Against the Hegelian dialectical, postmodern, post-structural, and postcolonial logic of many white Western and black bourgeois scholars exploring the Haitian Revolution, culture, and identity of the Haitian people, I propose an anti-dialectical perspective grounded in the Weberian (1958 [1904–1905]) sociology of The Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism coupled with the structural Marxism of structuration theory.[1] From the former my phenomenological structural sociology borrows the logic of the internalization of the ideas and ideals of the ideological superstructure of a society as the basis by which social actors go about recursively reorganizing and reproducing their being-in-the-world as their purposive-rationality or practical consciousness, which is the language of the latter, structurationism. Phenomenological structuralism seeks to fix structurationism to account for alternative agential moments outside of structural reproduction and differentiation. In the end, I apply my structurationist sociology to understanding the constitution of Haitian practical consciousness as the parallel development of two forms of system and social integration, the Catholic/Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism of the whites and Affranchis on the one hand; and the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism of the majority of the Africans on the other.
The structurationist or praxis school in the social sciences is commonly associated with Jürgen Habermas (1987 [1981], 1984 [1981]), Pierre Bourdieu (1990 [1980], 1984), and Anthony Giddens (1984) in sociology, and Marshall Sahlins (1976, 1995 [1981]) in anthropology (Crothers, 2003; Ortner, 1984). Elaborated in a series of theoretical works and empirical studies, structurationists or praxis theorists account for agency and consciousness in social structure or system, “by clamping action and structure together in a notion of ‘practice’ or ‘practises’” (Crothers, 2003, pg. 3). That is, structures are not only external to social actors, as in the classic structural functional view, but are also internal rules and resources produced and reproduced by actors “unconsciously” (intuitively) in their practices. In structurationist or praxis theory, as Marx one-hundred years before suggested, the structure is “not a substantially separable order of reality”, but “simply the ‘ideal’ form in which the totality of ‘material’ relations…are manifested to consciousness…” (Sayer, 1987, pg. 84). From this perspective, accordingly, structure or, sociological speaking, social structure, “may set [(ideological)] conditions to the historical process, but it is dissolved and reformulated in material practice [(through mode of production and ideological apparatuses)], so that history becomes the realization, in the form of society, of the actual [(embodied rules)] resources people put into play” (Sahlins, 1995 [1981], pg. 7): consciousness, as a result, refers to “practical consciousness” or the dissolution and reformulation of a social structure’s terms (norms, values, prescriptions, and proscriptions) in material practice.
Although this Neo-Marxist “clamping together” of structure, praxis, and consciousness descriptively accounts for “the individual moment of phenomenology” by explaining the unanimity, closure, and “intentionality” of a form of human action or sociation, the capitalist social (material) relations of production and its class division, which constitutes the integrative actions of modern society. It fails, however, as pointed out in the epistemological postmodern/post-structural positions of Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Jacques Lacan, bell hooks, and Patricia Hill-Collins, to account for the origins and nature of fully visible alternative forms of practices (i.e., “the variability of the individual moments of phenomenology”) within the dominant order that are not class based, but are the product of the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse, a la the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism social class language game of the Vodou leadership of Haiti. Structurationists fail to see that society and its dominant institutionalized identity and behavior is not solely “one-dimensional,” i.e., a duality, and differentiated by the dialectic of capitalist social relations of production, but is constituted, through power relations, as transition, relation, and difference. This difference, akin to Jacques Derrida's différance, is not biologically (racially) hardwired in the social actor. It is a result of self-reflective and non-impulsive social actors, upon internalizing the arbitrary structural terms or signifiers of their society via their consciousness, bodies, language, and linguistic communication, conceiving of and exercising other forms of being-in-the-world from that of the dominant symbolic order and its structural differentiation or relational logic through the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse (Habermas, 1987 [1981], 1984 [1981]; Giddens, 1984).
By “clamping” action, structure, and consciousness together, i.e., part/whole totality, however, structurationists do not account for, nor demonstrate, the nature and relation of this non-biologically and non-impulsive determined difference (différance) to that of the dominant practices of the social structure as highlighted in the theorizing of postmodern and post-structural scholars. Instead, they re-introduce the problem in a new form: How do we know or exercise anything at odds with an embodied received view grounded in, and differentiated by, capitalist social relations of production? Paul C. Mocombe’s (2013, 2014, 2015) phenomenological structural ontology, phenomenological structuralism, seeks to fix structurationism to account for this problematic by synthesizing the materialism of physics, with the agential initiatives highlighted in the phenomenological method and discourses of Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Sartre, the Neo-Marxist structuralism of structurationism, and Wittgenstein’s notion of language game. For Mocombe, in building on the duality concept of structuration theory, human social action, consciousness, and identity is not only a duality determined by their relation to the mode of production and its differentiation. But it is also a dualism, the externalized structure of a society reified, in the words of Louis Althusser (1970, 2001), through language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, communicative discourse, and the mode of production. As such, social action and identity/consciousness constitution are not necessarily a duality, i.e., the internalization of the external language, ideology, etc., of a social structure recursively (re) organized and reproduced as the practical consciousness of a social actor. Duality is a contingent phenomenon based on a human subject’s stance vis-à-vis the reified structure, which presupposes their existence and the will of those in power positions. In other words, alternative actions or practical consciousnesses are distinct reified languages, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and modes of production from that of the dominant social structure within which they operate. These alternative actions or practical consciousnesses are the product of four sources, and Being’s stance, ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand, vis-à-vis them: 1) the drives of the body and brain, 2) impulses of residual actions/memories of embodied recycled past consciousnesses of subatomic particles, 3) ideologies of a social system along with its differentiating logic (structural reproduction and differentiation), which produces the variability of actions and practices in cultures, social structures, or social systems as highlighted by structurationist theorists, and 4) the “present-at-hand” phenomenological meditation/deferment that occurs on the latter actions via linguistic/symbolic communication. The exercise of power by social actors in power positions in the ideological apparatuses social actors are interpellated in, in the end, determines what practical consciousnesses are allowed to manifest in a material resource framework without a social actor facing alienation, marginalization, or death.
To this end of fixing structurationism to account for the nature and origins of alternative practical consciousnesses outside the structural reproduction and differentiation of capitalist relations of production, Paul C. Mocombe’s (2014, 2015) phenomenological structuralism builds on the material relationship highlighted in physics between the identity and indeterminate behavior of subatomic particles highlighted in quantum mechanics and the determinate behavior of atomic particles in their aggregation as highlighted in general relativity to understand the material constitution of consciousness at the subatomic/neuronal level in, and as, the brain and its manifestation as human practical consciousness at the atomic level as revealed by modes of production, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, communicative discourse, and the actions of the body. I go on, in the subsequent chapters, to utilize Mocombe’s structurationism, phenomenological structural ontology, to account for the emergence of the two worldviews (forms of system and social integration), the Catholic/Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism social class language game and the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism social class language game, found in the nation-state of Ayiti (Haiti).
