INDEX
Page numbers refer to the print edition but are hyperlinked to the appropriate location in the e-book.
The Accidental Mind (Linden), 176
activity and passivity, 15, 22–23, 37–41
adequate and inadequate causes and ideas, 37, 38, 44
affectio and affectus, translation of, 4–5
Affective Neuroscience (Panksepp), 176–77, 186–87
affective structures (Affektbildungen), 110–13, 116, 157–58, 212
affects, xv–xviii; “affect” as positive term for a negative x, 209–10; as aftereffects of interactions of signifiers, 123, 135; and Agamben’s zoē-bios distinction, 193–94; as always affects of essence (Spinoza’s conception), 35–36, 43–44; anxiety as the sole or central affect (Lacan’s conception), 147–48, 151, 213; complex and enigmatic nature of, 134, 137–38, 146–47; and conatus, 37–41, 217; deceptive nature of, 206–9; defined, 4–5, 38, 41–42; detachment from (see affects, detachment from/absence of); displacement of, 124, 127, 137, 138, 155; distinction between affects and emotions/feelings (Lacan’s conception), 151; doubts raised about during analysis, 140–41, 147–48, 151–52; and the face, 46–48; and false connections, 103–4, 107, 122, 128, 145; and gap between the biological and the more-than-biological, 190; and homeostatic regulation, 31, 50–51, 217–18; and immediacy, 85–86, 134–35; impact of language on, 163, 189–90, 200; imprecise vocabulary for, 198–200, 207; as modifications, 5; modulation by intellectual, linguistic, and representational configurations, 163; as natural ontological phenomena, 36; origin of, 4, 6, 21; potential, 114–16; quota of (Affektbetrag), 109–10, 112–13, 214–16; and repression, 205; as signifiers, 205–10; and syncope, 23–24; three stages of processing (Damasio’s conception), 164–66; two-way modulation between affects and signifiers, 200; unconscious (see affects, unconscious); and warfare, 132; without subjects, 6–7. See also anxiety; emotions; feelings; Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis; Freudian metapsychology of affects; generosity; guilt; hatred; joy; Lacan-inspired metapsychology of affects; love; passions; sadness; shame; wonder; specific philosophers, psychoanalysts, and neuroscientists
affects, detachment from/absence of, 7–8; and brain damage, 58–60; Damasio and, 33–34, 58–60, 64; Elliot case, 11, 59–60; impaired capacity for wonder, 10–11; and lack of concern, 59–60, 71; “L” case, 60; Phineas Gage case, xii–xiv, 57–58; Sacks and, 71
affects, unconscious, xvii, xviii; Copjec’s denial of, 155; Damasio and, 163–65; distinguished from potential affects, 114–16; and false connections, 107, 122; Fink and, 122; and Freud’s Affekte/Gefühle/Emfindungen terminology, 112–13; Freud’s vacillations over, xvii, 75–80, 88–101, 105–13, 118, 119, 155, 212; Harari and, 122; Lacan’s denial of, 76, 84, 111, 119, 122, 129, 134, 149, 212–13; as misfelt feelings, 94–95; and neurobiology, 87; and pleasure and pain, 166–67; as potential-to-feel, 108–9; Pulver and, 113–17; and resistance to attempts to reconcile psychoanalytic theory with neuroscience, 81–82; and shame, 162. See also feelings, misfelt; guilt
Les affects lacaniens (Soler), 82
affectuation (Lacan’s neologism), 141, 146–47, 208
Affektbildungen, 110–13, 157–58, 212
Affekte, 111–14, 119, 212
agalma, 70–71
Agamben, Giorgio, 192–93
All About Eve (film), 11
alterity, xvi, 6, 9, 10, 17, 24, 64, 221
Alzheimer’s disease, xiii, xiv
amygdala, 218
anger, 13, 186
animals, 151, 170, 182, 186, 187, 189, 192
animal spirits, Descartes and, 13–14, 17, 46
anosognosia, 33, 60, 71. See also brain damage
Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (Kant), 196
antinaturalism, xi, 172, 180–84, 187–88, 190, 193, 197, 204
Anton’s Syndrome, 60
anxiety: and bodily movements, 13; Freud and, 89–90, 99–100, 110; and gap between cognitive and emotional abilities, 174; guilt felt as, 89–91, 99–101, 110, 212–13; Harari and, 134–35; and hysteria, 87; Lacan and, 82, 133, 139–40, 151–52; and obsessive disorders, 89–90; relationship to doubt, 151–52; and repression, 110; as a signal, not representing itself, 134–35; as sole or central affect, 147–48, 151, 213; Žižek and, 172, 174
autoaffection, xvi; autoaffection as temporality as the origin of all other affects (Heidegger’s concept), 6; cerebral autoaffection, 221–23; Damasio and, 31, 33–34, 51, 64; deconstruction of, 7; defined, 5–6, 21, 221; Deleuze and, 45, 48–49; Deleuze’s reading of Descartes and, 46; Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza and, 36, 45; Derrida and, 19–25, 63; and feeling of existence, 6, 20; Heidegger and, 5–6; and homeostasis, 31, 64; impaired mechanism for, 34 (see also brain damage); and imprecise vocabulary for affects, 199; and the “inner voice,” 20, 21; and mapping between affects and concepts, 42; as mutual mirroring of mind and body, 55; and neurobiology, 26; nonsubjective autoaffection, 55; and plane of immanence, 45–46; and self-touching, 19–21, 63; and spatiality, 46; term origin, 5–6; and types of knowledge, 45; and the unconscious, 221–23; and wonder, 9–11, 63–64
autobiographical self, 31–33, 169–70
auto-heteroaffection, 55
Badiou, Alain, 175
beauty, 160–61
Beyond the Pleasure Principle (Freud), 77–78
big Other, 173–75, 188, 200, 206
bios, 192–93
blood circulation, 13–14
body: bodily movements, 13–15, 37–38, 40, 46–48; delocalization of, 68–69. See also organism
body-mind connection: and conatus, 38; Damasio and, 29–30, 164–66; Derrida and, 21–23; Descartes and, 12–15, 18, 21–22, 30; emotions and physiological processes, 164–67; and generosity, 18; Green and, 202–3; and inadequacy of brain events, 29–30; and linguistic mediation, 201; mind and body as expressions of the same substance, 36, 51; mind as the idea of the body, 51, 53, 166; and “organism” term, 55; and passions “in” the soul, 12–15; and pineal gland, 14–16, 21–23; and spatiality of the soul, 21–23; Spinoza and, 36, 38, 51, 53; substance of Descartes’ error, 30
