‘In full possession of my faculties, I declare you my depositary before all eternity, that you may bear witness to my act in centuries to come, when my posthumous works and correspondence with Franca are published.’1
’We do not publish our own drafts, that is, our own mistakes, but we do sometimes publish other people’s … Marx did not publish the famous – alas – ‘1844 Manuscripts’ on philosophy and political economy … he did not even publish The German Ideology … though it is a crucially important text for us (nor did he publish the Theses on Feuerbach, our alpha and omega).’2
All Althusser lies in the gap between these two strictly contemporaneous texts; even, indeed, in the gap at the heart of the second. The thesis about the ‘break’ that was to make him famous was based on a meticulous study of Marx’s early works: his personal copy of the 1844 Manuscripts constitutes an impressive archival document in itself. Yet he sometimes regretted that these works had been published, occasionally even going so far as to deplore the fact that they had been written. As to the eventual fate of his own unpublished writings, if it is impossible to speak of any intention of Althusser’s in this connection, he was incontestably no stranger to the idea of posthumous publication.
Althusser certainly had sharply mixed feelings about his own work. He never disavowed his early writings. Thus he authorized the belated republication in Spanish of ‘A Matter of Fact’,3 a text his French readers would not get to see. He built up a myth, for those close to him, around his long letter to Jean Lacroix, but never showed them the letter itself. On the other hand, he did let a few friends read his diatribe ‘On Conjugal Obscenity’ in the 1970s, adding a complementary text ‘on the woman question’ to it in 1978. He kept his master’s thesis on Hegel secreted away, but felt the need to declare in 1963 that Merleau-Ponty had wanted to publish it.4 Moreover, not long after the publication of For Marx and Reading Capital, he invented what might be called texts with semi-public status, which he had typed and mimeographed by a secretary at the École normale supérieure for wide distribution to those around him. These texts had so powerful an impact that the criticisms Jacques Rancière later levelled at him5 were largely based on one of them, written in 1965: ‘Theory, Theoretical Practice, and Theoretical Formation: Ideology and Ideological Struggle’, a text still unavailable in France, though it was published in Latin America.6 Althusser was likewise not averse to publishing anonymous texts, a practice he had already experimented with in the early 1950s, and resorted to again, rather successfully, in 1966, when he published an unsigned article entitled ‘On the Cultural Revolution’ in Cahiers marxistes-léninistes (nos 13–14). Finally, his projects to publish certain texts came so close to realization that it is no exaggeration to say that his publicly acknowledged work was several times on the point of moving in a direction utterly different from the one history tells us it ultimately did – for better or for worse.
Known for his brief, incisive texts, Althusser nevertheless wrote two manuals on Marxism-Leninism7 and another two on philosophy for non-philosophers,8 and it was only at the last moment that he withdrew a book announced in a note to his ‘Preface to Capital Volume One’:9 ‘cf. A Revolutionary Science: Introduction to Book I of Capital, Éditions Maspero, Paris, 1969’. What is more, he several times refused to send the page proofs of a text to the printer after he had corrected them. Thus French readers never had an opportunity to read ‘The Historical Task of Marxist Philosophy’, though this work saw partial publication in Hungarian10 after being commissioned, and then declined, by the Soviet journal Voprossi Filosofi in 1967; a paste-up found in Althusser’s archives indicates that it had been slated for publication in his collection Théorie. Similarly, the fifth ‘Philosophy Course for Scientists’, which was to have been published in the Revue de l’enseignement philosophique in 1968 or 1969, well before the other four, ultimately went unpublished, and was not included in Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of Scientists in 1974.11 If Althusser does not seem to have regretted the fact that these texts did not appear in print, the same cannot be said of his ‘Machiavelli and Us’ (written between 1972 and 1976), as is shown by a letter of 28 May 1986 to his Mexican publisher Arnaldo Ofrila Reynal, director of the publishing house Siglo XXI.12 It is certainly strange to note the imbalance between the nine, often short, books Althusser published in French in his lifetime, and the thousands of pages discovered in his archives – including the typescripts of some ten books, many of them containing instructions for the printer. It is even stranger that his voluminous correspondence, all the more complete in that he generally kept copies of his own letters, contains virtually no mention of his reasons for abandoning any of his publication plans. His illness, the exacerbated attention he paid to the political conjuncture, and the often contradictory advice he received from friends he asked to read his texts all have something to do with this reluctance to publish; but we are doubtless also entitled to see in it the mark of the aleatory.*
The present volume offers a selection of texts drawn from Althusser’s prolific output. It was put together on principles that are by definition subjective. We have privileged texts which, in subject-matter, style, or content, diverge from the already well-known books and essays; hence we have given relatively small space to writings that tend merely to ring changes on familiar themes. Moreover, out of a concern for readability, we have opted to leave out the manuals on Marxism and philosophy.13 Often written in a style that pays heavy tribute to the notion Althusser then had of the demands of the theoretical conjuncture, these manuals have ironically not stood the test of time as well as earlier works. Finally, although the two volumes of the Écrits philosophiques et politiques are made up almost exclusively of hitherto unpublished material, a wish to offer the reader coherent groupings of texts has led us to reprint a few already published essays, which are either completely unknown or else have gone largely unnoticed.