According to the tenets of quantum physics as reflected in supersymmetry theory, dark matter, parallel universes (multiverses), and the EPR paradox, the universe is composed of ordinary matter (atoms and molecules) and dark matter (axions, wimps, neutrinos, bosons, and fermions).[2] Dark matter, as opposed to ordinary matter, constitutes over eighty percent of the material substance that constitute the cosmos. This dark matter is not constituted by atoms and molecules like ordinary matter but consists of subatomic particles and energy. The particles in the nature of quarks are identified as wimps or axions, very tiny particles that contribute to the formation of nuclear components. These tiny particles are conceived of as coiled energies, strings of space-time, packets of energy-like photons. They are physical in nature but immaterial, and coexist, in a parallel/alternate universe, with ordinary matter in the same location without impediment or interference. They belong to the fermion family of invisible particles whose counterparts are named a boson, which is pure energy. So, as highlighted in supersymmetry theory, for every boson particle of matter, a symmetry counterpart, fermion, exists which manifests itself as force or energy. Thus, for every reality we discover in the solid world around us, we must assume that there exists a symmetric counterpart, or boson, which is invisible but is nevertheless as physical as its visible counterpart. These supersymmetric doubles constitute the backbone of alternate realities, parallel universes that are displayed in ten dimensions, including our ordinary three-dimensional Cartesian reality. Moreover, according to the EPR paradox, these particles have psychic properties. That is, the particles are conscious. They are aware of their position, of themselves, and of their surroundings. In other words, the multiverses created by these particles are endowed with consciousness.
Hence the multiverse originated either by fiat or quantum fluctuation. It is a bosonic force that was brought forth together with a fermion counterpart. It is also the primeval pan-psychic field whose fermion can be called a psychion, a particle of consciousness. These have evolved together to produce the four forces of nature, electromagnetic force; gravity; the strong nuclear force; and weak nuclear force, in our universe, which in turn produced atoms, molecules, and aggregated life. In other words, according to quantum mechanics subatomic particles of energy constitute all the matter of the universe via the Higgs Boson Field, i.e., the god particle, which objectifies and materialize the matter that we are, see, hear, taste, feel, and touch. Subatomic particles constitute our material bodies and consciousness as neuronal energies, which constitute and operate the brain and the body. However, subatomic matter, which are strings at the subatomic particle level, operate differently from observable objectified energy, matter, in that their behavior are indeterminate and can exist in multiple places, dimensions or parallel universes, simultaneously prior to being observed or even during observation as aggregated matter. In fact, the subatomic particles that constitute our material bodies and consciousness as neuronal energies are the same subatomic particles that constitute everything that we consider to be the world, universe, other species, etc. At the subatomic particle level we are not subjects contemplating an object, i.e., the world, multiverse, etc., we are the world, an undifferentiating energy. Hence, the implication suggested by the Standard Model of physics is that the observable and non-observable matter that constitutes our universe exists elsewhere in other unseen dimensions and parallel universes simultaneously with our own dispensation of space-time. Contrary to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, we do not occupy a universe. We are part of a multiverse with a plethora of I (s) and other sentient beings existing in them indistinguishable from one another at the subatomic level as energy. They become distinguishable at the atomic level through subatomic particle aggregation, i.e., matter. Subatomic particles aggregate to form objectified matter, universes, worlds, species and sentient beings with consciousness, etc. The plethora of I (s) and other sentient beings are constituted and connected via subatomic particles that are recycled throughout and as the multiverse to constitute and operate consciousness as subatomic neuronal energies of the body and the brain, which encounters objectified matter as objectified matter via the actions and senses of the brain, body, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, modes of production, and communicative discourse. In essence, consciousness is recycled subatomic energies of the multiverse objectified and embodied, similar to Hegel’s conceptualization of Geist. Whereas for Hegel Geist is distinct from the material world and unfolds dialectically in it, via embodiment of certain individuals, towards an ever-increasing rationalization of the world towards self-knowledge and freedom. For me the historical manifestation, Being-in-Spacetime, of the objectification of subatomic particles of the universe as consciousnesses and bodies has no definitive end-goal and is indeterminate. But constrained in materialized space-time by our material bodies and power relations or the social class language games, dualism, of those whose objectification, i.e., historicity, precedes our own individual consciousnesses and control the economic conditions of a material resource framework, which they reify via mode of production, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse.
Like the laws of physics, which attempt to regulate and determine subatomic particle activity as general law (Theory of general relativity) once they are aggregated, the social class language game of those who control the economic conditions of a material resource framework attempts to regulate and determine the indeterminacy of meaning unfolding in and as the consciousnesses of social actors via bodies, mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse. Unlike, postmodern and post-structural theorizing, which utilize the indeterminacy of meaning as highlighted by the unconscious in the psychoanalytic works of Sigmund Freud and Jacques Lacan, my phenomenological structuralism analogously builds on the material relationship in physics between the identity and indeterminate behavior of subatomic particles highlighted in quantum mechanics and the determinate behavior of atomic particles in their aggregation as highlighted in general relativity to understand the material constitution of consciousnesses at the subatomic/neuronal level in, and as, the brain and their manifestation as human practical consciousnesses, via the body, at the atomic level. I do not, unlike psychoanalysts like Lacan and Freud or phenomenologists like Edmund Husserl, claim to know how the embodiment of recycled subatomic neuronal energies via the microtubules of the brain come to constitute consciousnesses in the brain and their subsequent revelation as the practical consciousnesses of bodies. That is, the transcendental ego or I of a differentiated individual subject, which I or anyone else does not have access to, could just as much be the past I, recycled subatomic particles, of a sentient being from an alternative universe or dimension of the multiverse and not necessarily the product of repression and the rule of the father, i.e., social construction. Psychoanalysis and the indeterminacy of the processes of the unconscious and the universal mapping of consciousnesses, i.e., its form of understanding, by Edmund Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology and contemporary neuroscientists, for me, in other words, neither adequately captures the indeterminate behavior of embodied recycled subatomic particles as neuronal energies of the brain and the myriad of practical consciousnesses they may produce as revealed by diverse practices of bodies, nor can they account for the origins of the transcendental ego or I. Husserl, Freud, and contemporary neuroscientists attempt to highlight and capture the Kantian form of the understanding and sensibilities of the aggregated body and brain, which is unable to explain how aggregated subatomic quantum particles give rise to the transcendental ego of consciousness, which produces praxis. I am not claiming that my phenomenological structural ontology captures this process. The only thing of consciousness, produced by embodied subatomic particles, I am claiming to be ontogenetically universal is the stance of the transcendental ego, what Heidegger calls the analytic of Dasein, vis-à-vis the drives of the aggregated body, impulses of recycled past consciousnesses of subatomic particle energies, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, structural reproduction and differentiation, once it becomes constituted by subatomic particles. Hence my use of phenomenology in phenomenological structuralism. I hold on to the phenomenological logic of Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Sartre here to capture, in a behavioral sense, the how, via Heidegger’s three stances ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, present-at-hand, of identity constitution amidst indeterminacy of consciousnesses and actions produced by embodied recycled subatomic neuronal energies/particles.