brain: and autoexcitation, 216–19; and bodily movements, 13–14; cerebral autoaffection, 221–23; Changeux and, 195–98; computer model of, 27; Damasio and, 26–34, 163–70, 187, 217; Descartes and, 16, 30; and drives, 213–16; as “electrical center” (Breuer’s conception), 213–14; and evolution, 175–76, 180–83, 187–89, 201; Freud and, 60–62, 214–16, 255–56nn7,21; hardwired absences of hardwiring, 201–2; as hodgepodge of modules without overall coherent function, 175–77; interconnectedness of, 177, 194, 200; and language, 177, 195–201; and language acquisition, 195–96, 199–200; and learning, 195–98; LeDoux and, 175–79, 187–88; Linden and, 176; location of cerebral sites producing emotion, 218–19; mirror neurons, xi, 256n20; and mortality, 223–24; neural plasticity, xi, 26–28, 56–58, 190–91, 194, 202; Panksepp and, 176–77, 190–91; and perception, 27, 166–67; Pommier and, 197; self-mapping, 164–67; and subjectivity, 28; substance of Descartes’ error, 30; and symbolic activity, 213–14, 216, 219–23; trinity of cognition, emotion, and motivation, 163, 176, 177; and the unconscious, 71, 219–21
The Brain and the Inner World (Solms and Turnbull), 27–28, 57, 186
brain damage, xii–xiv, 56–62, 71; and damaged subjectivity, 28, 33–34; and detachment from one’s own affects, 7–8, 33, 58–60; and dreaming, 62; Elliot case, 11, 59–60; “L” case, 60; and loss of wonder, 11, 33, 60; and neuropsychoanalysis, 29; Phineas Gage case, xii–xiv, 57–58; and plasticity of the brain, 56–58; and role of emotions in reason, 8; and transformation of personality, xiii–xiv, 57–61
Breuer, Josef, 213–14, 218
care for self and others: CARE emotional system, 186; relationship between feelings, emotions, and care for self and others, 51
cathexes, 110, 125, 131
La causalité psychique: Entre nature et culture (Green), 202–3
causes. See adequate and inadequate causes
Chalmers, David, 202
Changeux, Jean-Pierre, 165, 195–97
Cinema I (Deleuze), 46
civilization, 132, 184
Civilization and Its Discontents (Freud), 95–98, 100–101, 184
class consciousness, 86
cognition: differences between cognition and emotion, 194; entanglement of emotional and nonemotional dimensions, 177–78, 190–91, 194, 200; trinity of cognition, emotion, and motivation, 163, 176, 177. See also rationality; thought
cognitive games, 195–96
conatus, 6, 217; affects and variability of conatus, 37–41, 54; defined, 38; and definition of emotions, 41–42; feelings, emotions, and self-attachment, 51; and joy and sorrow, 39–40; and origin of personal identity, 52; and self-preservation, 52; and wonder, 40–41
conscience, 77–79, 91–92, 95. See also guilt
consciousness: as awareness of a disturbance caused by an external object, 30; and dupery, 208; LeDoux on, 188–89; link between consciousness and emotion, 30–31; as outgrowth of self-mapping dynamics, 164–67; as two-sided instance (speaker/listener etc.), 20. See also mind; psyche; self; soul; subjectivity; specific philosophers, psychoanalysts, and neuroscientists
conscious-preconscious-unconscious triad, 69–70, 78, 92
conversion, conversion symptoms, 103–4
Copernicus, Nicolaus, 83, 148
Copjec, Joan, 154–55
core self, 31–32, 169–72
Corpus (Nancy), 23–24
criminality, 72, 78, 92–93
Critique of Judgment (Kant), 53
Critique of Pure Reason (Kant), 5–6
Damasio, Antonio, xvi, xviii; and autoaffection, 31, 33–34, 51, 64; and brain damage, 33–34, 58–60, 71–72; and debate between naturalism and antinaturalism, 180–84; definition of emotion, 51; Descartes and (see Damasio’s reading of Descartes); distinction between pain and emotion caused by pain, 65–66; distinction between public emotions and private feelings, 163–64, 166, 179–80; and Elliot case, 11, 59–60; and evolution of the brain, 187; feelings-had and feelings-known, 165, 167–69; and Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis, 165–66; and heteroaffection, 34, 65–66; importance of emotions and feelings for survival, 50–53; importance of emotions in neural regulation, 7, 217; and “L” case, 60; and loss of wonder, 11, 33, 64; and mental images/ideas, 54; and nonconscious affects, 163–65; and Phineas Gage case, xii–xiv, 57–58; Spinoza and (see Damasio’s reading of Spinoza); structure of the self, 31–33, 169–74, 217, 219–20, 222–23; three stages of processing in affective life, 164–66; and the unconscious, 163–68, 179–80; and wonder, 11, 32–33, 64; Žižek’s critique of, 162–63, 165, 169–74, 179–84, 190
Damasio’s reading of Descartes, 7; and body-mind connection, 29–30; Cartesian mind as a “disembodied” mind, 22; and inadequacy of brain events, 29–30; and link between consciousness and emotion, 30–31; and neural plasticity, 26–28; substance of Descartes’ error, 30
Damasio’s reading of Spinoza, 7, 50–55; and body-mind connection, 53; differing readings of Damasio and Deleuze, 36; emotions, feelings, and conatus, 50–53; and mapping, 51–55; and self-preservation, 52–53
Darwin, Charles, 83
Davidson, Donald, 200–201
death, 159–61; death drive, 172, 181–82; and the unconscious, 223
deceptive nature of affects and signifiers, 206–9
decision making, 7, 30
defense mechanisms, xviii, 76, 87, 127, 155; Damasio and, 168–69; and doubt and anxiety, 152; Freud and, 103–10, 115, 131; and shame, 162. See also repression
In Defense of Lost Causes (Žižek), 172
Deleuze, Gilles, xvi; affect term definition, 4–5; and conceptual personae, 48; and delocalization of the natural body, 68–69; Descartes and (see Deleuze’s reading of Descartes); and different concepts of affects and autoaffection, 48–49; and heteroaffection, 65, 68–69; and nonmetaphysical concept of philosophy, 48–49; and perception, 67; and plane of immanence, 45–46, 48, 64, 67; privileged metaphor of the face, 64; Spinoza and (see Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza); and touch, 66–67; and wonder, 47–48, 64, 71