The first [French] volume has been organized chronologically; the organizing principle of the second is essentially thematic. We could hardly have broken up the group of texts on art, or those on the history of philosophy which Althusser wrote for courses he gave in different periods; accordingly, these texts appear in the second volume. On the other hand, the early writings, whatever their themes, must be read together: though it would have been possible to group the 1947 master’s thesis on Hegel with the writings on the history of philosophy, the other texts of the period shed a great deal more light on it.
The internal organization of this first volume rests on a very simple principle. A political-philosophical subject named ‘Althusser’ emerged in the course of the 1960s, becoming, with the publication of For Marx and Reading Capital in 1965, one of the major poles of reference of intellectual life in France and elsewhere. A product, like many others in Gaullist France, of converging factors that seemingly had as little to do with one another as the advent of structuralism, the rediscovery of epistemology, the highly problematic repercussions of de-Stalinization on the French Communist Party, the Sino-Soviet split, the emergence of the student movement, and, let us not forget, the Catholic past and very special psychological make-up of an individual ensconced in an École normale supérieure that was forced to invent new strategies to compete successfully with other institutions, this subject would, as such, disappear during the events of May 1968. The philosopher’s celebrity remained intact, and there was no sudden drop in his theoretical production. But the world had changed; certain ruptures had been consummated. Althusser served notice of his new situation by publishing, for the first time, an article in L’Humanité, the main organ of the French Communist Party.14 If there had indubitably been an Althusserian school before this date, it had now practically ceased to exist.
The object of the present [French] volume is to introduce readers to, or, at least, afford them an opportunity to become better acquainted with, Althusser’s output in the years preceding and following the 1960s;† the general contours of his development in the 1960s are already familiar. Althusser’s early works, written between 1946 and 1951 by a subject still in the process of emerging, undeniably correspond to a precise moment in his evolution, one marked by a double transition: from Hegel to Marx and from Catholicism to Communism. These texts make up the first part of the present volume [entitled, in the original French edition, ‘Louis Althusser before Althusser’]. As to the 1970s, they were extremely problematic years. Althusser was still a figure to be reckoned with; his writings were cited more frequently than ever, at least in the first half of the decade, and he was publishing texts seemingly very sure of their foundations, among them the 1972 Reply to John Lewis, in which he defined philosophy as ‘class struggle in the field of theory’.15 But, below the surface, profound changes were underway. Althusser’s unpublished work was in fact highly variegated: a new subject was trying to make himself heard at the cost of provoking a generalized crisis of which only a few publications provide even a glimpse.16 Because the specificity of this new Althusser has, for the most part, gone largely unnoticed, the second part of the present [French] volume, entitled ‘Texts of Crisis’, has been given over to him. When Althusser killed his wife on 16 November 1980, he ceased to be a political-philosophical subject for good and all. Beyond the continuities with his earlier work, his often strange texts on aleatory materialism constitute the final moment of his theoretical activity, a moment inseparable from a renewed preoccupation with the question of his own first name:17 ‘Louis Althusser after Althusser’.‡
French philosophy in the post-war period was profoundly marked by Hegel, little read since the nineteenth century. To be sure, important essays had occasionally been devoted to him earlier in the twentieth century:18 Jean Wahl published Le Malheur de la conscience dans la philosophic de Hegel in 1929,19 together with a translation of selected passages from the Phenomenology of Spirit; Henri Lefebvre and Norbert Guterman, after publishing their Selections from the work of Karl Marx in 1934, edited an anthology of selections from Hegel in 1939;20 from 1933 to 1939, Alexandre Kojève gave a series of courses on the Phenomenology of Spirit at the École pratique des Hautes études, which were attended by a public with a brilliant future ahead of it.