six
THE METHOD OF EQUALITY
Politics and Poetics
JACQUES RANCIÈRE
I GAVE this text the title: “The Method of Equality.” I am aware there is something that sounds strange in the formula. Equality is not supposed to be a method. Equality is supposed to be either a fact—an effective relationship—or an ideal. And a method is supposed to be a set of procedures through which a definite effect can be produced or, at least, a path through which one must move to acquire a new knowledge or new practical abilities. On this basis, there are two usual ways of thinking about the relationship between method and equality. The first one consists in saying that a method is not committed to issues of equality and inequality. It is only committed to its own progress and results. The second one consists in saying that equality is certainly a good thing but that one must deal with it methodically. This means first defining what kind of equality you wish to achieve, secondly the path and steps by means of which it is possible to achieve it.
For instance, when I was young I was taught that political and social equality was certainly a nice purpose, but that for this to be reached, one had to proceed methodically. Domination and exploitation, so the argument went, are the effects of a whole mechanism of social relationships. Those who suffer from them are made passive because they ignore the laws governing that mechanism. They must be taught how inequality works in order to know how they can change it. Of course, it is not enough to know it. The point is acting according to that knowledge, shifting from passivity to activity. But at this point, it appeared that the most difficult thing was to know what to do on the basis of that science, in what circumstances it could be turned into action and how that could be done. I was warned that those who rebelled against the law of domination did it wrongly most of the time: some of them, because, as workers pinned down to their work place, they had no view of the global social structure; others, because, as petit-bourgeois intellectuals, they had no concrete experience of class exploitation, and so on and so forth.
* * *
At this point, the lesson of the science of inequality appeared to be a double-edged one: on the one hand, it taught that the dominated are dominated because they ignore the law of domination. But at the same time, it taught that this ignorance is the product of the very mechanism of domination. Domination was said to impose itself by appearing to its subjects in an inverted manner in the ideological mirror of their consciousness. So the method appeared to be a perfect circle. On the one hand, it said: people get pinned down to their place in the system of exploitation and oppression, because they don’t know about the law of that exploitation or oppression. But on the other hand, it said: they don’t know about it because the place where they are confined hinders them from seeing the structure that allots them that place. In short, the argument read as follows: They are where they are because they don’t know why they are where they are. And they don’t know why they are where they are because they are where they are. This theoretical circle resulted in an endless spiral: the possessors of social science were always one step ahead, always discovering a new form of subjection and inequality. They never stopped finding a new type of illusion in the forms of consciousness of those who thought they were acquiring science, a new form of inequality subjecting those who thought they were moving toward equality. They never stopped demonstrating that people were ignorant when they thought they knew something, passive when they thought they were active, subjected to exploitation by the very illusion of being free, and so on. The method for reaching equality in an indeterminate future was in fact a method for postponing it indefinitely. It was a method for endlessly reasserting the grip of inequality and the incapacity of those who were subjected to it to acquire by their own capacities the knowledge that could free them. It was a method for reproducing indefinitely the separation between those who know and those who ignore. It was, strictly speaking, a method of inequality, reasserting continuously the division between the learned ones and the ignorant ones.
That circle of domination and ignorance could thus be read as the modern and progressive version of an old narrative that was first formulated in its rough conservative version in Plato’s Republic, namely, the identification of social hierarchy with a hierarchy of souls. Modern social science endlessly demonstrates why people stay at their place. But Plato had already dealt with the issue in a straightforward manner that made every future theory of ideology an academic joke. He said that there are two reasons why workers must stay at their place. The first reason is that they have no time to go elsewhere, because work does not wait, which appears to be merely an empirical fact. The second reason is that they have the aptitudes, the intellectual equipment that makes them fit for this occupation and for nothing else. So there is a perfect equation between an occupation and a mental equipment. According to that equation, being a worker is an occupation that entails that you have no time to be elsewhere than the place you are geared for occupying—which means that you have no time to chat on the agora, make decisions in the assembly, or look at shadows in theaters. This is what I call a distribution of the sensible: a relation between occupations and equipments, between being in a specific space and time, performing specific activities, and being endowed with capacities of seeing, saying, and doing that “fit” those activities. A distribution of the sensible is a set of relations between sense and sense, that is, between a form of sensory experience and an interpretation that makes sense of it. It is a matrix that defines a whole organization of the visible, the sayable, and the thinkable.