Deleuze’s reading of Descartes, 7, 45–48, 229n1; and facial expressions, 46–48; two possible readings of Descartes, 48–49; and wonder, 47–48
Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza: and affects as affects of essence, 36, 43–44; and affect term definition, 4–5; and autoaffection, 45; differing readings of Damasio and Deleuze, 36; and God/Nature, 41–42; and heteroaffection, 65; and joyful and sorrowful affects, 39–40; and nonsubjective autoaffection, 36; and touch, 66–67; and types of knowledge/ideas, 44–45, 66–67; and variability of conatus and the power of acting, 41–42
denaturalized subjectivity, 172–74, 178, 180–84, 187–88, 202. See also antinaturalism
Derrida, Jacques, xvi, xvii; and autoaffection, 19–25, 63; and delocalization of the natural body, 68–69; Descartes and, 19–25; and generosity, 24–25, 64; and heteroaffection, 7, 19, 20–21, 24, 25, 58, 64–65, 68–69; and pineal gland, 21–23; privileged metaphor of the graft, 64; and sense of touch, 21–24, 64, 69; and spatiality of the psyche, 69; tribute to Jean-Luc Nancy, 23; “two lovers” text, 64–65; and wonder, 11, 23–25, 64, 71
Descartes, René, xvi; and body-mind connection, 12–15, 18, 21–22, 30; definition of passions of the soul, 6, 13; Derrida’s interpretation of, 19–25; Descartes-Spinoza conflict, 7, 37–38; external signs of the passions (facial expressions etc.), 45–48; and functions of the soul, 15; and generosity, 13, 17–18, 25; and immediacy, 85; Irigaray and, 226n15; and nonmetaphysical concept of philosophy, 48–49; passions “in” the soul as consequences of bodily movements, 13–15; passions “of” the soul as related to the soul alone, 15–16; and perception, 14–15; and pineal gland, 14–16, 22; repudiation of Descartes’ equation of the mental with the conscious, 85; and wonder, 8–9, 16–18, 25. See also Damasio’s reading of Descartes; Deleuze’s reading of Descartes
DescartesError (Damasio), 4, 7–8, 26–28, 57, 59–60, 189
desire: and agalma, 70–71; Lacan and, 124; as one of six primitive passions (Descartes’ conception), 9, 12; and power of acting, 40; SEEKING emotional system, 186, 201. See also conatus; drives
Le discours vivant (Green), 106–7
doubt: and deceptive nature of signifiers and affects, 210; doubts raised about affects during analysis, 140–41, 147–48, 151–52; relationship to anxiety, 151–52
dreaming, 62
drives: and the brain, 213–16; and confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32; Damasio and, 164, 165, 167; death drive, 172, 181–82; Descartes and, 226n15; Freud and, 105–6, 109, 127, 131, 213–16; Lacan and, 125–32; Leclaire and, 136; and SEEKING emotional system, 201; and sexuality, 214–15
dupery, 207–8
ego: and “ego ideal,” 92, 95; and the protoself, 222; and spatiality of the psyche, 69; structural dynamics between ego and superego, 92–93, 99–101; and the unconscious, 92. See also id-ego-superego triad
The Ego and the Id (Freud), 78, 88, 91–94, 101, 113, 212, 222
Elliot (Damasio’s detached patient), 11, 59–60
The Emotional Brain (LeDoux), 175, 188
emotions, xvii–xviii; and Agamben’s zoē-bios distinction, 193–94; and decision making, 7, 30; distinction between affects and emotions/feelings (Lacan’s conception), 151; distinction between public emotions and private feelings (Damasio’s conception), 163–64, 166, 179–80; entanglement with nonemotional dimensions, 177–78, 190–91, 194, 200; and formation of images/ideas, 54; greater variety of negative emotions compared to positive emotions, 187; and homeostatic regulation, 31, 50–51; imprecise vocabulary for, 198–200, 207; link between consciousness and emotion, 30–31; Panksepp’s taxonomy of seven elementary emotions, 186–87, 192, 201; primary and secondary (“social”) emotions, 217; and rationality, 7–8, 30, 50; relationship amongst affects, emotions, and feelings (Freud’s conception), 110–14; relationship amongst emotion, feeling, and knowing (Damasio’s conception), 164–65; relationship amongst feelings, emotions, and care for self and others (Damasio’s conception), 51. See also affects; feelings; passions; specific philosophers, psychoanalysts, and neuroscientists
Empfindungen, 212; confusion caused by translation issues, 119; Damasio and, 165; and deception, 208; and feelings-had and feelings-known, 167–69; and honte (shame as a felt feeling), 157–58; relation to Affekte and Gefühle, 111–14
epigenetics, xi, 188, 191, 194, 196–97, 199
Ethics (Spinoza), 4–5, 35–42
evolution, xi, 175–76, 180–83, 186–87, 201
existence, 5, 6, 20, 32, 39–40. See also self-preservation
experience, 27–28, 44, 56, 57
face and facial expressions, 46–48, 64
false connections, 103–4, 107, 122, 128, 145
fear: and bodily movements, 13, 14; FEAR emotional system, 186, 189; and wonder, 9
The Feeling of What Happens (Damasio), 58, 162–63, 169, 170
feelings, xvii–xviii; and deception, 208; distinction between affects and emotions/feelings (Lacan’s conception), 151; distinction between public emotions and private feelings (Damasio’s conception), 163–64, 179–80; feelings-had and feelings-known, 165, 167–69; as feelings of feelings, xviii, 85; and Lacan’s distinction between honte and pudeur, 157–62; misfelt (see feelings, misfelt); and neural maps, 52, 165; relationship amongst affects, emotions, and feelings (Freud’s conception), 110–14, 164–65; relationship amongst feelings, emotions, and care for self and others (Damasio’s conception), 51. See also affects; emotions; Empfindungen; passions; specific philosophers, psychoanalysts, and neuroscientists
feelings, misfelt, xviii, 86, 212; Damasio and, 165; and doubts raised about feelings during analysis, 140–41; and enigmatic nature of affects, 146–47; and false connections, 107; Freud’s statements on, 106–7 (see also Freudian metapsychology of affects); Green and, 106–7; and guilt, 90–91, 99–101, 107, 162, 212–13; and hysteria, 87, 103; Lacan and, 106–7, 141, 146–47, 152–53, 162; and shame, 162; and three destinies of quotas of affect (felt, misfelt, unfelt), 109–10; unconscious affects as, 94–95; Žižek and, 141. See also defense mechanisms