It is the stance of a transcendental ego vis-à-vis 1) the drives of the aggregated body, 2) the drives or impulses of recycled subatomic particles, 3) structural reproduction and differentiation of ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and mode of production, and 4) the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse, which determines our practical consciousness. In other words, what I am suggesting here in my phenomenological structuralism, which seeks to highlight the phenomenology of being-in-the-structure-of-those-who-control-a-material-resource-framework and the origins of our practical consciousness, is that embodiment is the objectification of the transcendental ego, which is a part of an universal élan vital (Henri Bergson’s term), the primeval pan-psychic field, that has ontological status in dimensions existing at the subatomic particle level and gets embodied via, and as, the body and connectum of Being’s brains. Hence the transcendental ego is the universal élan vital, which is the neuronal energies of past, present, and future Beings-of-the-multiverse, embodied. This transcendental ego, and its stance, encounters a material world via and as the body and brain in mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse.
Once embodied in and as human individual consciousnesses in a particular universe, world, and historical social formation, the transcendental ego becomes an embodied hermeneutic structure that never encounters the world and the things of the world in themselves via the aggregated built-in genetic ontology of the body and the impulses of the neuronal energies. Instead embodied hermeneutic individual consciousness is constituted via the recycled subatomic neuronal particle energies which are aggregated as a transcendental ego and the body in their encounter and interpretation of past recycled neuronal memories and things enframed in and by the language, bodies, ideology, ideological apparatuses, practices, and communicative discourses of those who control the economic conditions of a material resource framework and its social relations of production. In consciousness, as phenomenology posits, it (individual subjective consciousness of embodied beings) can either choose to accept the structural knowledge, differentiation, and practices of the body; the impulses of recycled past consciousnesses of subatomic neuronal particles; the ideologies of those who control, via their bodies, mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse, the economic conditions of the material resource framework and recursively reorganize and reproduce them in their practices; or reject them, given the ability to defer meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse, for an indeterminate amount of action-theoretic ways-of-being-in-the-world-with-others, which they may assume at the threat to their ontological security. It is Being’s stance, ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand vis-à-vis 1) the drives of the body, 2) impulses of residual actions/memories of embodied recycled past consciousnesses, 3) the phenomenological meditation/deferment that occurs on the latter actions via linguistic communication, and 4) ideologies of a social system along with its differentiating logic, coupled with the will of those in power positions, which produces the variability of actions and practices in cultures, social structures, or social systems that enframe the material world.
As such, as in Heidegger’s phenomenology, phenomenology in phenomenological structuralism is not just transcendental, it is also hermeneutical. The act of interpretation (based on the stance of Being) or an embodied hermeneutic structure via the body, language, ideology, and communicative discourse is a universal precondition of being-in-the-world-with-other-human-beings. However, whereas Heidegger is interested in the question of the meaning of Being-as-such, i.e., the phenomenology of Being, phenomenological structuralism is concerned with the sociology of Being, the question of the meaning or constitutive nature of embodied Being-as-such’s-being-in-the-world-with-others who attempt to constrain practical consciousnesses via their bodies, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse derived from social relations of production. That is, as in Martin Heidegger’s phenomenological ontology, I am interested in the necessary societal relationship and practical consciousnesses that emerge out of the phenomenology of Being-in-the-world-within-structures-of-signification-of-others, who control the economic conditions of the material resource framework we find ourselves existing in, that presuppose our historicity, and Being’s perceptions, responses, and practices, i.e., relations, to these structures-of-signification in order to be in the world. Unlike Heidegger, however, my concern is not with the phenomenology of being-in-the-world as such because Being never encounters the world and its transcendental ego as the-thing-itself. Instead being encounters the world via its body/brain, recycled (impulses of) past consciousnesses, and structures of signification, which derive from class division and social relations of production as reified in the bodies (as agential initiative), language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse of those who control the resources of a material resource framework.
Be that as it may, whereas I accept the Husserlian phenomenological understanding that the facts of the world and their conditions of possibility are present in consciousness, i.e., the notion of intentionality, consciousness is always consciousness of something as we experience being-in-the-world-with-other-beings via our consciousness, i.e., transcendental ego, bodies, language, ideologies, and communicative discourse. My position here, however, is that as an embodied hermeneutic structured being we never experience the facts of the world and their conditions of possibility as the “the things in themselves.” We experience them not culturally and historically, which is a present-at-hand viewpoint, but structurally and relationally, via the bodies, language, ideology, and communicative discourse in institutions or ideological apparatuses, i.e., the social class language game, of those who control the economic conditions of the material resource framework we find ourselves thrown-in, via our bodies, language, and communicative discourse. In other words, my phenomenology of embodied Being-in-the-world-as-such’s-Being-with-others, phenomenological structuralism, synthesizes Merleau-Ponty’s and Heidegger’s phenomenology with Karl Marx’s materialism and Ludwig Wittgenstein’s language game to suggest that being-in-the-world with others, our practical consciousness, is a product of our interpretation, acceptance, or rejection of the symbols of signification, social class language game, of those bodies in institutional/ideological power positions who control via their bodies, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse the economic conditions of a material resource framework as we encounter them and their symbols/signifiers in institutions or ideological apparatuses via our own transcendental ego, bodies, language, and communicative discourse. Hence we never experience the things-in-themselves of the world culturally and historically in consciousness. We experience them structurally or relationally, and our stances, ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, present-at-hand, vis-à-vis these ideological structures determine our practical consciousness or behaviors.
