I showed a number of objections in chapter
2 to doxastic cognitivism and to reductive cognitivism, some relying upon scientific results. But there are things commonly observed and experienced by all of us that entail very obvious objections to these theories. One of the most interesting of these is music. Music need not be about anything to generate affects; we hear a particular melody and, as if entrained to the dynamic of the flow, our affective state can change. There is no plausible way for a reductive or doxastic cognitive theory to cohere with this possibility: no beliefs are required, it is unclear in what sense any complex cognitions, such as other propositional attitudes, could be required. If music can generate emotions, then these kinds of cognitive theories are simply false.
32 This alone is a compelling mystery that is, more often than not, ignored by cognitivists. But in this chapter I will be concerned with another anomaly: that we emote for the concreta or the events portrayed in fictions. If a basic emotion were to require, or were in part even constituted by, a particular kind of belief, then how can it be that we frequently have that emotion for situations in which we explicitly understand that the relevant proposition is false? Typically, for doxastic cognitivism and related kinds of reductive cognitivism, for someone to be angry, she must believe that someone has been wronged; to feel sad, she must believe that someone has suffered some loss; to feel fear, she must believe that something of value is in danger. The problem for emoting for fictions, therefore, is that we have (what some will say only appear to be) emotions for fictional characters and situations. If Karen is angry that King Lear's daughters are cruel to him, and Karen is sad for the king, then on the reductive or doxastic cognitivist theory of emotions she must believe that King Lear's daughters are being cruel to the king and that the king is suffering as a result. But Karen knows that
King Lear is just a play, that she is sitting in the theater, that John Gielgud is an actor and not a king, that he does not suffer (at least not in any direct, morally culpable way) the harms being portrayed. Presumably she also does not believe that King Lear was an actual person. So what exactly is happening when she frowns, and turns red, or even when tears come to her eyes? As Bijoy Boruah has put it: "Why is it that the sadness, which is defined in real-life contexts by reference to an appropriate belief about the sad object, recurs in a context that excludes the rational possibility of forming the appropriate belief?" (
1988, 83). On pain of contradiction, some presupposition must be rejected—either the claim that Karen is having an emotion, or the claim that Karen does not believe that King Lear exists, or the assumption that the appropriate kind of belief is necessary for the emotion.