This book employs history to illuminate questions of policy and politics which still have resonance now. It aims to make visible some of the threads by which the past is connected with the present. It does so by bringing to light the first debates, which occurred in the late eighteenth century, about the possibility of a world without poverty. These arguments were no longer about Utopia in an age-old sense. They were inspired by a new question: whether scientific and economic progress could abolish poverty, as traditionally understood. Some of the difficulties encountered were eerily familiar. Many of the problems which politicians and journalists imagine to have arisen in the world only recently – globalisation, financial regulation, downsizing and commercial volatility – were already in the eighteenth century objects of recurrent concern.
It is of course true that the world in which discussion of these issues first arose was very different from our own. It was dominated by the revolutions of 1776 in America and 1789 in France, as well as by the first movements to overcome slavery and empire. The arguments discussed in this book took place in a period which witnessed the overturning of ancient forms of sovereignty across Europe, direct assaults upon monarchy, aristocracy and church, crises of religious belief, the emergence of ‘the common people’ as an independent political force, and a war fought across all the oceans of the world.
But to a greater degree than we are prone to imagine, those upheavals and their legacy are still relevant to us. Our conceptions of the economy, both national and international, and its relationship to political processes are still in some ways shaped by the conflicts discussed in this book. So are the relationships between religion, citizenship and economic life. Those who doubt the relevance of history because they believe that the world was made anew by the defeat of Communism, the end of the Cold War, and the demise of socialism at the beginning of the 1990s, do not escape its hold. They simply become the guileless consumers of its most simple-minded reconstructions. Those who devised the new reform programmes of post-socialist parties, desperate to remove any residue of an old-fashioned and discredited collectivism, hastened to embrace a deregulated economy hopefully moralised by periodic homilies about communitarian sentiment. By doing this, they imagined themselves to be buying into an unimpeachable and up-to-date liberal tradition handed down in a distinguished lineage of economists and philosophers inspired by the laisser faire libertarianism of Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations.
This book reveals that such assumptions are at best dubious and, for the most part, false. The free market individualism of American conservatives and the moral authoritarianism which often accompanies it are not the products of Smith (although they certainly draw selectively upon certain of his formulations), but of the recasting of political economy in the light of the frightened reaction to the republican radicalism of the French Revolution.
Smith’s analyses of ‘moral sentiments’ and commercial society were not the exclusive possession of any one political tendency. The battle to appropriate his mantle was closely intertwined with the battle over the French Revolution itself. Modern commentators are agreed that Smith was not in any distinctive or meaningful sense a Christian, while those who wrote about him at the time strongly suspected it; worse still, at least for contemporaries, the evidence provided by his revisions to the 1790 edition of The Theory of Moral Sentiments, which he had originally written in 1759, suggested that at the end of his life he was even less of a Christian than before. This was not merely a minor or incidental quirk in Smith’s picture of the world, it informed his fundamental conception of human motivation as well as his theory of history. In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith wrote of the ambition which drove on ‘the poor man’s son’ to strive to become rich and, if successful, to advertise his newfound status by procuring ‘mere trinkets of frivolous utility’. After a disquisition on the impossibility of translating wealth into happiness, Smith concluded:
Power and riches appear then to be, what they are, enormous and operous machines contrived to produce a few trifling conveniences to the body, consisting of springs the most nice and delicate, which must be kept in order with the most anxious attention, and which in spite of all our care are ready every moment to burst into pieces, and crush in their ruins their unfortunate possessor.
Nevertheless, he continued, ‘It is well that nature imposes on us in this manner. It is this deception which rouses and keeps in continual motion the industry of mankind.’1
The idea that some kind of trick or self-deception was the basic motivating factor behind human activity, but that it was nevertheless to be cherished – because it explained why mankind was induced to ‘found cities and commonwealths, and to invent and improve all the sciences and arts, which ennoble and embellish human life’ – was difficult to integrate either into Christianity or into what in the years after 1789 was presented as a post-Christian republican alternative. Smith’s picture derived from classical sources, part stoic and part epicurean. It sat ill with Christian evangelicalism. Nor did it accord well with counter- or post-revolutionary apologias for aristocracies, merchants, established churches, low wages or the outlawing of combinations of labourers. But then nor could it be said to endorse republicanism, egalitarianism, democratic representation or the toppling of aristocracies. Supporters and opponents of the Revolution, therefore, annexed different parts of Smith’s picture of commercial society to support rival visions of social and political life.