We initially know, experience, and utilize the things of the world in the preontological ready-to-hand mode, which is structural and relational. That is, our bodies and impulses encounter, know, experience, and utilize the things of the world in consciousness, intersubjectively, via their representation as objects of knowledge, truth, usage, and experience enframed and defined in the relational logic and practices or language game (Wittgenstein’s term) of the institutions or ideological apparatuses of the other beings-of-the-material resource framework whose historicity comes before our own and gets reified in and as language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse based on their mode of production or satisfying the needs of the aggregated body. This is the predefined phenomenal structural, i.e., ontological, world we, the psychion or transcendental ego of the primeval pan-psychic field, and our bodies are thrown-in in coming to be-in-the-world. How an embodied-hermeneutically-structured Being as such solipsistically goes on to view, experience, understand, and utilize the predefined objects of knowledge, truth, and experienced defined by others and their conditions of possibilities in consciousness in order to formulate their practical consciousness is albeit indeterminate. Heidegger is accurate, however, in suggesting that three stances or modes of encounter (Analytic of Dasein), “presence-at-hand,” “readiness-to-hand,” and “un-readiness-to-hand,” characterizes our views of the things of consciousness represented intersubjectively via bodies, language, ideology, and communicative discourse, and subsequently determine our practical consciousness or social agency. In “ready-to-hand,” which is the preontological mode of human existence thrown in the world, we accept and use the things in consciousness with no conscious experience of them, i.e., without thinking about them or giving them any meaning or signification outside of their intended usage. Heidegger’s example is that of using a hammer in hammering. We use a hammer without thinking about it or giving it any other condition of possibility outside of its intended usage as defined by those whose historicity presupposes our own. In “present-at-hand,” which, according to Heidegger, is the stance of science, we objectify the things of consciousness and attempt to determine and reify their meanings, usage, and conditions of possibilities. Hence the hammer is intended for hammering by those who created it as a thing solely meant as such. The “unready-to-hand” outlook is assumed when something goes wrong in our usage of a thing of consciousness as defined and determined by those who adopt a “present-at-hand” view. As in the case of the hammer, the unready-to-hand view is assumed when the hammer breaks and we have to objectify it, by then assuming a present-at-hand position, and think about it in order to either reconstitute it as a hammer, or give it another condition of possibility. Any other condition of possibility that we give the hammer outside of its initial condition of possibility which presupposed our historicity becomes relational, defined in relation to any of its other conditions of possibilities it may have been given by others we exist in the world with. Hence for Heidegger, the ontological status of being-in-the-world-with-others, via these three stances or modes of encountering the objects of consciousness hermeneutically reveal, through our view, experience, understanding, and usage of the predefined objects of knowledge, truth, and experience. Whereas Heidegger in his phenomenological work goes on to deal with the existential themes of anxiety, alienation, death, despair, etc. in my phenomenological stance regarding societal constitution or Beings-as-such’s-being-in-the-world-with-others via our stances to the body, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, communicative discourse, and social relations of production I am not concerned with the phenomenological preoccupation of individual solipsistic existence as defined in Jean-Paul Sartre’s work which claims to take off from Heidegger. Instead, I am interested in the universal ontological structure, i.e., social structure or societal constitution and practical consciousness, which arises out of Heidegger’s three stances, what I am calling phenomenological structuralism, vis-à-vis embodiment, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, communicative discourse, and social relations of production. That is, I am not concerned with Sartre’s phenomenologization of the Cartesian res cogitans/ transcendental ego, i.e., the present-at-hand transcendental ego, which he gives ontological status in the world as a solipsistic individual seeking to define themselves for themselves lest they be declared living in bad faith. In my view, the overemphasis of that particular aspect of Dasein is a product of a specific historical and relational mode of production, and only account for one of its analytics as highlighted by Heidegger. For me, the transcendental ego, which is a part of a universal élan vital, the primeval pan-psychic field, existing in another dimension at the subatomic particle level, does not originate out of the historical material world, but several variations of it becomes objectified via embodiment and the aforementioned stances in a universe, galaxy, and historical material world structured by other embodied Beings and their stances. Upon death its historicity via subatomic neuronal particles gets reabsorbed into the élan vital, primeval pan-psychic field, to be recycled to produce future beings. As such consciousness, i.e., practical consciousness, is a product of the stances of Dasein vis-à-vis its embodied recycled past consciousnesses/impulses, language and ideology, which can be deferred in ego-centered communicative discourse, and structural reproduction and differentiation determined by mode of production, ideological apparatuses, and those in power positions. Be that as it may, as with Heidegger, who refutes Sartre’s existential rendering of his phenomenological ontology, I am interested in the objectified/reified societal constitution and practical consciousnesses of the transcendental egos and their relations that emerge within a dominant constitution of Being that controls a material resource framework of the world via bodies, mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse vis-à-vis the stances of the transcendental ego.
Hence the understanding here is that the transcendental ego of Being becomes embodied and objectified in a material resource framework enframed by bodies, the mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse of those who control a material resource framework. As embodied consciousness the transcendental ego initially encounters itself and the world in the ready-to-hand preontological mode. This means as aggregated recycled subatomic particle, Being is, initially, unconsciously driven by the drives of its body and the agential initiatives or impulses of recycled past subatomic neuronal particles as limited by their embodiment. If its drives or impulses are uninhibited by the bodies, mode of production, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse, i.e., social class language game, of those who control the material resource framework, Being may spend all of their existence in this stance. However, should they encounter resistance vis-à-vis their drives and the social class language game of those who control the material resource framework, Being moves to the unready-to-hand stance where they think about and question their own drives and or those of the material resource framework. At which point, they may become present-at-hand and may opt for either the practices associated with their internal drive or impulses, which they reify as culture, or that of the social class language game in power. If they choose the latter, being simply seeks the structural practices and differentiation of power at the expense of their internal drive. In the former case, choosing to reproduce their internal drives, impulses, or deferred meaning of linguistic structures, Being, attempts to recursively reproduce what was the unconscious drives of recycled past consciousnesses, the body, or deferred meaning in the conscious present-at-hand stance at the threat to their ontological security in the material resource framework. At which point they may seek other Beings who share their drives, impulses, deferred meaning, or seek to change the ideology of power to accept what has become a decentered subject who has deferred the meaning of power. The latter position is the basis for postmodern and post-structural thought, and alternative practices outside of structural reproduction and differentiation.
Phenomenological structuralism, therefore, seeks to highlight the ontological universal modes of embodied human existence with others, which relationally has emerged out of the phenomenological processes (Heidegger’s three stances) of the transcendental ego experiencing, interpreting, and using the representational facts of its embodiment vis-à-vis the world as defined by and in the language game of others who control objects of a material resource framework, and how these modes of human existence come to (re) shape practical consciousness and constitute social structure or societal constitution. It is within this Wittgensteinian/Marxian/Heideggerian derivative ontology I explore the origins of Haitian practical consciousness as the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism as it stands against the Catholic/Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism of the whites and Affranchis of the island.
Generally speaking, consciousnesses for me then are the embodiment of recycled subatomic neuronal energies of the multiverse objectified in the space-time of multiverses. Once objectified and embodied the neuronal energies encounter the space-time of physical worlds via a transcendental subject of consciousnesses and the sensibilities and form of the understanding of the body and brain in reified structures of signification, language, ideology, and ideological apparatuses, defined and determined by other beings that control the resources (economics) of the material world required for physical survival in space-time. The stances, ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand, of the transcendental ego vis-à-vis, 1) the sensibilities or drives of the body and brain, 2) impulses of embodied residual memories of past recycled subatomic particles, 3) the actions produced via the body in relation to the indeterminacy/deferment of meaning of linguistic and symbolic signifiers as they appear to individuated consciousnesses in ego-centered communicative discourse, 4) and the differentiating effects of the structures of signification, social class language game, of those who control the economic materials of a world is the origins of practical consciousnesses. All four types of actions, the drives or sensibilities of the body, impulses of embodied recycled past consciousnesses, structural reproduction/differentiation, and deferential actions arising via the present-at-hand stance, exist in the material world with the physical, mental, emotional, ideological, etc. powers of those who control the material resource framework via the mode of production, language, ideology, and ideological apparatuses as the causative agent for individual behaviors.
In other words, our stances in consciousness vis-à-vis the drives of the body, structural reproduction and differentiation, embodied (impulses of) past consciousnesses of recycled subatomic particles, and deferential actions resulting from the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse determines the practical consciousness we want to recursively reorganize and reproduce in the material world. Those who control, through their bodies, language, mode of production, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse, the material resource framework, however, determines what actions they will allow to manifest without the embodied individual facing alienation, marginalization, or death.