Fink, Bruce, 118, 119, 122, 125–26, 145
force of existing, 5, 39–40
Foucault, Michel, 192
free association, 166, 203
free will, 18
Freud, Sigmund, x, xiii, 88–101; and affects (see Freudian metapsychology of affects); and anxiety, 89–90, 99–101; belief in lack of symbolic activity in the nervous system, 214–15; and the brain, 60–62, 214–16, 255–56nn7,21; city of Rome analogy for psyche, 60–61, 198; and conscience, 77–78, 91–92, 95; and “criminals from a sense of guilt,” 78, 92–93; dichotomy between energy and structure, 84, 102, 126; and drives, 105–6, 109, 127, 131, 213–16; on the ego, 222; focus on guilt, 78–79; Green and, 111; and hysteria, 86–87, 103–4; Kant and, 69; Lacan and, 84, 103, 119, 148–49 (see also Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis); and moral masochism, 93, 95–97; and negative therapeutic reaction, 94; and obsessive disorders, 88–89, 98–99, 103; and plasticity (capacity to preserve the past), 60–62; and pleasure principle, 95, 218; and primacy of the unconscious, 83–84; and principle of inertia, 218; and problem of unconscious guilt, 78–80, 88–101; and psychical energy, 215; recognition of possible to-be-discovered physiological mechanisms in affective life, 104–5; and remorse, 98–99; and revolutionary nature of discovery of the unconscious, 83–84, 148–49; and sleep, 61–62, 93; and spatiality of the psyche, 69–70; and structure of the self, 69–70, 78, 92 (see also id-ego-superego triad); vacillations over possibility of unconscious affects, xvii, 75–80, 88–101, 105–13, 118, 119, 155, 212; and warfare, 132. See also consciousness; ego; Freudian metapsychology of affects; id; id-ego-superego triad; preconscious; superego; unconscious
Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis, xii, xvii; affects as aftereffects of interactions of signifiers, 123, 135; and anxiety, 133, 151–52; complexity and enigmatic nature of affects, 134, 137–38, 146–47; cross-resonating relations between multiple representations, 128–29; Damasio and, 165–66; and desire, 124; and drift/displacement of affects, 122, 124, 137, 138, 155; estrangement of the parlêtre from its affects, 137–38; inextricable entanglement of the affective and the intellectual, 120–22; Lacan’s assertion that there exists one central affect (anxiety), 139–40, 147–48, 151; Lacan’s denial of unconscious affects, 76, 84, 111, 119, 122, 129, 134, 149, 212–13; Lacan’s objections to affective life as primary focus of analysis, 120–21; neologism affectuation, 141, 146–47, 208; neologism jouis-sens, 143–46, 196–98; neologism lalangue, 141–46, 195–200; neologism senti-ment, 141, 146–47, 213; priority of signifier-ideas over affects, 122–24; representation and the confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32, 135–37; repression, 122, 125–34, 138; sexuality and death, 161; signifiers as sole entities capable of becoming unconscious through repression, 119
Freudian metapsychology of affects, 102–17; affective structures (Affektbildungen), 110–13, 116, 157–58, 212; confusion caused by translation issues, 119, 125–32; conversion, conversion symptoms, 103; defense mechanisms, 103–10, 115, 131; dichotomy between energy and structure, 102, 112, 144; distinction between “affect” (Affekt) and “idea” (Vorstellung), 102–3; and drives, 105–6, 109; false connections, 103–4; Lacan and, 114 (see also Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis); and misfelt feelings, 106–7; misunderstandings in Anglo-American tradition, 114–15, 119; primary and secondary processes, 143–45; primary repression and secondary repression/repression proper, 125–26; Pulver and, 113–17; quota of affect (Affektbetrag), 109–10, 112–13, 214–16; relationship amongst affects, emotions, and feelings, 110–14, 164–65; three destinies of quotas of affect (felt, misfelt, unfelt), 109–10; and unconscious vs. potential affects, 114–16
Gage, Phineas, xii–xiv, 57–58
gaze, and psychoanalytic relationship, 70–71
Gefühle, 111–14, 212
generosity, 13, 17–18, 24–25, 64
God, 36, 41–42, 44, 53
Green, André, 106–7, 111–12, 202–5
guilt, xv, xvii, 88–101, 110–13; and anxiety, 89–91, 99–101, 110, 212–13; and civilization, 97–98; feeling of culpability without awareness of transgression, 78, 91, 110, 162, 212; Freud’s vacillations over unconscious sense of guilt, 78–80, 88–101, 113, 212–13; as fundamental philosophical affect in relation to ethics, 77; guilt-in-search-of-a-crime, 78, 92–93; and id-ego-superego triad, 78–80, 88, 91–93, 99–101; and moral masochism, 93, 95–97; and need for punishment, 96–97, 99, 101; and negative therapeutic reaction, 94; and obsessive disorders, 88–89, 98–99; as penalty imposed by conscience, 95; as potentially misfelt feeling, 107 (see also anxiety); reasons for focus on, 77; and three destinies of quotas of affect (felt, misfelt, unfelt), 110; two modes of unconscious guilt (Žižek’s conception), 162; unconscious guilt as instance of Gefühl, not Empfindung, 113; unresolved questions about, 78. See also conscience
haptocentrism, 21
Harari, Roberto, 122, 134–35
Harvey, William, 13–14
hatred, 9, 12, 146
heart, 13–14, 21
Hegel, G. W. F., xviii, 85, 190–91
Heidegger, Martin, xi, xvi, 5–6, 20
heteroaffection, xvi, 7; auto-heteroaffection, 55; and biological basis of subjectivity, 55; and conatus, 42; Damasio and, 34, 65–66; defined, 20–21, 63; Deleuze and, 49, 65, 68–69; Derrida and, 19, 20–21, 24, 25, 58, 64–65, 68–69; and generosity, 25; and Nancy’s nonmetaphysical sense of touch, 23–24; and neural maps, 55; and pain, 65–66; and “self-touching you,” 24; and source of affects, 21; and spatiality of the psyche, 69; Spinoza and, 42; and wonder, 9, 11, 63–64