§ Yet none of this was enough to induce people actually to read Hegel. It was not until 1939 that Aubier undertook publication of the first full-length translation, by Jean Hyppolite, of the Phenomenology of Spirit, the second volume of which came off the presses in 1941; the Philosophy of Right and the Aesthetics appeared during the war under circumstances that were, to say the least, disagreeable.21 The Lectures on the Philosophy of History were published in 1945, followed, in 1947 and 1949, by the first French translation of the Science of Logic, by Samuel Jankélévitch; The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate, translated by Jacques Martin, to whom Althusser was to dedicate For Marx, was released by Vrin in 1948. Thus, in the space of a few years, Hegel’s major work was made available to the French public. Studies now began to mushroom. Two monuments emerged: Jean Hyppolite’s Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (1946),22 and Alexandre Kojève’s Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (1947).23 Among the other works to appear in this period were Father Henri Niel’s De la médiation dans la philosophie de Hegel.24 Untold articles on Hegel were published by Kojève, Hyppolite, numerous theologians, such as Rev. Father Fessard, and many others. In a context in which Karl Marx was also assuming central importance, the dialectic of master and slave, the struggle unto death, the for-itself and the in-itself, consciousness and self-consciousness, and the other and alienation were on everyone’s lips. Hegel was becoming familiar, if only by way of Sartre’s Being and Nothingness.
There is thus nothing astonishing about the fact that Althusser should have been working on Hegel in 1947. His master’s thesis25 is all the more solid because he was twenty-nine when he wrote it, an unusual age to be engaging in an academic exercise of this type: matured by the war and his experiences in a POW camp, the ‘young Althusser’ was no longer a young man. The volumes found in his library at his death show that, subsequent disclaimers notwithstanding, he had read Hegel with great care. He made extensive annotations in his copy of the Phenomenology, the Lectures on the Philosophy of History, and the Philosophy of Right, and he was plainly familiar with the old translation of the Encyclopædia by Véra;‖ he read Faith and Knowledge in German, along with The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy and the early theological writings – especially The Spirit of Christianity and its Fate, which he very probably discussed with Jacques Martin, then at work on a translation of it. If he knew The Science of Logic only imperfectly, he had nevertheless read the preface and the last chapter in German. Like most of those who have written about Hegel, he was captivated by his subject: not only did he write about Hegel, he was, incontestably, an Hegelian.
Althusser’s study of Hegel in this period was inseparable from his study of Marx, whom he devoured in Jacques Molitor’s translation.26 He did not altogether neglect Capital or the Histoire des doctrines économiques [Theories of Surplus-Value], a few volumes of which he annotated, although his interest in the Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy did not, in this period, go much beyond the 1859 Preface and the 1857 Introduction. However, he covered his copies of Marx’s Œuvres philosophiques with annotations, especially Philosophy and Political Economy (as the ’1844 Manuscripts’ were then called), The German Ideology and the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. His master’s thesis, informed by a historicism that is rather surprising for those who know his later works, describes the relations between Marx and Hegel in the following anything but unambiguous terms:
Yet Hegel clearly saw another point as well, one Marx neglects. How was one to think the essence of philosophy, that is, the alienation of thought, without becoming the prisoner of the essence of one’s own thinking?… As philosopher, Marx was thus a prisoner of his times and hence of Hegel, who had foreseen this captivity. In a sense, Marx succumbed to the necessity of the error he wished to retrace in Hegel, in that Hegel had exposed this necessity in the philosopher, while overcoming it in himself so as to engender the Sage. Marx’s error lay in not being a sage.27
We are inevitably reminded of this passage by the early Althusser when we read a work like ‘Marx in his Limits’.28
In Althusser’s case, the confrontation between Hegel and Marx was played out in the ideological context of a transition from Catholicism to Communism. Althusser’s Catholicism went back a long way; it did not always have a leftist bent.29 If his political positions changed radically after the war, he nevertheless continued to call himself a Catholic. Thus he took part in a journey to Rome and gave an account of it in Témoignage chrétien under the pseudonym Robert Leclos;30 he published a review of Georges Izard’s L’homme est révolutionnaire in the review Dieu vivant;31 and his article ‘The International of Decent Feelings’, which opens the present volume, was initially intended for publication in another Catholic review, Les Cahiers de notre jeunesse.