As such, phenomenological structuralism synthesizes, the notions of the materialism and indeterminacy of behavior of recycled subatomic particles in quantum mechanics as they get objectified as neuronal energies of the brain and body to produce the transcendental subject of consciousness; with the potentiality for the multiplicity of choice or meaning in Heideggerian phenomenology (Heidegger’s analytic of Dasein) to capture the process of indeterminacy and deferment of meaning highlighted by postmodern and post-structural theory; with Marxist dialectic and Wittgensteinian notions of language games to highlight the reified atomic structures, bodies, mode of production, language, ideology, and ideological apparatuses, collectively understood here under the concept social class language game, which attempts to structure the indeterminacy of consciousness at the atomic human level as revealed in the practices, i.e., practical consciousnesses, of social actors.
As such, the notion of language game utilized here is an adoption of the “language-games” later philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein (1953) conceptualized within a Marxian understanding of the constitution of identities based on the practical consciousness and ideology of those who control the economic conditions, social relations of production, of a material resource framework. For the Wittgenstein of the Philosophical Investigations language is a tool and must be thought of as a rule-governed, self-contained practice, like a game, of activities associated with some particular family of linguistic expressions, which have no point outside themselves, but is simply associated with the satisfactions they give to the participants and their form of life. What I am suggesting here, against the genetic ontology of Christopher Macann (1993) who views the transcendental ego as “a subjectification of embodied human being,” in my phenomenological ontology, phenomenological structuralism, which seeks to highlight the phenomenology of being-in-the-structure-of-those-who-control-a-material-resource-framework-in-space-time through bodies, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and the social relations of production, i.e., being-in-time, is that embodiment is the objectification of the transcendental ego, which is a part of an universal élan vital (which is a material thing, the subatomic particles of past consciousnesses, the eternal recurrence of past consciousnesses, that gets encapsulated in the brain of breathing subjects we see in any given historical formation) that has ontological status in dimensions existing at the subatomic particle level and gets embodied as and via the connectome of Beings’ brains and their bodies. Embodiment is the multiverse manifesting itself as embodied consciousness or a transcendental ego. Once objectified, materialized, and embodied as human individual consciousnesses in a present historical formation the transcendental ego becomes an embodied hermeneutic structure that never encounters the world and the things of the world in themselves as highlighted by Jacques Lacan through his conception of the symbolic. Instead embodied hermeneutic individual consciousnesses are constituted via, and as, recycled neuronal energies of past consciousnesses, the body, language, and ego-centered communicative discourse in their encounter and interpretation of things either ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand enframed in and by the historical consciousness, language, bodies, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and practices, i.e., language game, of those who control the economic conditions, social relations of production, of the material resource framework it finds itself thrown in. As embodied consciousness, whose ideas and practices are revealed and manifested through the body and language, it (individual consciousnesses of beings) can either accept (ready-to-hand) the signified historical structural knowledge, differentiation, and practices (social class language game) of those who control the economic conditions, social relations of production, of the material resource framework and recursively reorganize and reproduce them in their practices and institutions, or reject them (in the unready-to-hand and present-at-hand stance), given the ability to defer meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse, for an indeterminate amount of action-theoretic ways-of-being-in-the-world-with-others-in-space-time, which they may assume at the threat to their ontological security. It is the ready-to-hand drives of the body, ready-to-hand and present-at-hand manifestation of past recycled residual consciousnesses, the present-at-hand phenomenological meditation and deferment of meaning that occurs in embodied consciousness via language, ideology, and communicative discourse as reflected in diverse individual practices, within the ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand differentiating logic or class divisions of the social relations of production, which produces the variability of actions and practices in cultures, social structures, or social systems. All four types of actions, the drives of the body and residual past consciousnesses, structural reproduction/differentiation, and actions resulting from the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse, are always present and manifested in a social structure (which is the reified ideology via ideological apparatuses, their social class language game, of those who control a material resource framework) to some degree contingent upon the will and desires of the economic social class that controls the material resource framework through its body, language, symbols, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and social relations of production. They choose, amidst the class division of the social relations of production, what other meaning constitutions and practices are allowed to manifest themselves without the Beings of that practice facing alienation, marginalization, domination, or death.
In sum, phenomenological structuralism posits consciousness to be the by-product or evolution of subatomic particles unfolding with increasing levels of abstraction. Subatomic particles, via the Higgs boson particle, gave rise to carbon atoms, molecules and chemistry, which gave rise to DNA, biological organisms, neurons and nervous systems, which aggregated into bodies and brains that gave rise to the preexisting consciousness of the subatomic particles, bodies, and languages. In human beings, the indeterminate behavior of subatomic neuronal energies that produced the plethora of consciousnesses and languages in the neocortex of the brain gave rise to ideologies, which in turn gave rise to ideological apparatuses and societies (sociology) under the social class language game or language, ideology, and ideological apparatuses of those who organize and control the material resources required for physical (embodied) survival in a particular resource framework. So contrary to Karl Marx’s materialism which posits human consciousness to be the product of material conditions, the logic here is a structural Marxist one. That is, the aggregated, atomic, mature human being is a body and neuronal drives that never encounters the (ontological) material world directly. Instead, they encounter the (ideological) world via structures of signification, which structures the world or a particular part of it through the body, language, ideology, and ideological apparatuses, i.e., social class language game, of those whose power and power positions dictate how the resources of that framework are to be gathered, used, and distributed (means and mode of production).
Hence phenomenological structuralism agrees with the structurationists that in the constitution of society the individual elements incorporate the structure of the ideological whole and gets differentiated by the relational logic of that whole. My understanding, unlike that of the traditional structurationists, attempts to provide an analytical tool to explain and examine the relation of the “others” within the totality who do not, however: the relationship between “the individual elements [, who,] internalize [and recursively reproduce,] the structur[ing ideology] of the whole,” and those who as a result of their ready-to-hand, unready-to-hand, and present-at-hand stances vis-à-vis the drives of their bodies, residual past consciousnesses of recycled subatomic particles or through self- reflection or phenomenological meditation in the unready-to-hand and present-at-hand mode of encountering the structural terms of a society conceive of, or choose among, fully visible “alternative” ways of being-in-the-world, which they attempt to exercise in the “totality.”