This story of the bifurcation of Smith’s legacy is relevant to the present. On the one side, anti-republicans married a version of Smith to a bleak possessive individualism underpinned by Christian evangelical theology. This authoritarian but anti-paternalist philosophy was elaborated into what became known in Britain as ‘liberal Toryism’ and it remained dominant in the ‘Treasury view’ of economic and welfare policy from the aftermath of the battle of Waterloo down to the criticisms of Keynes and the end of the gold standard in 1931.2 In modified form, parts of it have survived and continue today in the neo-conservative ethos of American Republicanism.
One extreme bred another. It was this conservative and anti-utopian transformation of political economy which in turn produced by way of reaction the genesis of revolutionary socialism. Especially influential was Malthus’s Essay on the Principle of Population of 1798. The population theory provided the main bulwark against further attempts to enlarge the framework of collective welfare provision for around a century. Furthermore, its replacement, both in economic theory and in social policy of a language of civil society and political participation by a language of ‘natural forces’, legitimated and institutionalised a fear and suspicion of the ‘labouring poor’ which the reaction against the Revolution had already done so much to intensify.
For conservatives, the Revolution was almost from the beginning a demonstration of the fallacy of ignoring the primacy of the passions over reason in human affairs. In the course of the 1790s, this outlook, deeply rooted in Christian assumptions about original sin, was translated into the terms made available by the Newtonian language of natural theology and was extended into the sphere of sexual gratification. By treating reproduction as a biological imperative and the primal driving force behind the activities of the mass of humanity, past, present and future, Malthus subordinated all history, law and culture to an instinctual non-social and ahistorical force. Once this conception had been implanted at the heart of political economy, the core of economics was henceforth situated in the realm of nature. It was for this reason that a crude behavioural approach to human psychology came to be considered the appropriate method in the development of economic theory.
What this ignored was the fact that observed regularities in the process of production, consumption and exchange, far from belonging to nature, were only possible when such transactions were regulated according to law and custom. It was for this reason that Hegel, who was a careful reader of Smith, treated the emergence of ‘civil society’ and the formalisation of its anatomy in political economy as distinctive products of the modern world. For ‘civil society’ presupposed a set of legal and cultural norms within which a ‘system of needs’ could develop. It presupposed the overthrow of the violence and arbitrariness of slavery and feudalism.
In Germany, Hegel’s optimistic and moderately progressive picture of civil society was also pushed on to the defensive by a combination of fundamentalist pietism, aristocratic reaction, possessive individualism and a romantic reassertion of the divine right of monarchy.3 Marx’s redescription of Hegel’s conception of civil society, what he called ‘the capitalist mode of production’, also therefore drew more upon Malthus than upon Smith and Hegel in its depiction of the economy. The economy was depicted as an arena in which man had become dominated by his own creations and had reverted to a language of ‘natural forces’ to describe his relations with his fellow beings. As Marx wrote to Engels about The Origin of the Species in 1862:
It is remarkable how Darwin rediscovers, among the beasts and plants, the society of England with its division of labour, competition, opening up of new markets, ‘inventions’ and Malthusian ‘struggle for existence’. It is Hobbes’ bellum omnium contra omnes [the struggle of all against all] and is reminiscent of Hegel’s Phenomenology in which civil society figures as an ‘intellectual animal kingdom’, whereas, in Darwin, the animal kingdom figures as civil society.4
Thus, both in the dominant language of political economy and, perversely, in what was to become the most influential critique of political economy, a strange consensus conspired to push the legal, institutional and cultural dimensions of the analysis of commercial society to the margins.