Althusser took an interest in the activities of two Catholic groups: the ‘Union of Progressive Christians’ [l’Union des Chrétiens progressistes] and ‘Youth of the Church’ [Jeunesse de l’Église]. Founded on the initiative of André Mandouze, the Union of Progressive Christians was politically very close to the Communist Party, which many of its members, including Maurice Caveing, Jean Chesneaux and François Ricci, would soon join. Although numerous documents connected with the group were preserved in his archives, Althusser did not really help shape its thinking: progressive Christians were doubtless too political in his view, and failed to establish a satisfactory link between their secular commitment and their faith. ‘Youth of the Church’32 was very different. In January 1936, the Dominican father Maurice Montuclard founded, in Lyons, a group he then called ‘The Community’; out of it would evolve a centre for religious studies, ‘Youth of the Church’, which from 1942 to 1949 published, among other things, ten Cahiers, including L’Incroyance des croyants [The Unbelief of Believers], Le Temps du Pauvre [The Time of the Poor Man], and L’Évangile captif [The Captive Gospel]. One of the paradoxes of Althusser’s evolution is that the moment he chose to join the Communist Party coincided with the period of his closest collaboration with this religious community, which settled in Petit-Clamart33 after the Liberation. The following passage by Maurice Montuclard, to whose anti-humanism Althusser was doubtless not indifferent, provides some idea of what might have brought Althusser to take this step:
It is of crucial importance to the Gospel and the Church that Christians cast off … the bonds of humanism and a civilization that was once Christian, and is now ‘bourgeois’; that they bring to today’s historical developments their active, lucid presence, and, with it, the influence and reality of grace. This entails … 1) A Christian vision of secular History which is distinct from the historical action of the Church visible, though never opposed to it, and is a progressive force to the extent that God chooses to make this vision too an instrument of Salvation in Jesus Christ. 2) A subordination of politics to religion, and, more broadly, of the temporal to the spiritual, different … from the kind of subordination authorized by Christianity’s post-medieval regime.34
Or, again, the following passage:
If we want the Christian message to be heard, we have to preach the Gospel – the Gospel, not Christian humanism. If we want people to believe in the Church, we have to present it, and consequently experience it, in such a way that it will show it is capable of relying on its own supernatural means, not superfluous human help, to bring a reborn humanity to life, liberty, fraternity, and the worship of the true God … A world is disappearing; as it falls, it is taking with it, along with our privileges and certitudes, all the sources of support the Church once fell back on to facilitate and promote its mission by human means. This world is disappearing in favour of a better humanity in a new civilization. How can we not wish that its fall will create new opportunities, as yet unknown but already certain, for the progress of evangelization? How can we not choose to free the Gospel of its trammels so as to pave the way, in this nascent world, for a Church wholly attuned to the freedom of the Gospel, and wholly based, in its teaching, methods, and institutions, on the sovereign power of grace? No, we no longer have a choice: we have chosen the Gospel.35
If Althusser, for his part, chose the Communist Party, Catholicism would never entirely cease to hold a place in his thinking: an article published in 1969 in the review Lumière et Vie bears witness to this,36 as does the transcription, made in 1985 and discovered in his archives, of a discussion he had with Father Stanislas Breton on the subject of liberation theology.37
