees independently of our neocortical systems.
The neuroscientist Jaak Panksepp also offers a compelling approach to the basic emotions that is consistent with the affect program theory. He has offered six criteria that distinguish the basic emotional systems:
1. |
The underlying circuits are genetically predetermined and designed to respond unconditionally to stimuli arising from major life-challenging circumstances.
|
2. |
These circuits organize diverse behaviors by activating or inhibiting motor subroutines and concurrent autonomic-hormonal changes that have proved adaptive in the face of such life-challenging circumstances during the evolutionary history of the species.
|
3. |
Emotive circuits change the sensitivities of sensory systems that are relevant for the behavioral sequences that have been aroused.
|
4. |
Neural activity of emotive systems outlasts the precipitating circumstances.
|
5. |
Emotive circuits can come under the conditional control of emotionally neutral environmental stimuli.
|
6. |
Emotive circuits have reciprocal interactions with the brain mechanisms that elaborate higher decision-making processes and consciousness. (1998, 49)
|
What these various approaches share is a common recognition that some emotions are complex, coordinated events that include motor programs or
end p.24
subroutines, that evolved and are recognizable in homologous form in related organisms, and that are fundamentally enabled in neural circuits. For my purposes here, one of the most fruitful features of the basic emotions, as understood in the affect program theory, is the action or motor programs that in part constitute some of them.
The Central Role of Action and the Parsimony of the Affect Program Theory
The linking of emotions to actions is widely accepted. Nico H. Frijda writes, "Emotions are changes in readiness for action as such . . . or changes in cognitive readiness . . . or changes in readiness for modifying or establishing relationships with the environment . . . or changes in readiness for specific concern-satisfying activities" (
1986, 466). More strongly, he says: "It will be clear that 'action tendency' and 'emotion' are one and the same thing" (71). The psychobiologist Robert Plutchik has argued that "an emotion is a patterned bodily reaction of either protection, destruction, reproduction, deprivation, incorporation, rejection, exploration or orientation, or some combination of these, which is brought about by a stimulus" (
1980, 12). More recently, he added that "emotions are complex chains of events with stabilizing loops that tend to produce some kind of behavioral homeostasis. . . . [The] physiological changes [that accompany an emotion] have the character of anticipatory reactions associated with various types of exertions or impulses, such as the urge to explore, to attack, to retreat, or to mate" (
1994, 100). So that
From an evolutionary point of view one can conceptualize emotions as certain types of adaptive behaviors that can be identified in lower animals as well as in human. These adaptive patterns have evolved to deal with basic survival issues in all organisms, such as dealing with prey and predator, potential mate and stranger, nourishing objects and toxins. Such patterns involve approach or avoidance reactions, fight and flight reactions, attachment and loss reactions, and riddance or ejection reactions. (229)
Silvan Tomkins claims that emotions are innately patterned responses and that these affect programs are stored in subcortical brain centers (
1962,
1963). Richard Lazarus argues that emotions result from primary appraisal of a situation, and a secondary appraisal results in a coping action (
1991). And, as noted above, Panksepp advocates a psychobiological theory of some emotions in which they arise from neural circuits and enable adaptive behaviors; these neural circuits "are genetically hard-wired and designed to respond unconditionally to stimuli arising from major life-challenging circumstances" and they "organize behavior by activating or inhibiting classes of related actions (and concurrent autonomic/hormonal changes) that have proved adaptive in the face of those types of life-challenging
end p.25
circumstances during the evolutionary history of the species" (
1982, 411). Howard Leventhal has presented a perceptual motor theory of emotions, in which "there is a basic set of stimulus-sensitive expressive-motor templates, each of which generates a different emotional experience and expressive-motor behavior" (
1984, 127). I advocate, and will assume here, the hypothesis that basic emotions have as an essential element a motor program.
What is the motor program that is part of the affect program of some emotions? This is an empirical question, but here I can clarify the notion, draw some likely conclusions about its evolution, and warn off likely misunderstandings of the term "program." The program need only be functionally specified for my purposes, but it surely is (primarily) instantiated in a neural system. Once activated, this action program will, if not actively inhibited, result in the emotional behavior. Strictly speaking, the functional definition of the action program therefore has the action as a consequence—much as a functional definition of motor cortex activity, for example, can have motor activity as a consequence.