hetero-heteroaffection, xvi, xviii, 11
homeostasis: and autoaffection, 31, 64; and the cerebral unconscious, 220–21; consciousness as awareness of a disturbance to an organism’s homeostasis caused by an external object, 30; Damasio and, 30–33, 50–51, 64, 168–69; role of emotions in homeostatic regulation, 31, 50–51, 217–18; and structure of the self, 33, 220–23; and symbolic activity in the brain, 219–23
homunculus, 222–23
honte, 82, 157–62
Husserl, Edmund, xi, 20
hysteria, 86–87, 103–4
hystericization of the analysand, 140–41, 153
icon, 47, 49
id: as intercessor between the brain and the psyche, 203; and SEEKING emotional system, 201; and spatiality of the psyche, 69. See also id-ego-superego triad
ideas: affects without ideas as blind/ideas without affects as empty, 121; ideas as only entities ever repressed, 155 (see also Lacan, Jacques: denial of unconscious affects); inextricable entanglement of the affective and the intellectual, 120–22, 163; unconscious ideas, 110, 164
ideational representations, 84; affects as aftereffects of interactions of signifiers, 123; cross-resonating relations between multiple representations, 128–29; and defense mechanisms, 103, 107–10, 125–26, 155; distinction between “affect” (Affekt) and “idea” (Vorstellung), 102–3; and drives, 105–6; and false connections, 107; Green and, 205; and instincts, 214–15; Lacan and (see signifiers); and misfelt feelings, 107; and obsessive disorders, 90; priority of signifier-ideas over affects, 122–24; representation and the confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32. See also signifiers; Vorstellungen
id-ego-superego triad, 101; and moral masochism, 95–97; and possibility of unconscious guilt, 78–80, 88, 91–93; relation to conscious-preconscious-unconscious triad, 78, 92; structural dynamics between ego and superego, 92–93, 99–101; superego distinguished from conscience, 92. See also ego; id; superego
identity: conatus and origins of personal identity, 52; personality transformation due to brain damage, xiii–xiv, 57–61; and the protoself, 219–20; self-model and a new conception of materialism, 72; and the unconscious, 92, 221
immediacy, 85–86, 134–35, 151, 192
instincts, 182, 190–91, 213
International Neuropsychoanalysis Society, 28
intuition, 44–45, 69
Irigaray, Luce, 226n15
Jablonka, Eva, 188
Jacob, François, 176
jouis-sens (Lacan’s neologism), 143–46, 165, 167, 196–98
joy: neural maps associated with, 54; as one of six primitive passions (Descartes’ conception), 9, 12; and power of acting, 39–40, 53; Spinoza’s definition, 39, 54; and states of equilibrium, 54; and variability of conatus, 39–40; and wonder, 40–41
Kant, Immanuel: and autoaffection, 5–6; Freud and, 69; and intuition, 69; Panksepp and, 190–91; and “plastic force,” 53; relationship between affects and ideas, 121; and socialization, 196; and subjectivity, 170
Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (Heidegger), 5–6
Kantbuch (Heidegger), 20
Kludge (Marcus), 176
knowledge: intuition, 44–45, 69; knowledge from random experience, 44; knowledge from signs, 44–45; Spinoza’s conception of three kinds of knowledge/ideas, 44–45, 66–67
Lacan, Jacques, x, 117–49, 195–200; agalma and the gaze, 70–71; and alienation, 129–30; and anxiety, 82, 133, 151–52, 213; and beauty, 160–61; contrast to Pulver, 114; Copjec and, 154–58; and deceptive nature of signifiers and affects, 206–9; denial of unconscious affects, 76, 84, 111, 119, 122, 129, 134, 149, 212–13; dichotomy between the signifier and jouissance, 155; distinction between “dupery” and “deception,” 207–8; and events of May ‘68, 154–55; formations of the unconscious, 108, 111; and free association, 166; Freud and, 84, 103, 119, 148–49 (see also Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis); and the intersection of the biological and the social, 202–3; lack of references to Freud’s German terminology for affects, emotions, and feelings, 119, 134, 151, 156; and language and translation issues, 155–56; and misfelt feelings, 152–53; and the nature of reality, 139; opposition between conscious affects and unconscious signifiers, 84; and resistance to attempts to reconcile psychoanalytic theory with neuroscience, 81; responses to criticisms of neglect of affects, 81–82, 123–24, 133–36, 150; seminars (see Lacan, seminars of); and shame, 153–62; signifiers (see signifiers); theory of the four discourses (analyst, master, university, hysteric), 139–41, 147; and thinking without thinking that one thinks/knowing without knowing that one knows, 84, 87, 149; and the unconscious, 82–83, 155, 179–80, 208; and wonder, 70–71; Žižek and, 162. See also Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis; Lacan-inspired metapsychology of affects; signifiers
Lacan, seminars of, 212–13; 5th seminar, 158–59; 6th seminar (Desire and Its Interpretation), 122–23, 128; 7th seminar (The Ethics of Psychoanalysis), 123, 132, 160–61, 213; 9th seminar (Identification), 123; 10th seminar (Anxiety), 119–20, 133, 134, 150, 151–52, 213; 11th seminar (The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psycho-Analysis), 129, 132, 153; 17th seminar (The Other Side of Psychoanalysis), 119–20, 133, 137–38, 153–54, 156; 18th seminar, 146; 19th seminar, 141–42; 21st seminar, 206; 23rd seminar (Le sinthome), 124; 25th seminar, 143
Lacan-inspired metapsychology of affects: and Agamben’s zoē-bios distinction, 193–94; Damasio and, 167–68; distinction between affect and emotion/feeling, 151; relationship between anxiety and doubt, 151–52; and shame, 153–62
lalangue (Lacan’s neologism), 141–46, 167, 195–200
Lamb, Marion J., 188