This “mechanical” relationship can be expressed diagrammatically (see Figure 1), and is an adaptation of Stephen Slemon’s (1995) description of colonialism’s multiple strategies for regulating Europe’s others (Slemon, 1995, pg. 46), and the way I see it, whether in my usage of it or Slemon’s slightly different depiction, it is a macro, at the societal level, extrapolation of Hegel’s and Marx’s master/slave dialectical power model, which would proceed along line A1, since we both suppose that our respective concepts (colonialism for Selmon and society, culture, structure, what have you, for me) are ideological or discursive formations constituted through power relations.[3]
The general understanding, within a phenomenological structural understanding of the constitution of society and practical consciousness, is that individual actors or network of solidarity or cultural groups (irreducibly “mediating” situated subjects), represented by lines “A” and “B” on the diagram, are relationally socialized within society—its semiotic field or predefined and predetermined lexicons and representations of signification (at the bottom of the diagram) i.e., the field of socialization “and its investment in reproducing and naturalising the structures of power” (Slemon, 1995, pg. 47)—through “ideological apparatuses” (at the top of the diagram) controlled by socialized institutional regulators (“As”), power elites or those in power positions, who recursively reorganize and reproduce the rules of conduct (which appear to be natural and commonsensical) of the social structure, which in modern times represent an ideological flanking for the protestant/capitalist economic subjugation running along line “A1.” Where in the first instance (A) there is encountering of the rules of conduct of the society at the preontological ready-to-hand mode of encountering, there is adoption or internalization (the Structurationist view) on behalf of the individual or network of groups of the prescribed understanding of the representations and practices of the semiotic field, i.e., the recursively organized and reproduced rules of conduct which are sanctioned. In the second (B), the individual encounters the facts and values of the world in either unready-to-hand or the present-at-hand mode, and through a form of phenomenological meditation on the structural terms (i.e., norms, values, prescriptions and proscriptions of power) that presuppose their existence, conceives of, or chooses among other or fully visible alternatives (other “Bs” discriminated by the social structure), a different understanding (, i.e., practical means, arriving from the drives of the body, unconscious drives of recycled subatomic particles, or through the deferment of meaning in ego-centered communicative discourse) of being-in-the-world ; or as in the case of racism, sexism, and classism is prescribed a structurally differentiated unalterable subordinate role based on the relational binary logic (rules for inclusion and exclusion) of the semiotic field of those in power positions (“As”). In this structurally differentiated mode the encountering is always either at the ready-to-hand or unready-to-hand mode of encountering, in the latter because something, discriminatory effects of the totality, is wrong in allowing the social actor to partake in the rules of conduct of the society. So regardless if they accept or reject the rules of conduct, they are still classified by the power elites as (Bs).
The socialized individuals or groups (“As”)—socialized in the “constitutive power of societal apparatuses like the church, education, etc., and the constitutive power of fields of knowledge [, which stems from the semiotic field,] within those apparatuses” (46)—possess the potential to become, if they so choose, power elites and as such institutional regulators (at the top of the diagram), who subordinate through the manufacture of consent. Now to maintain power, those who become regulators (some “As”) must address “B’s” signification, which relationally undermines (it gives social actors an “alternative” form of being-in-the-world), as well as define, delimits, and stabilizes the predefined lexicons and representations of signification that is the society’s semiotic field. In other words, their (“Bs’”) interpretations or structurally differentiated identity in relation to “A’s” reject the singularity and realism or naturalism attached to the representations and meanings of the social field, while at the same time helping to constitute it by defining, delimiting, and stabilizing the field, i.e., “B’s” interpretation in relation to “A’s” helps to define, because it is not, “A’s” interpretation. Hence, the “As” must negotiate, appropriate, and reinflect “Bs” interpretive-practices into the semiotic field in order to delimit, their own; this is done, or has been done, up to this point in the human archaeological records on the constitution of society, by having them (“Bs”) remain outside the field, by dismissing their interpretive-claims, in which case the field justifies their permanent outsider status (oppressed or discriminated against minorities, i.e., marginalized “other”).
The “Bs,” for the most part, can either accept (if their gaze is upon the eye of power—“As”—for recognition as a structurally differentiated “other,” i.e., a class-in-itself) their appropriation, the rationale the institutional regulators (“As”) prescribe to their (“B1s’”) interpretive-practical consciousness which legitimates it as a representation, or they (“B2s”) may choose (by averting their gaze as a class-for-itself) to remain quasi-outsiders if the meaning disclosed by the dominant institutional regulators is not in accordance with their own, or a previously discriminated subculture’s, interpretive-practical understanding of the signifiers of the social structure. Regardless of what choice they (“Bs”) make, however, they, “Bs,” because the validity claims the institutional regulators provide for their (Bs’) understanding validates their existence to start with, constantly attempt incorporation and acceptance, either, as a “class-in-itself,” pushing for integration as a structurally differentiated “other” (hybrid) who recursively reproduce the rules of conduct of the social structure (“B1s’”); or separation (“B2s’”), as a “class-for-itself,” for their own rules of conduct which are sanctioned by the power elites of the subculture. The former is the position of the bourgeoisie’s of once discriminated against groups, such as blacks, women, etc., in contemporary postindustrial Protestant capitalist societies seeking to partake as an hybrid other in the social class language games of the society.
Thus there are two fundamental paths which are open to “Bs”: first, if they (B) accept the understanding of (A), regarding their interpretation as an “other,” and seek integration, as a structurally differentiated “class-in-itself,” they have to give up their interpretive-practical consciousness, which on the one hand undermines the legitimation of the interpretive community they are classed with, while on the other hand, legitimating society’s semiotic field, which has appropriated their (“Bs’”) understanding and representation to substantiate and delimit their (As’) power position and “practical consciousness.” From this perspective, the “Bs,” “B1s’”,who accept appropriation, are socialized (institutionalized) and attempt to live as (“As”), which entail recursively organizing and reproducing, as a hybrid “other,” the rules of conduct of the society which are sanctioned. Those who do not (the second path), that is, those in the present-at-hand mode of encountering who reject the rules of conduct of the society, for their own, “B2s’”, may seek to reconstitute society in line with their interpretive-practical consciousness, which gives rise to another (warring) structure of signification or form of being-in-the-world, which, as a segregated categorical boundary or alternative practical consciousness, relationally and differentially delimits that of the society or social structure, which they initially constituted.[4]
From the perspective of power, “As,” “Bs’” interpretations, their interpretive-practical consciousness, are always represented in the semiotic field in order to define, delimit, and stabilize the power structure. Thus, “Bs” are always oppressed minorities or majorities, i.e., “others,” in the Hegelian master/slave relationship (A1), who must construct their identities or consciousness within two or more ideals: that of the social structure (master’s own understanding of themselves) and what it says of the discriminated against “other” (the slave). Hence, the “Bs,” as long as their gaze is turned back upon the eyes of power (vector of motion of “B1s’”) for recognition in the unready-to-hand mode of encountering, which seeks to fix the status quo for their participation, pose no real danger to the semiotic field, unless—following the aforementioned second path,“B2s’,”—they should take-up arms against it as a distinct structuring structure, i.e., “class-for-itself” or categorical boundary, which has averted their gaze, and are attempting to preserve or universalize their “alternative” ontology or “practical consciousness.” This latter position is represented by Islamic fundamentalists contemporarily, and the African participants of Bois Caiman during the Haitian Revolution.