Could there have been an alternative to this conservative trajectory and the revolutionary communism it provoked in response? What of the use that the republican supporters of enlightenment and the Revolution, Antoine-Nicolas Condorcet and Thomas Paine, made of Smith and other advances in the eighteenth-century moral and social sciences, to form the social underpinnings of a viable republic? As this book makes clear in its discussion of the reaction to the proposals of Condorcet and Paine in anti-Jacobin England and post-Jacobin France, such an alternative was virtually smothered at birth. Even when its protagonists were not literally burnt in effigy – as Paine was all over England in the early 1790s – or pushed like Condorcet to a premature death, their proposals were radically misrepresented. Nor was there a strong constituency pushing for such policies among those supporting the ideals of the Revolution. Moderates simply hoped that post-1789 France would resemble post-1688 England. But among those still pressing for reform at home, Smith was henceforward harnessed together with Malthus. Those who seriously questioned this equation were relegated to a romantic twilight zone beyond the pale of respectable economics. Conversely, for those on the left of the Revolution, the proposals associated with Paine and Condorcet were considered too respectful of commerce and private property to be of use. Nor did the situation greatly improve in the two centuries following 1789. The tax and welfare policies of Condorcet and Paine, when not wholly forgotten, were only recalled as oddities of no programmatic relevance. Later proposals for national insurance and old age pensions drew upon other sources of inspiration and were designed to attain different political aims.
In the twentieth century, the tradition which pushed the interpretation of Smith rightwards, from Hayek to Himmelfarb, built up a strong and elaborate case resting, among other things, upon an old-fashioned respect for historical scholarship.5 By contrast, the left, which was reluctantly forced to retreat from Marxism, often seems drawn towards the abandonment of any detailed engagement with the historical terrain at all. Its preoccupation with what it likes to call ‘the enlightenment project’ has generally been of a distant and condescending kind, largely uninterested in the detailed political and cultural disagreements that arose between those covered by the term. By making knowledge itself the enemy of progress, this approach has closed off historical curiosity and has deprived progressive currents in contemporary political debate of a usable and honourable historical tradition upon which to build.
In this book, by contrast, I will argue that the moment of convergence between the late Enlightenment and the ideals of a republican and democratic revolution was a fundamental historical turning point. However brief its appearance, however vigorously it was thereafter repressed, it marked the beginning of all modern thought about poverty. Neo-conservative historiography belittles the importance of this episode in the history of social thought as little more than an eccentric tinkering with Poor Law reform. Old left historiography minimises its significance because it is still fixated upon the ‘bourgeois’ limitations of such programmes. Post-Marxist parlance, on the other hand, condemns it for its supposed equation between knowledge, power and emancipation, or for its imagined epistemic inadequacies on questions of race, class or gender.
What was new about this revolutionary moment at the end of the eighteenth century was the realisation that there need no longer be such thing as ‘the poor’. This in turn was a product of the new conditions of the eighteenth century. After the bitter and protracted conflicts unleashed by the religious and civil wars of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the eighteenth century was the first period in which the populations of many European countries experienced prolonged periods of internal peace. It was the first time, therefore, that observers were in a position to discern an underlying pattern, rhythm or system to economic life, a pattern that was relatively distinct from the bellicose politics – military, commercial and imperial – of the courts and aristocracies of Europe. This was the context in which, for the first time, contemporaries could begin to discuss the meaning and implications of living in a commercial society, or what would now be called ‘capitalism’.
Across Europe, the period between the late seventeenth and the early nineteenth centuries witnessed an increase in market-oriented activity on such a scale that economic historians have called it ‘the industrious revolution’. The imperatives of commercial society reached into the poorest cottage. Leisure time declined, as the attractions of a money income or the necessity for it increased. Domestic production was increasingly devoted to marketed goods and no longer to goods or services directly consumed within the household. Seasons of under-employment in marginal agricultural areas were increasingly absorbed by spinning, weaving or other manufacturing activities in what used to be called ‘the putting-out system’, or more recently ‘protoindustry’. There was a substantial increase in the market-oriented labour of women and children. The pace and intensity of work increased.6
In such a society, the afflictions regularly attending the lifecycle of wage and salary earners became clearly visible. For the first time, such afflictions could be seen to form part of a pattern which pre-existed the peculiarities of temperament or behaviour of particular individuals. This sense of a pattern was the product of a prolonged period of internal peace, of the rule of law, of growing prosperity, and of the relatively uninterrupted development of economic activity. As a result, habitual attitudes towards the poor had begun to become dislodged.