language: and body-mind connection, 201; confusion caused by translation issues, 119, 125–32, 135–37, 155–56; and desynchronization in the brain, 177; and free association, 142–43; impact on experience of feelings, 189–90; imprecise vocabulary for affects, 198–200, 207; and inextricable entanglement of the affective and the intellectual, 120–22; lalangue neologism, 141–46, 167, 195–200; language acquisition, 195–96, 199–200; and neuroscience, 195–201; and structure of the self, 171
Laplanche, Jean, 102, 136–37, 213
learning theory, 195–98
Leclaire, Serge, 136–37
Lectures on Internal Time Consciousness (Husserl), 20
LeDoux, Joseph, xvi, xviii, 174–79, 182, 187–90
libidinal economy, 3–4, 109, 126, 201, 211
life: Agamben’s zoē-bios distinction, 192–93; and autoaffection, 20; and conatus, 38; and debate between naturalism and antinaturalism, 172–74; survival promoted by emotions and feelings, 50–53; Žižek’s life 2.0, life 1.0, 172–73, 192–94, 197–98
limbic system, 176, 218
Linden, David J., 176
logocentrism, 21
Looking for Spinoza (Damasio), 4, 50, 53, 166
love, 9, 12, 70, 174
Lukács, Georg, xi, 86
Luria, A. R., 27
LUST emotional system, 186
The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat (Sacks), 71
maps, mapping, 64; and Damasio’s reading of Spinoza, 51–55; and Deleuze’s reading of Descartes, 45; and Deleuzian conception of autoaffection, 45; and feelings as perceptions, 166–67; interruption of mapping process (see affects, detachment from/absence of; brain damage); maps between affects and concepts, 42; self-mapping in the brain, 164–67, 220; and structure of the self, 171, 219–20; and symbolic activity in the brain, 219–23
Marcus, Gary, 176
Marxism, 86
masochism, 93, 95–97
materialism, new conception of, ix, 72, 204
McDowell, John, 85–86
melancholy, 174
memory, 32, 60–61, 168
mental illness. See brain damage; hysteria; obsessive disorders; psychopathologies; psychosis
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 66–67
Metzinger, Thomas, 72
Miller, Jacques-Alain, 129, 153
mind. See body-mind connection; consciousness; psyche; self; soul; subjectivity
mirror neurons, xi, 256n20
misfelt feelings. See feelings, misfelt
modesty, 158–62
The Movement Image (Deleuze), 43
Nancy, Jean-Luc, 20, 23–24, 227n18
Nature: and debate between naturalism and antinaturalism, 172–74, 180–84, 187–88, 190, 204; and self-preservation, 53; Spinoza and, 36, 53; Žižek’s life 2.0, life 1.0, 172–73, 192–94, 197–98
neurobiology, x, 166; and autoaffection, 26; conflict with metaphysics, 7; and Damasio’s structure of the self, 31–32; and detachment from one’s own affects, 7 (see also brain damage); distinction between psychoanalytic unconscious and term as used in neuroscience, 177–78; evolution of field, 27; importance of emotions in neural regulation, 7, 217–18; and language, 195–201; neural maps, 51–55 (see also maps, mapping); neural plasticity, xi, 26–28, 56–58, 60–62, 190–91, 194, 199, 202; neurological difficulties analyzed in terms of functional systems, 27; reality of affective unconscious, 87; resistance to attempts to reconcile psychoanalytic theory and philosophy with neuroscience, x, 81. See also body-mind connection; brain; brain damage; homeostasis; specific philosophers and neuroscientists
neuroscience-psychoanalysis relationship, xi–xii, 28–29; connection/overlap of neuroscience and psychoanalysis, 194–95, 200–202, 204–5, 213–14; and language, 194–95; neuropsychoanalysis, Anglo-American, xi–xii, 28–29, 80–81, 165, 183, 200 (see also Solms, Mark); neuro-psychoanalysis, new conception of, xv, 188, 198, 204; and problem of unconscious affects, 80–81; and resistance to attempts to reconcile psychoanalytic theory with neuroscience, 81
neurosis. See guilt; hysteria; obsessive disorders
New Introductory Lectures on Psycho-Analysis (Freud), 101
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 48, 192
object: consciousness as awareness of a disturbance caused by an external object, 30; and joyful and sorrowful affects, 39–40; space of encounter between thought and its object, 45; and wonder, 16–17, 40–41
obsessive disorders, 88–89, 98–99, 103, 152–53
Of Grammatology (Derrida), 21
ontological phenomena: and Damasio’s and Deleuze’s differing readings of Spinoza, 36; ontological generosity, 24–25, 64; and self-preservation, 54–55
organism, 217; body maps and capacity for feeling, 167; and consciousness, 188–89; and debate between naturalism and antinaturalism, 182; joy and sorrow as states of equilibrium/disequilibrium, 54; and mortality, 223–24; as term encompassing both mind and body, 55. See also body-mind connection; homeostasis
pain, 65–66, 166–67
PANIC emotional system, 186, 189
Panksepp, Jaak, xviii, 182, 190–94; denial of compartmentalized anatomical brain loci, 176–77; differences between cognition and emotion, 194; and imprecise vocabulary for affects, 199; Kant and, 190–91; and the protoself, 222; taxonomy of seven primary emotions, 186–87, 201
The Parallax View (Žižek), 162–63, 172, 179, 181
Pascal, Blaise, 83
passions: Descartes and, 12–18, 45–46; external signs of, 45–48; generous people as masters of their passions, 18; passions “in” the soul as consequences of bodily movements, 13–15; passions “of” the soul as related to the soul alone, 15–16; passions “of” the soul defined, 6; and pineal gland, 14–16; primitive and derived passions, 12; Spinoza’s critique of Descartes, 35, 37–38; wonder as first of six primitive passions (Descartes’ concept), 9. See also generosity; wonder
The Passions of the Soul (Descartes), 9, 12–18, 21–22, 30, 47–48, 85
passivity. See activity and passivity
perceptions: adequate and inadequate perceptions, 44; and body-mind connection, 53, 166–67; and the brain, 27; Deleuze and, 67; Descartes and, 14–15; generosity as a perception directed at the self, 18; McDowell and, 86; Spinoza and, 53; as type of passion “in” the soul, 14–15
personality transformation due to brain damage, xiii–xiv, 57–61