What exactly is the difference between the notion of the distribution of the sensible and the concept of ideology? The difference is as follows: the distribution of the sensible is not a matter of illusion or knowledge. It is a matter of consensus or dissensus. To understand what consensus means, let us go back to what is apparently a flaw in the Platonic demonstration. It is easy to understand that when you are in a place you cannot be elsewhere. What is trickier is to recognize that the individual who is in that place has the exact aptitude to be there and nowhere else. Plato, of course, had an answer for this: the latter, he says, is a myth. We have to accept a story or a lie: the story has it that God mixed iron in the makeup of the artisans while he mixed gold in the makeup of the legislators who are destined to deal with the common good. The story has to be believed. Now the key point is what “belief” means. Obviously Plato does not demand that the workers get the inner conviction that a deity truly mixed iron in their soul and gold in the soul of the rulers. It is enough that they sense it, that is, that they use their arms, their eyes, and their minds as if it were true. And they do even more so as this lie about “fitting” actually fits the reality of their condition. The ordering of social “occupations” works in the mode of this as if. Inequality works to the extent that one “believes” it, that one goes on using one’s arms, eyes, and brains according to the distribution of the positions. This is what consensus means. And this is the way domination works.
From this point on, we can understand the signification of the science of inequality with which we were dealing at first. This science is a science of the verification of inequality, a verification of the verification that is performed by those who are subjected to it. The verification of the verification makes it more radical since it transforms the arbitrary story into a scientific demonstration. By the same token, it transforms the as if into an illusion. Plato said that the city should be organized as if the story of the division of the souls were true. Artisans did as if it were true by the very fact of doing their everyday job. But modern social science turned the practice of the as if into an illusion in their mind, an ideological delusion making them ignore the laws determining their condition. The method of inequality starts with the very distribution of the positions. There are two ways of doing so: Plato makes inequality a “story” that has to be believed in order to make inequality a reality. Modern social science makes inequality a reality and equality a goal to be reached from this starting point. But this simple dispositif is already the principle of an infinite reassertion of inequality. This is the point that was made as early as the 1820s by an extravagant French professor named Joseph Jacotot. At the time, all the progressive minds were concerned with the purpose of educating lower classes in order to make them move toward equality and take their part in modern society. Jacotot put the whole story upside down. He said that the method that pretends to move from inequality to equality is the way of perpetually reproducing inequality, since it continually makes the ignoramus lag behind the master. That is the bias of the pedagogical logic: the role of the schoolmaster is posited as the act of suppressing the distance between his knowledge and the ignorance of the ignorant. Unfortunately, in order to reduce the gap, he has to reinstate it ceaselessly. In order to replace ignorance with adequate knowledge, he must always run one step ahead of the ignorant and confirm the ignorance he is supposed to dismiss. By so doing, the presupposition that is at the core of the system is continually reproduced: the presupposition, namely, that there are two kinds of intelligence, or, in Platonic terms, two types of souls, iron souls that move in the darkness unless they are guided by golden souls who know the right path from darkness to light. Knowledge in fact means two things: it means the possession of this or that specific science, art, or practice, and it means the fact of occupying the position of one who knows. The master knows in two senses: because he knows grammar, arithmetic, or any other discipline, and because he occupies the position of the one who knows. And what the master knows is first and foremost the ignorance of the ignoramus. The same goes for the ignoramus: he knows what he has learned from the master and he knows that he would not know without the help of the master. In other words, his knowledge is a specific linkage of capacity and incapacity. If we translate the pedagogical logic in social terms, the artisan has the know-how of his job and he has—or he is supposed to have—the awareness that his lot in society is to perform his know-how for work that “does not wait” without caring for general issues about the organization of society. The progressive path from inequality to equality is entrapped in that logic, which is a logic of verification of inequality or what Jacotot calls a process of stultification that puts the subject that one is supposed to teach in the structural position of the ignoramus.