14 Thus, on this view, given an occurrent basic emotion, it is not the emotional action but the common lack of it, or the modification of it, that requires additional theoretical posits. This is all consistent with the compelling working hypothesis that some emotions evolved from innate behavioral responses—that is, what ultimately amounts to motor programs—in ancestors of the emoting agent. The term "program" is perhaps unfortunate, but I use it because I know of no clear alternative. The motor program is not meant to be a simplistically deterministic list of discrete symbolic instructions, such as a computer program written in Java, for example. It is rather a dynamic capability. A rat running from a fearful stimulus might take a different path each time it flees—but it still may always consistently flee. Many brain systems are perhaps best thought of as dynamical systems (see Port and van Gelder
1995), and like many dynamical systems result in output that is most conveniently described in terms of a range of possible continuous trajectories moving through a state space—which, compared to a computer program, has the flavor of a kind of qualitative, as opposed to quantitative, description.
With this general notion of motor programs in place, the affect program theory yields a bonus of increased parsimony in our theorizing. As we saw, many theories of emotion (including some cognitive theories) share the supposition that an essential feature of emotions is that they have some kind of significant relation to action; the most widespread agreement is that the emotions are at least some kind of disposition or tendency. Although "disposition" takes on the sound of a substantial and well-placed primitive concept in much action theory, it is a mysterious entity and provides not a proper part of a theory but rather a debt to be discharged. Present understanding of the human mind and brain are not sufficient to expect a successful theory of all our disposition talk, and many or most of our disposition concepts and related concepts are merely placeholders for the possibility of the relevant action. However, I have suggested an inversion
end p.26
of the usual explanations: we should take the emotional action as primary, and either the failure to act, or the cognitive guidance of action, as secondary. Since we do have general theories of how inhibitions can work,
15 and since cognition is already a problem, there is some theoretical gain in this approach. Every debt we can pay off is, after all, a net gain in our theoretical finances.
Evolution, Innateness, and Inheritability
The affect program theory will ultimately be verified and fully developed as the relevant neural systems are identified and understood. However, from a functional and from a psychoevolutionary perspective, the most distinguishing feature of an affect program is the behavior that, at least in part, constitutes it. Presumably, like the facial expressions that accompany and express some basic emotions, the more complex relational action patterns that characterize some basic emotions started as motor programs that evolved into inheritable patterns of behavior. As some of the species having these motor programs evolved ("toward" us, for example), some of these behaviors remained, although they became subject to alteration and inhibition via new capabilities that accrued to the species involved. In ourselves, these action programs can be occurrent—one might say, "running"—but result in diverse or even no overt behavior. Thus, the program that makes up an occurrent basic emotion, I claim, is in part the occurrence of the relevant behaviors (in the broad neuroscientific sense); and for at least some of the basic emotions, this includes some relational action. The relational action of a basic emotion is a consequence of the occurrent action program if the action program is not inhibited. Similarly, most other features of an affect program can also best be explained by reference to their role in the behavior of the emotion.
But I have been rough with the evolutionary claim about the affect program. This is partly because the conclusions I aim to draw in this book are largely independent of the variations that I gloss over. Thus, how "universal" the relevant affects are is a concern I hope to pass over in the interest of avoiding a set of important but distinct philosophical problems. For my purposes here, any significant portion of the relevant populations having some of these features is going to be sufficient. Thus, I will hold only that the basic emotions are biologically based capabilities (that is, the structures which allow them to occur can be described by a biological science—above all, neuroscience), that they are pancultural (that they arise in every culture, even if not in every individual), and that they are inheritable (the reason they occur in individuals in every culture is because some people inherit this capability). Maintaining only these presuppositions should allow me to avoid such issues as, for example, the degree to which the inheritability of the basic emotions is "innate" or a result of the inheritance of common environments. It is fair to say that no feature of our neuroanatomy is not shaped by learning, and I certainly would deny a claim that basic
end p.27