It would have been surprising if Althusser had not been a Stalinist. No-one who joined the Communist Party in November 1948, as he did, and remained faithful to it as few others have, could have avoided it. His Stalinism, which was at all events predictable, is amply attested by his writings: the great post-war trials did not trouble him in the least, and he apparently entertained no doubts as to Rajk’s guilt.38 But, by itself, the adjective ‘Stalinist’ does not tell us much. There are different ways of being a Stalinist, and the history of the phenomenon cannot really be understood if one fails to recognize its diversity: the ‘Letter to Jean Lacroix’ probably has no equal. If Althusser indicates his agreement with Zhdanov’s lecture on philosophy,39 nowhere in his work does one find the least trace of a defence of socialist realism; yet the theory of socialist realism had itself been propounded by Zhdanov. Althusser took a close interest in the Lysenko affair, reading and annotating several propaganda pamphlets, and yet it is not easy to guess what he thought of it. Unlike, for example, Jean-Toussaint Desanti, then a member of the editorial board of La Nouvelle Critique, he does not seem to have succumbed to the folly of the theory of the ‘two sciences’, ‘bourgeois’ and ‘proletarian’; it is hard to imagine him writing a panegyric to ‘Stalin, scientist of a new type’.40 If, despite all, he did approve Lysenko’s doctrines, he clearly did so, even at this early date, in the name of science, in the singular; his position was thus diametrically opposed to the one Aragon took on the same question. To be sure, these texts of Althusser’s have something disturbing about them. Yet one whole facet of his later work can be fully understood only after a reading of these early writings: thus the preface to For Marx acquires a dimension that has largely escaped notice. Moreover, in this light, the relationship to Hegel appears in all its complexity.
The 1970s were dramatic years for Althusser. Cut off from the movements of the far Left after 1968, he had also ceased to utilize the École normale supérieure as the centre of a complex politico-philosophical strategy: the era of the seminar on Capital or of the ‘Philosophy Course for Scientists’ was definitively over. He now chose to wage a struggle essentially internal to the Communist Party, at the very moment when it was going into a phase of decline that, at the time, could be only dimly foreseen: its position within the academy was still very strong, and the Union of the Left had bright days ahead of it. Publications continued to appear at the usual slow pace, as if nothing had changed: Reply to John Lewis41 was published in England in 1972 and in France a year later, Elements of Self-Criticism42 and Philosophy and the Spontaneous Philosophy of Scientists in 1974,43 Positions in 1976.44 Yet the success of these works, especially that of Reply to John Lewis, which was considerable, could not hide the depths of Althusser’s disarray – witness the self-parody he wrote in the same period.45 Something had definitely snapped. The crisis of the middle of the decade did nothing to improve the situation: France’s intellectuals suddenly rediscovered the horrors of Stalinism, and, in time, a reference to Marx became a mark of ignominy.
Althusser’s reaction was by no means all of a kind. His most noticeable impulse, at least initially, was to rise to the defence of basic principles. Thus he undertook a vigorous campaign in defence of the concept of the dictatorship of the proletariat, the most conspicuous result being the pamphlet ‘On the Twenty-Second Congress of the French Communist Party’.46 He took part in several public debates on this theme, in France and in Spain, and wrote a long work, which would remain unfinished, called ‘The Black Cows: An Imaginary Interview’. At about the same time, he drew up an unsparing account of the crisis in the Communist Party in a series of articles published in Le Monde and reprinted in the book What Must Change in the Communist Party.47 He also embarked on a full-scale review of the crisis of Marxist theory; this time, the primary objective was not to defend principles, but to show that a renewal of Marxist thought could take place only on the basis of an analysis of its inherent limits. Thus, attentively rereading Gramsci, he tried to define Marx’s ‘absolute limits’, in particular with regard to the question of the state. This procedure had its own dark side: the crisis was perhaps even deeper, it was perhaps time to do something completely different – that was at least one of the senses of the ‘return to philosophy’ which began at the same moment, to say nothing of the writing of the first autobiography, The Facts, in 1976. Thus, in the two philosophy manuals mentioned above, we find what for Althusser were unusual references: he evokes Epicurus, Heidegger, and also Derrida, whom he had been reading for a long time, but had never publicly discussed. It is in this period that the metaphor of the train makes its appearance in his theoretical writings; it was to become one of the main preoccupations of his last years. If Althusser’s thought had always had many facets, the divergence amongst them was here extreme.