This means that there is no path from inequality to equality. There is either a path from equality to equality or a path from inequality to inequality. A method is always the verification of a presupposition and there are only two presuppositions: the presupposition of equality or the presupposition of inequality. What the presupposition of equality means is the rupture of the inegalitarian belief or inegalitarian knowledge. The name of this decision is emancipation. Emancipation is the decision to verify that there are not two kinds of souls or two kinds of intelligence. Intelligence is the same in all its operations and it belongs to everybody. All intelligences are equal, said Jacotot. This does not mean that all intellectual performances are equally valuable. This means that intelligence is the same in all its operations. The scientist constructing hypotheses and the young child listening and looking around proceed in the same basic way: they set out to discover what they don’t know yet by tying it to what they already know. Theirs is not a path from ignorance to knowledge. It is a path from an existing knowledge to further knowledge. The method of inequality supposes that you must start from this point and try to reach that point by following one step after the other. The method of equality supposes that you can start from any point and that there are multiple paths that can be constructed to get to another point and still another one that is not predictable. There is a multiplicity of paths, a multiplicity of ways of constructing one’s intellectual adventure, but a prior decision has to be made beforehand: the decision that one can do it because one participates in an intelligence that is the intelligence of anybody. Emancipation designates that prior decision to enact the capacity of anybody and verify it. There is no passage from ignorance to knowledge or from inequality to equality. Each situation can be dealt with either as an occasion for the verification of inequality or as an occasion for the verification of equality.
Jacotot had a pessimistic view about the possibilities of social change. He thought that only individuals could be emancipated so that they could live as equals in an unequal society. But this pessimistic view was turned upside down by the attempts of the workers who were his contemporaries to construct a world of equality within the world of inequality. Emancipation means that you must not wait to be taught about the mechanism of exploitation and domination. Such a mechanism is only too clear. What I called consensus means precisely the impossibility of ignoring it. Social emancipation began with the decision to ignore it. Ignoring it meant reconfiguring the way they occupied their space and time. Emancipation for those workers meant the attempt to get rid of the ways of being, seeing, saying, and doing that made them fit for their condition. What their texts first witness is the attempt to conquer the useless, the look of the aesthete, the language of the poet, or the time of the loiterer. It is the attempt to take the time that they “do not have” to go to the places where they are not supposed to have anything to do. There is no privileged starting point, said Jacotot. As a matter of fact, dissensus can start from an imperceptible modification of the forms of everyday experience. During the French Revolution of 1848, a revolutionary workers’ newspaper publishes the long description by a joiner of the working day of the jobber who is laying the floor of a rich house. We could think that a workers’ newspaper, in a time when revolutionary and counterrevolutionary forces are in open conflict, would have more urgent concerns. But precisely what is at work in this apparently plain description is a redescription, a reconfiguration of daily experience that invents a time and space of freedom and equality in the space and time where the jobber is exploited by a boss to build a house that he will never live in. To understand how it works, I quote a brief extract of his narration: “Believing himself at home, he loves the arrangement of a room, so long as he has not finished laying the floor. If the window opens out on a garden or commands a view of a picturesque horizon, he stops his arms and glides in imagination toward the spacious view to enjoy it better than the possessors of the neighbouring residences.”1