phallus, 159–61
Phantoms in the Brain (Ramachandran), 27
philosophy, Continental. See Deleuze, Gilles; Derrida, Jacques; Descartes, René; Spinoza, Baruch
philosophy, theoretical vs. practical, xv, 77
pineal gland, 14–16, 21–23
plane of immanence, 45–46, 53, 54, 64, 67
plasticity of the brain, xi, 26–28, 56–58, 60–62, 190–91, 194, 199, 202. See also brain damage
PLAY emotional system, 186
pleasure, 166–67, 218
pleasure principle, 77–78, 95, 187, 218
politics, 77, 98
Pommier, Gérard, 192
Pontalis, Jean-Bertrand, 102, 136–37, 213
power of acting, 38–40, 41–42, 53
power of existing, 6. See also force of existing
preconscious, 69, 78, 205
pride, 18
primordial affect, 24, 31
principle of inertia, 218
Project for a Scientific Psychology (Freud), 102
protoself, 31–32, 169–72, 217, 219–20, 222–23
psyche, x, 11, 28; and autoaffection, 31, 70; and brain damage, 57, 61–62, 71–72; Descartes and, 45; Freud’s city of Rome analogy for psyche, 60–61; interacting layers of, 198; spatiality of, 64, 69–70. See also body-mind connection; brain; consciousness; Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis; Freudian metapsychology of affects; id-ego-superego triad; Lacan-inspired metapsychology of affects; self; soul; subjectivity
psychic events (Freud’s conception), 28–29, 71
psychoanalysis, clinical practice of, xii, xiv–xv, 76; and brain damage, xiv; and deception, 207–8; doubts raised about affects during analysis, 140–41, 147–48, 151–52; and free association, 142–43; Lacan’s insistence upon cognitive structures as central object of analysis, 124; and Lacan’s lalangue neologism, 141–45; Lacan’s objections to affective life as primary focus of analysis, 120–21; Lacan’s theory of the four discourses (analyst, master, university, hysteric), 139–41, 147; and psychopathologies/psychosis, xiv–xv
psychoanalysis-neuroscience relationship. See neuroscience-psychoanalysis relationship
psychoanalytic theory of affects, 4; resistance to attempts to reconcile psychoanalytic theory with neuroscience, 81. See also affects, unconscious; defense mechanisms; feelings, misfelt; Freud, Sigmund; Freudian-Lacanian psychoanalysis; Freudian metapsychology of affects; guilt; id-ego-superego triad; Lacan, Jacques; Lacan-inspired metapsychology of affects; unconscious
psychopathologies, xiv
psychosis, xiv–xv
The Psychopathology of Everyday Life (Freud), xiii
pudeur, 82, 157–62
Pulver, Sydney, 113–17
RAGE emotional system, 186
Ramachandran, V. S., 27
rationality, 7–8, 30, 44, 50
reality: and deceptive nature of signifiers, 206–7; Lacan and, 139
religion, 203–4
remorse, 98–99
Repräsentanz, 107, 125–32, 136–37
representation: and confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32; symbolic activity in the brain, 213–14, 216, 219–23. See also ideas; ideational representations; language; signifiers
repression: and confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32; Copjec and, 155; Damasio and, 168–69; displacement of affect as result of, 155, 212; and drives, 215; Freud and, 105–10, 125–26; Green and, 205; Lacan and, 122, 125–34, 138, 155; and memory, 168; primary repression and secondary repression/repression proper, 125–26, 138
respect, 18
Sacks, Oliver, 27, 71
sadness. See sorrow
Sartre, Jean-Paul, xi
schizophrenia, xiv–xv
SEEKING emotional system, 186, 201
self: and Deleuzian conception of autoaffection, 45; feelings and concern for self-attachment, 51, 59–60; and homeostatic regulation, 217–22; impaired sense of, 33, 58–60 (see also brain damage); self-mapping in the brain, 164–67; self-model and a new conception of materialism, 72; sense of self as state of the organism, 223; and storytelling, 223; structure of (Damasio’s conception), 31–33, 169–72, 217, 219–20, 222–23; structure of (Freud’s conception of consciousness, preconscious, unconscious), 69–70, 78; structure of (Freud’s conception of id, ego, and superego), 69–70, 78; Žižek’s critique of Damasio’s conception, 169–74. See also brain damage; consciousness; identity; personality; psyche; soul; subjectivity
self-preservation, 51–54. See also conatus; homeostasis
self-touching, 221; and definition of autoaffection, 19–21, 63; Deleuze and, 45; Derrida and, 21–24, 64, 69; and Nancy’s nonmetaphysical sense of touch, 23–24; self-touching you, 20, 23–24, 64; and spatiality of the psyche, 69. See also autoaffection
Sellars, Wilfrid, 86
senti-ment (Lacan’s neologism), 141, 146–47, 213
sexuality, 159–61, 214–15
shame, 153–62; and beauty, 160–61; distinction between honte and pudeur, 82, 157–62
signifiers: affects as, 205–10; affects as aftereffects of interactions of signifiers, 123, 135; cross-resonating relations between multiple representations, 128–29; deceptive nature of, 206–9; dichotomy between the signifier and jouissance, 155; and diplomat metaphor, 130–31; existence in sets of two or more, 128–29, 208–9; Green and, 205; and inextricable entanglement of the affective and the intellectual, 121–22; priority of signifier-ideas over affects, 122–24; and repression, 119, 122, 128–30, 155; Saussure and, 208–9; two-way modulation between affects and signifiers, 200; and the unconscious, 84, 122, 208, 212; Vorstellungen as, 119, 122, 129; and Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, 127–28
sleep, 61–62, 93
Soler, Colette, 82, 141
Solms, Mark, 27–29, 57–58, 71, 186, 200–202, 228n6
somatic markers, theory of, 7
sorrow: as one of six primitive passions (Descartes’ idea), 9, 12; Spinoza’s definition, 39, 54; and states of functional disequilibrium, 54; and variability of conatus, 39–40
soul: activity and passivity of, 15, 22–23; functions of, 15; and generosity, 18; Green and, 203; passions “in” vs. passions “of,” 12–18; passions “of” the soul as related to the soul alone, 15–16; and perception, 15; and pineal gland, 14–16, 21–23; and spatiality, 21–23; as two-sided instance (speaker/listener etc.), 20; and wonder, 9–11, 18. See also autoaffection; body-mind connection; consciousness; existence; mind; psyche; self; subjectivity; specific philosophers