In the last years of his life, Althusser no longer had, in a certain sense, to answer to anyone for anything. Despite the fidelity of his friends, this state of extreme solitude had a shaping influence on his theoretical writing, which now displayed a pronounced tendency to take on a prophetic tone. There is often only a thin line between the philosophical work and texts whose often immense import is primarily clinical. We have decided not to publish such writings here; in our judgement, they belong somewhere else. Indeed, the only book to be published in Althusser’s lifetime after the murder of Hélène – it appeared in Mexico in 198848 – was the end result of so complex a process of production that a lengthy narrative would be required to give a full account of it.
The relation these late writings bear to Althusser’s work as a whole is not simple. In one sense, the break is obvious: to borrow one of Althusser’s favourite expressions, the concept of ‘aleatory materialism’ was not explicitly present [trouvable] in his earlier work. ‘Aleatory materialism’ combines two terms in a way totally foreign to the tradition of dialectical materialism; and yet the phrase forcibly brings ‘theoretical practice’ to mind. Moreover – indeed, above all – the theme of the encounter had long been at the centre of Althusser’s thinking about history and the concept of mode of production.49 The ideas about the conjuncture that he worked out in the 1960s had obviously emerged against the backdrop of a projected theory of the conjuncture that was never to crystallize. After the initial surprise has worn off, we are finally not puzzled to find, in working notes dating from 1966, comments that would be repeated almost word for word in his last writings: ‘1. Theory of the encounter or conjunction (= genesis …) (cf. Epicurus, clinamen, Cournot), chance etc., precipitation, coagulation. 2. Theory of the conjuncture (= structure) … philosophy as a general theory of the conjuncture (= conjunction).’ And it is not without a certain emotion that we discover, suddenly surging up in the midst of notes on Pierre Macherey’s book Towards a Theory of Literary Production, phrases which, at first sight, are very far removed from the subject: ‘Theory of the clinamen. First theory of the encounter!’ If, finally, the image of the train elaborated in the ‘Portrait of the Materialist Philosopher’, the text that rounds off this [French] volume,50 occurs in most of Althusser’s late writings, it does not materialize out of nowhere in the 1980s. It can, for example, also be found in a letter to René Diatkine probably written in 1972: ‘There is no point of departure and no destination. One can only ever climb aboard moving trains: they come from nowhere and are not going any place. Materialist thesis: it is only on this condition that we can progress.’
Althusser has left us no word of conclusion: his work stops in mid-course, essentially unfinishable. But if we had to identify something like the motor of his theoretical production, we would hazard calling it the void. From the conjuring away of the necessary void in the master’s thesis on Hegel, through the ‘void of a distance taken’ in Lenin and Philosophy, to, finally, the void as the ‘one and only object’ of philosophy, fascination with a word doubtless underlies the construction of a philosophical object.
We wish to thank all those who have helped make publication of this volume possible: first and foremost, François Boddaert, Louis Althusser’s heir, Olivier Corpet, and Yann Moulier Boutang, whose day-to-day support has been invaluable. Our thanks also go to Étienne Balibar, Madame Behr, chief librarian of the Library of the Catholic University of Lyons, Madame Bely, Dean of the Philosophy Faculty at the Catholic University of Lyons, Gilles Candar, André Chabin, Marcel Cornu, Dominique Lecourt, Jacqueline Pluet-Despatin, Robert F. Roeming, Jacqueline Sichler. And a special thanks to Sandrine Samson.
* L’aléatoire, a notion that was to take on crucial importance in Althusser’s writings of the 1980s; see pp. 10–11 below.
† A number of texts from the 1970s and 1980s have been published for the first time in Écrits philosophiques, Vol. I, pp. 341–582 and Vol. II, passim.
‡ This is the subtitle of the second half of the Écrits philosophiques et politiques, Vol. 1.
§ Notably Raymond Aron, Georges Bataille, Roger Caillois, Pierre Klossowski, Jacques Lacan, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Raymond Queneau, Jean-Paul Sartre.
‖ Auguste Véra, whose French translation of the Encyclopædia began to appear in 1859.