* * *
Dissensus starts with a new belief: the joiner believes he is at home in the place where he is exploited. He enjoys the perspective through the window better than the possessors of the neighboring residences. In his Critique of Judgement, Kant made an apparently paradoxical statement about the disinterested character of the aesthetic judgement. He said that if I am asked whether I find this palace beautiful, I must let go of any “social” concern about the sweat of the workers that has been spent for serving the luxury of the rich and focus only on the form I am looking at. Aesthetic judgement is disinterested, which means that it does not look at its object as an object of knowledge or an object of desire. It is a power to appreciate appearance as such, and since this power has nothing to do with the reality of the object, it can be shared by anybody at all. That definition of the aesthetic judgement as “disinterested” judgement that can be shared by everybody has often been denounced as a typically idealistic view. A French sociologist, Pierre Bourdieu, devoted six hundred pages demonstrating that it denies social reality, which is that each class has the form of taste that befits its condition. But the core of emancipation is precisely the possibility of denying this kind of reality, the possibility of breaking the link between a social occupation and a mental equipment. The practice of dissensus actually started with the possibility of forgetting reality in favor of appearance and of casting a “disinterested” look on a building that is no longer an object of desire and frustration. The description made by the joiner gives that allegedly “idealistic” idea quite a materialistic meaning. The laborer stops his arms in order to let his eyes take possession of the place. His “disinterested” look means a disjunction between the activity of the hands and the activity of the eyes. We can call it an aesthetic experience. An aesthetic experience is not the experience of the aesthete enjoying art for art’s sake. Quite the contrary, it is a redistribution of the sensible, a dissociation of the body of the Platonic artisan whose eyes were supposed to focus only on the work of his arms. It is a way of taking the time he does not have. This is what emancipation first means: an exercise of equality that is an experience of dissociation of the body, space, and time of work.
This exercise of equality has the apparently paradoxical effect of making the worker “less aware” of exploitation. The text of the joiner spells out very clearly this dialectic of emancipation: since no look of a master precipitates his movements, the jobber “believes” that his powers are his own. He does not even hesitate to call this belief a “delusion” and to tell the consequence of this delusion. As he puts it, “He believes he is obeying only the necessity of things, so much does his emancipation delude him. But the old society is there to treacherously sink its horrible scorpion claws into his being and ruin him before his time, deluding him about the excitement of the courage that he uses for the benefit of his enemy.” He seems then to confess that the mastery he has gained is a mere illusion that contributes to his exploitation at the moment and to his unemployment later. But things are immediately overturned: this countereffect, which results from his way of reframing the space and the time of the exercise of his force of labor, is the source of a new pleasure, the pleasure of a new freedom in which even unemployment becomes a choice. I quote him: “This worker draws secret pleasure from the very uncertainty of his occupation.” The surplus of physical force given for a short time to the powers of domination is exceeded by the surplus of freedom that has been gained for long in relation to the whole logic of domination. The same joiner invented for himself a countereconomy of everyday life, where all budget items—food, clothing, and the like—were calculated to both minimize expense and optimize freedom.