spatiality, 21–23, 46, 64. See also maps, mapping; plane of immanence
Spinoza, Baruch, xvi; and active affect/autoaffection, 45; activity and passivity, 37–41; adequate and inadequate causes, 37; affects and variability of conatus, 37–41; affects as always affects of essence, 35–36, 43–44; affects as natural ontological phenomena, 36; critique of Descartes’ theory of passions, 35; definition of affects as modifications of the power of existing, 6; definition of affects related to the body’s power of activity, 37, 41–42; definition of joy and sorrow, 39, 54; Descartes-Spinoza conflict, 7, 37–38; lack of knowledge of neurobiology, 54; mind and body as expressions of the same substance, 36, 37, 51; mind as the idea of the body, 51, 53; and Nature/God/Being, 36, 53; and power of acting, 38–41, 53; as protobiologist, 50, 52; Solms and, 200–201; three kinds of knowledge/ideas, 44–45, 66–67; translation of affectio and affectus, 4–5; and wonder, 8–10, 40–41. See also Damasio’s reading of Spinoza; Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza
Stanovich, Keith, 182
Studies on Hysteria (Freud and Breuer), 213–14
subject, xvi; and absence of emotions and feeling, 8, 11 (see also affects, detachment from/absence of); and conceptual personae, 48; and definition of autoaffection, 5–6; and heteroaffection, xvi, 7; and icons, 49; Kant on, 5–6. See also autoaffection
subjectivity, xvi–xvii; biological basis of, 55; and brain damage, xiii–xiv, 28, 33–34, 58; and cerebral autoaffection, 223; and denaturalization, 172–74, 178, 180–84, 187–88, 202; disembodiment of, 29–30; Kant and, 170; Lacan’s barred subject ($), 151, 169–74, 187, 200; and language, 200 (see also language); and misfelt feelings, 86 (see also feelings, misfelt); neural subjectivity as a plastic structure, 26–28; and new conception of materialism, 72; and “self-touching you,” 64; and time, 6; wonder and the structure of the self, 32–33; and Žižek’s critique of Damasio’s conception of the self, 169–72. See also consciousness; mind; psyche; self; soul; specific philosophers, psychoanalysts, and neuroscientists
superego: and civilization, 97–98; distinguished from conscience, 92; Freud’s introduction of concept, 78; and moral masochism, 95–97; sadism of, 95–96, 98; and spatiality of the psyche, 69; structural dynamics between ego and superego, 92–93, 99–101; and unconscious guilt, 88, 91, 99–101, 212–13
syncope, 23–24
thought: and Deleuzian conception of autoaffection and “maps,” 45; and free association, 142–43, 166; Freud’s primary and secondary processes, 143–45; Lacan and, 138–39, 142–43; and perceptions, 166–67. See also cognition; ideational representations
Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Nietzsche), 48
time, and autoaffection, 6, 20
touch, 66–67; and activity and passivity of the soul, 22–23; Deleuze and, 66–67; Derrida and, 21–24; Nancy’s nonmetaphysical sense of touch, 23–24; “touching-touched” relationship between me and myself (Merleau-Ponty’s schema), 66, 67. See also self-touching
On Touching (Derrida), 21, 64–65, 68
Turnbull, Oliver, 27–28, 186, 201–2
unconscious: and the brain, 71, 219–21; and conscience, 78–79, 91–92; Damasio and, 163–68, 179–80; and death, 223; and defense mechanisms, 104–10, 124 (see also repression); discovery as revolutionary breakthrough, 83–84, 148–49; distinction between psychoanalytic unconscious and term as used in neuroscience, 177–78; Freud and (see Freud, Sigmund; Freudian metapsychology of affects); and id-ego-superego triad, 78–80, 92–93, 99–101; Lacan and, 82–83, 108, 119, 124–44, 155, 179–80, 208; and lalangue neologism, 143–45; LeDoux and, 188; as negative term for a positive x, 209; Panksepp and, 188; and personal identity, 92; and potential-to-feel, 108–9; repression and the confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32; slips of the tongue, jokes, etc., 143, 196; and spatiality of the psyche, 69–70; unconscious sense of guilt (see guilt); and Vorstellungen as signifiers, 122. See also affects, unconscious
“unpleasure principle,” 187
virtue, 17–18, 41
vision, 62
Vorstellungen: confusion caused by translations of Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, Vorstellung, and Repräsentanz, 125–32, 136–37; Green and, 205; and inextricable entanglement of the affective and the intellectual, 121–22; as Lacan’s signifiers, 119, 122, 129; and lalangue neologism, 143; and obsessive disorders, 90; and the unconscious, 122. See also ideational representations
Vorstellungsrepräsentanz, 125–32, 136–37
warfare, 132
What Is Philosophy? (Deleuze), 43, 48, 67
wonder, xv–xvi, 225n10; and alterity, 10; as ambivalent affect, 64; and autoaffection, 9–11, 63–64; and brain damage, 11, 33, 60; Damasio and, 11, 32–33, 64; deconstruction of, 10–11; defined, 8–9, 16; Deleuze and, 64, 71; Deleuze’s reading of Descartes and, 47–48; Derrida and, 11, 23–25, 64, 71; Descartes and, 8–9, 12, 16–18, 25; and facial expressions, 47–48; and fear, 9; function of, 17; and generosity, 17–18, 24–25; and heteroaffection, 9, 11, 63–64; impaired capacity for, 10–11, 17, 33, 60, 64; as intermediary between passion and thought, 47; Lacan and, 70–71; nonjudgmental nature of, 17, 18; as source driving philosophizing, 77; Spinoza and, 8–10, 40–41; and the structure of the self, 32–33; and virtue, 41
Žižek, Slavoj: critique of Damasio, 169–74, 179–84, 190; and debate between naturalism and antinaturalism, 180–84, 190; LeDoux and, 174–79, 190; life 2.0, life 1.0, 172–73, 192–94, 197–98; and misfelt feelings, 141
Žižeks Ontology: A Transcendental Materialist Theory of Subjectivity (Johnston), 170
zoē, 192–93