As far back as the end of the seventeenth century, the difference in prosperity between the English economy and any other in the world had been noted by John Locke. Modern nations, even if poor in resources, could feed their populations without resort to conquest, thanks to the increasing productivity of the land. According to Locke: ‘There cannot be a clearer demonstration than that American tribes who possess unlimited land, but no private property, have not one hundredth part of the Conveniences we enjoy.’ A king of one their large territories ‘feeds, lodges and is clad worse than a day labourer in England’. The same point was reiterated by Smith at the beginning of The Wealth of Nations.7
But if commercial society were associated with a progressive improvement in the conditions of life and a greater chance of bettering one’s condition, it came at a cost. The cost of enjoying the opportunities offered by this more volatile world was the willingness to live with chance. The afflictions which individuals had to face were not confined to the ups and downs of the lifecycle. There would also be those ‘constantly thrown off from the revolutions of that wheel which no man can stop nor regulate, a number connected with commerce and adventure’.8 The ever-changing development of the division of labour and the expansion of the market meant that no person’s employment could be considered wholly secure. In the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, as the development of this market became ever more extensive, shifts in the international division of labour meant that thousands of families could lose their principal source of livelihood overnight.
Finally, there was what has come to be known as ‘the vision thing’, which, as most political observers are aware, is always prone to become more expansive in times of revolution. As a result of 1776 and 1789, references to the ‘people’ could no longer ignore or evade questions about representation, democracy or equality, while the rich were reminded that their hegemony was provisional and contingent. Politically, the effect of the American and French Revolutions was to dislodge or undermine early modern commonplaces about the place of the poor in the social hierarchy. Instead, there emerged the beginnings of a language of social security as a basis of citizenship.
In this new approach, there was no such thing as poverty; there was no such entity as ‘the poor’. In their place, there were ‘a great number of individuals almost entirely dependent for the maintenance of themselves and their families either on their own labour or on the interest from capital invested so as to make their labour more productive’.9 Such individuals encountered difficulties in the course of their lives, some predictable, some unforeseen. Some individuals were afflicted by disability from the beginning; some were disabled by accident, violence or war. Breadwinners died prematurely or became chronically sick. In old age – and now even more in extreme old age – individuals could no longer earn their living, and so were likely to need increasing amounts of care. In many instances, their families were no longer able to help them; or they might have lost what families they once had. The care of children before they were able to contribute to the livelihood of the household could also become onerous. It could be measured particularly in the temporary loss of the earnings of one of the parents, or alternatively in the cost of child care and schooling. Then again, economic misfortune might strike, not because a breadwinner died, but because marriages broke down or a partner suffered desertion. Throughout recorded history the phenomenon of the single-parent family has reappeared at the forefront of every investigation of poverty, too often to the surprise of investigators expecting to find something darker or more sinister at its unromantic core.
These new ways of thinking about the traditional notion of poverty raised new questions. Should the welfare of the poor be left to the face-to-face ministrations of the charitable, or should it be assigned to the statutory but often punitive relief afforded by the Poor Laws? Should individuals be entrusted to exercise their own independent foresight and be prepared to pit their own modest resources unaided against the uncertainties of life? Or should the development of international markets be slowed down or limited through government control or protection? Should the abandonment of leadership implied in the term laisser faire be condemned and replaced by a new sense of interdependence between rich and poor reminiscent of what had once supposedly pertained in the feudal world? Should people attempt to create a new sense of spiritual community? Should chance be eliminated altogether through the establishment of ‘villages of cooperation’ or the formation of one large ‘association of the producers’? Or should governments attempt to live with chance, both national and international, but establish effective control over its effects through the universal and comprehensive adoption by their citizenry of a scheme of universal and comprehensive social insurance? As this book argues, such were the questions about poverty and its abolition which the era of the American and French Revolutions first raised – questions, or questions very like them, which are still with us today.