In other words, in having to construct their (Bs) identities or consciousness by warring against the ideals of the social structure, which become the relational terms that defines, delimits, and stabilizes the social structure and that by which all (“As” and “Bs”) must construct their consciousness, the gaze back upon the eye of power is a sign of recognition of the validity claims of the social structure, which necessarily implies that in order to be recognized the “Bs” must attempt to be what they are not, like “As.” This agential move to be like “As,” however, constrains the variability of practices, which, as the diagram highlights, can only be maintained if the gaze of Bs’ (vector of motion of “B2s’”) are averted away from the eyes of power in order to establish another segregated structuring structure, which celebrates and reproduces the practices’ of their “otherness.” So long as the aim of “B” is for acceptance into the structure of social relations that constitute the society, their “otherness” can only be expressed as those (“As”) who recursively reorganize and reproduce the rules of conduct of the social structure. For it is only upon the world of existing state of affairs, i.e., the valid norms and subjective experiences of power, which is taken to be the nature of reality and existence as such, will they (“Bs”) be admitted into the structure of social relations that constitute the society, for any other form may undermine the whole of social relations that is the constituted society.[5]
Whereas, figure 2.1 demonstrates the action of individual social actors or groups within “a” reified consciousness, social class language game, that forms the structure of relations that is their society, figure 2.2 makes evident the actions of social actors (As), if and when, they become institutional/ideological regulators or power elites.
The understanding here is that it is the legal regulations of a society, its “lexicons and representations of signification,” its rules of conduct that are sanctioned, as outlined by the power elites, or institutional regulators in power positions, which represent the objective conditions (social structure) of society that structure social relations and constitute the materials by-which embodied consciousness is to be cultivated for the ontological security of the individual. In other words, the general understanding, within a phenomenological structural understanding, is that individual actors or groups (irreducibly situated subjects), lines A and B, are socialized within society—its semiotic field or predefined and predetermined lexicons and representations of signification (at the bottom of the diagram) i.e., the field of socialization “and its investment in reproducing and naturalising the structures of power” (Slemon, 1995, pg. 47)—through “ideological apparatuses” (at the top of the diagram) controlled by socialized institutional regulators (“As”), which represent an ideological flanking for the economic subjugation running along line “A1.” The relation between the two runs this way: societal power operates through a complex relationship between apparatuses (i.e., the law, education, rituals, family etc.) placed on line “C,” where in the first instance institutional regulators (“As”)—at the top of the line—appropriate and manufacture, based on what is already understood, lexicons and representations of signification of individuals in order to consolidate and legitimate itself as a natural “order” and to reproduce individuals as deployable units of that order. So, in the first instance, societal power runs not just through the middle ground of this diagram (A1) but through a complex set of relations happening along line “C;” and since the argument here is that a function (i.e., socialized social actor) at the top of this line is employing those representations created at the bottom of the line in order to make up “knowledges” that have an ideological function, one can say that the vector of motion along line C is an upward one, and that this upward motion is part of the whole complex discursive structure whereby society manufactures individuals and thus helps to regulate societal relations. This is the first position.
The second position, as the diagram demonstrates, is the downward movement of societal power, where the institutional regulators of society’s apparatuses are understood to be at work in the production of a purely unique and entirely projected idea of the individual, relationally delimited by other fully visible marginalized “alternative” forms of the individual being-in-the-world. The point this movement, which is inextricably tied to the first, is trying to articulate is that society is a product of the working and reworking of reified psychic projections, i.e., ideologies and their apparatuses. Hence, society has to be understood as a structure or system of power relations in which those in power positions attempt to structure, via bodies, language, ideology, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse individuals toward an unchangeable unified end.[6] This does not mean that there is no agency, for whom or what acts oppositionally, in this understanding of the constitution of society, is demonstrated through an understanding of the movements of lines A and B described above.
Essentially, then, in this phenomenological structural understanding, society develops from the interpretive-practical consciousness of those (power elites or social actors in power positions) who maintain control of and integrate its material resource framework.[7] Through this economic and political process, all individual actors (“As” and “Bs”), unless they choose (as a “class-for-itself” under the auspices of their own power elites) to establish their own institutions, are socialized in apparatuses controlled by these social actors, institutional regulators (at the top of the diagram), who employ their representations, the reified symbolic objects that constitute the semiotic field (society)—at the bottom of the diagram, in institutions—so as to control, guide, and incorporate the ambivalence that lies in the act of interpretation (Bhabha, 1995, pg. 208)—in order to make up and reproduce ideological “knowledges” that maintain the functioning of the society as a whole.[8] I am arguing that this model, up to this point in the human archaeological research on societal relations, is a general structure for understanding the multivalent strategies at work in the reproduction and transformation of societies. Furthermore, it resolves the issue of agency, which is problematic when one posits ideology or discourse or psychic processes as constructing human subjects, for who or what acts is clearly demonstrated in the model through the praxis of the structure (“As”) and anti-structural elements (“Bs” if they form interpretative communities, “B2s’”, which do not seek incorporation or cooptation).
Hence, the logic here is that Karl Marx’s materialism is the product of the first group of embodied human beings initial encounter with the material world. Upon that initial ready-to-hand encounter, driven by the drives of the body and impulses of subatomic particles, two present-at-hand worldviews emerged and became reified via mode of production, language, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourse. In a fruitful and bountiful environment, as early humankind encountered ready-to-hand in Africa prior to their migration elsewhere, a harmonious disposition towards the world took hold, which was juxtaposed against an antagonistic disposition arising from a lack of resources, etc., as was found among Europeans who migrated out of Africa to Europe. According to Cheik Anta Diop (1981, 1988, 1989), as a result of these experiences African and most people of color on the earth, the Taino people of the Caribbean, for example, who inherited hospitable environments, shared certain linguistic and cultural commonalities that formed a tapestry that laid the basis, present-at-hand, for African cultural unity, which was reified and diametrically opposed to the European cultural unity that would develop, unready-to-hand and present-at-hand, in the barren and harsh environments of Europe as early humans migrated out of Africa.
What Diop called the Southern Cradle-Egyptian Model (African): 1) Abundance of vital resources, 2) Sedentary-agricultural, 3) Gentle, idealistic, peaceful nature with a spirit of justice, 4) Matriarchal family, 5) Emancipation of women in domestic life, 6) territorial state, 7) Xenophilia, 8) Cosmopolitanism, 9) Social Collectivism, 10) Material solidarity—alleviating moral or material misery, 11) Idea of peace, justice, goodness, and optimism, and 12) Literature emphasizes novel tales, fables, and comedy, emerged, present-at-hand, among the people of color in tropical climates with bountiful resources. This Southern Cradle-Egyptian Model was diametrically opposed to an unready-to-hand and present-at-hand Northern Cradle-Greek Model: (European), 1) Bareness of resources, 2) Nomadic-hunting (piracy), 3) Ferocious, warlike nature with spirit of survival, 4) Patriarchal family, 5) Debasement/enslavement of women, 6) City state (fort), 7) Xenophobia, 8) Parochialism, 9) Individualism, 10) Moral solitude, 11) Disgust for existence, pessimism, 12) Literature favors tragedy. The European/Greek model, over time became reified and recursively reorganized and reproduced, present-at-hand, as the Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism under the leadership of Pastors, merchants, and owners in their encounter with Christiantiy; and the former, African model, as the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism under the leadership of priests, priestesses, healers, and elders (oungan, manbo, gangan, and granmoun in the Kreyol language of African/Taino/Haitian Vodou).
Hence unlike Karl Marx, which views the origins of modern capitalist relations of production via the notion of primitive accumulation, phenomenological structuralism is in agreement with Max Weber and views it as the product of the (ideological) structures of signification of European Protestant Christianity, i.e., the Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism reified via ideological apparatuses based on the mode of production, which I juxtapose against the African Vodou Ethic and spirit of communism of the original inhabitants of the earth who, because of their material abundance, did not develop an antagonistic present-at-hand view of the world as their European counterparts who experienced hardship in satisfying their basic needs. In other words, African peoples, and other people of color originally inhabited the earth, ready-to-hand, in environments with abundance of vital resources. Over time, their tribal and village leaders developed present-at-hand structural ideologies, Vodou; ideological apparatuses, villages, Lakous, peristyles, lwa yo, and herbal medicine; and modes of productions, subsistence agriculture, husbandry, and komes that reified their experiences and formed a tapestry, i.e., social class language game under the leadership of oungan yo, manbo yo, and granmoun yo (elders) that laid the basis for African cultural/structural unity, which was diametrically opposed to a European cultural/structural unity that encountered, ready-to-hand, a barren material resource framework.[9]
The latter because they were unable to satisfy their bodily needs in the barren material resource framework of Europe, in other words, became unready-to-hand and developed an antagonistic stance vis-à-vis the world, which became reified, present-at-hand, as the Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism when they encountered Christianity under the leadership, initially, of Pastors and merchants. Hence, what Cheikh Anta Diop called the Southern Cradle-Egyptian Model (African), which I call the Vodou Ethic and the spirit of communism social class language game, emerged, ready-to-hand and present-at-hand, among the Africans, and the Northern Cradle-Greek (European) Model, or the Protestant Ethic and the spirit of capitalism social class language game, emerged, unready-to-hand and present-at-hand, among the Europeans. The latter sought embourgeoisement and domination, and the former, ounganification/manboification, harmony, balance, perfection, and subsistence living, both models, or structuring structures, interpellated individual Beings of their material resource frameworks via different modes of production, languages, ideologies, ideological apparatuses, and communicative discourses. Both models converged on the island of Hispaniola, at the height of the slave trade and African enslavement during the eighteenth century, where the enslaved Africans of Haiti juxtaposed the latter against the former in the attempt to overthrow it on the island.
Within my phenomenological structural sociology, the concepts of postmodern, post-structural, and postcolonial theories represent the practical consciousness of the “other” bourgeoisies.
My phenomenological structuralism, as in Western epistemology and ontology which developed as a result of the ever-increasing rationalization and testing of Christian notions, reflects my rationalization of Vodou metaphysics as an ontology and sociology for understanding cosmic and societal constitution. As such, my work builds off of Reginald O. Crosley’s (2006) essay, “Shadow-Matter Universes in Haitian and Dagara Ontologies: A Comparative Study,” whose physics I summarize here.
For an in-depth look at Slemon’s diagram and description see: Slemon, Stephen (994). “The Scramble for Post-colonialism.” In De-Scribing Empire: Post-colonialism and Textuality, Eds. Chris Tiffin and Alan Lawson. London: Routledge. Slemon borrows this model (see figure 1 in the text) from De Saussure (1983 [1916]: 80), who prescribes the model as means for all sciences to map out the things they are concerned with. He calls the horizontal axis, “the axis of simultaneity.” “This axis concerns relations between things which coexist, relations from which the passage of time is entirely excluded.” The vertical axis, “the axis of succession:” “Along this axis one may consider only one thing at a time. But here we find all the things situated along the first axis, together with the changes they undergo.”
Slemon, in using this model to understand Edward Said’s depiction of colonialism and the role of the “other” argues, as many critics of structuralism have done, that there is no agency regardless of the practices taking place along the diachronic axis (i.e., the vertical axis; the horizontal axis for Saussure is the synchronic). Using this model to depict what I mean by phenomenological structuralism, I am arguing that my description is not historically specific, and resolves the issue of agency in structure (in this case ideological structure or hegemony).
Some may point to a third alternative, i.e., subversion from within, but this is a misconception because in order to be a subverter, the social actor must still recursively reorganize and reproduce the practical consciousness of the whole.
In other words, although “Bs” in the diagram represent the variability of praxis within structure, “counter-movements” in the Polanyian (2001 [1944]) sense only refer to embodied variable practices—which diametrically oppose the structuring end of the society or social structure they constitute and delimit—which seek to reconstitute society. As long as the aim of the discriminated against minority (“Bs”) is for recognition as an “other,” the variability of praxis is negated by the non-subversive hybridity of the discriminated against social actor.
According to the Structuralism of De Saussure, “[c]hange originates in linguistic performance, in parole [(i.e., speech, practice, or event)], not in la langue [(formal structure or institutions)], and what is modified are individual elements of the system of realization. Historical changes affect the system in the end, in that the system will adjust to them, make use of the results of historical change, but it is not the linguistic system which produces them” (Culler, 1976, pg. 41). From a phenomenological structural perspective what this means is that the ends to which the structure of society is directed appears to be unchangeable, even though the interpretive-practices amongst individuals and groups are, and may even contradict that appearance. What happens in the end is that institutional regulators attempt to incorporate these differential interpretive-practices in a way to maintain the order of things so that the end to which society is structured continues to be realizable in spite of the differential practices. In fact, these practices, defined by their relation with the practices of the structure come to delimit the actual structure.
This, as André C. Drainville (1995) observes, “is the essence of what Nicos Poulantzas called the political task of transformation” (57).
Whereas at issue for Bourdieu, Sahlins, and Giddens “is the being of structure in history and as history” (Sahlins, 1985, pg. 145), my approach does not see structure and history as antinomies, and therefore, focuses on the issue of “being” in a structure of history, or the predefined and predetermined “lexicons and representations of signification” that attempt to reproduce an aspect of “Being.” Transformation in this understanding is in the development of the historical structure as played-out in the interpretive-practices of the “Beings” or subjects of the system. In other words, reproduction is only attempted in the actual use of the structural ideas in “ideological apparatuses.” But this is only an attempt, for the ideas, as objectified by those in power, are distorted as a result of the interpretive-practices of irreducibly situated individuals. So what we have is a dynamic structure driven by interpretive-practices within what is already understood of the objectified concepts of those in power positions, who must attempt to appropriate and redirect interpretative-practices that oppose or threaten their symbolic order. In doing so the structure may or may not be transformed, for transformation rests only in the ability of those with contradictory understandings of the symbolic order (Bs in the diagrams) to reconstitute society based on their understanding. As long as, power (As) is able to appropriate and reinflect their (Bs) understanding, reproduction, and as such structural domination along the same structural line (horizontal axis), is the only necessary outcome.
I am using the Haitian/African Kreyol language for priests (oungan), priestesses (manbo), gangan (healers) and elders (granmoun), here out of convenience.