This is what dissensus means: dissociation between the know-how of a job and the awareness of a condition, between the exercise of the arms and the exercise of the eyes; it means the dismemberment of the worker’s body, which was accustomed to domination, a revolution in the very balance of pain and pleasure. One thing, of course, must be emphasized, namely, the very fact of his writing the “narration” of this “day at work,” the very fact of his getting into the world of writing. This is the point where aesthetics and politics mean the same thing. At the beginning of the Politics, Aristotle made the famous statement about man as a political animal. He said man is a political animal because he has the power of logos, the power of the speech that spells out issues of justice and injustice, while the other animals are restricted to the voice that expresses their feelings of pleasure and pain. I translated this statement by saying that man is a political animal because he is a literary animal. Now it is well known that the traditional distribution of the sensible has it that the major part of humankind is made of noisy animals, enclosed in the oral world of mere pain and pleasure. Therefore writing about this day at work did not mean expressing the pleasures and pains of the worker. It meant affirming himself as a literary animal. The power of the literary animal is the power of the sensible operation that is the preliminary condition of any justice: the possibility of exchanging a pain for another. This exchange is made possible by the appropriation of words, even in the form of a bad metaphor: the “scorpion claws” of exploitation. It is precisely this excess of the words that matters: exploitation has no scorpion claws. What matters is the very use of the metaphor, the very use of words that are not supposed to belong to the vocabulary of the everyday of the poor. Those words—the emancipated worker first found them in the random literature of the sheets of paper used by the grocers to wrap the vegetables, before getting to real books. In a letter to a friend, the same joiner tells him to “plunge into terrible readings” because, he says, “that will awaken passions in your wretched existence, and the laborer needs them to stand tall in the face of that which is ready to devour him.” What is needed in the process of emancipation is first and foremost passions. As has been well known since Plato, passion means a certain balance of pleasure and pain. What is provided by writing and reading is a new way, a human way, of feeling pleasure and pain. This is why the “terrible readings” he recommends to his friends are not books describing the horrors of capitalism and the wretched condition of the poor. On the contrary, he recommends to him the books of the great romantic writers. Those books told the misfortunes of characters whose sorrow was that of not having a place and an occupation in society, of being born for no definite job or task, of having “nothing to do” out of their life. This was not the case of those workers, indeed: they suffered from the contrary, from the fact of having a place in society, of being born for a definite way of living and doing and being unable to escape that necessity. But this is what literature is about: exchanging one’s pain for another’s pain. And this is what those workers needed: exchanging their pain for another’s pain; making their voice not the voice of their condition but the voice of anybody, the expression of the capacity of anybody, confronting the social distribution of capacities and incapacities. The same goes for those “terrible readings” as for the reframing of the time and space of labor operated by the joiner: those forms of “aesthetic experience” do not work by providing definite messages or conveying specific forms of energy. They work by disrupting the way in which bodies fit their functions and destinations.
That disruption started with what was the very condition for reading and writing, namely, using for them a time that was normally dedicated to sleep. The very core of the distribution of the sensible is the division of night and day. This division is the least escapable partition of time, the least escapable separation between those who can and cannot play with it. The division has it that those who work all day long must sleep during the night to restore their force and go back to work heartedly the following day. This is why the core of emancipation was the intellectual decision and the physical attempt to break this circle, to put off as long as possible the entry into sleep and use this time for reading, writing, and discussing, for composing workers’ newspapers or poetry, if not both of them. The core of the process of emancipation could be located in that quasi-imperceptible interruption of the normal round of work and repose, allowing those workers to both prepare for the future and live in the present the suspension of the hierarchy subordinating those dedicated to manual labor to those dedicated to the task of thinking. Emancipated workers were workers who constructed for themselves in the here and now a new body and a new soul, the body or the soul of those fitted for no specific occupation, but who put into work the capacities of seeing and speaking, thinking and doing that belong to no class in particular, that belong to anybody. It is this affirmation that linked the apparently harmless practice of writing poetry to the creation of workers’ newspapers and the capacity to build cooperatives of workers, republican barricades, and the organizations for class war. As emancipation entails a reconfiguration of the sensible world, it dismisses the classical oppositions between the means and the ends. The time of emancipation creates no opposition between the present and the future, in the same way as it creates no opposition between lived experience and strategic designs or between the discovery of private life and the construction of collective forms of life. This is why this apparently plain description of the day-at-work of a solitary joiner was at its right place in a worker’s journal in a time of revolution. A workers’ journal is not the expression of the workers’ sufferings and demands. It is a break away from the old distribution of the sensible that divides humankind in two categories: those who can only shout to express their pains and complaints, and those who are able to discuss matters of justice concerning the whole community; those who are enclosed in the circle of so-called oral culture and those who live in the universe of writing. It is the affirmation of their capacity to reconstruct their world of experience, therefore to take their part in the global reconfiguration of the social world. A political capacity is the product of an aesthetic revolution. An aesthetic revolution is not a revolution in the arts. It is a revolution in the distribution of the forms and capacities of experience that this or that social group can share. Those forms of “aesthetic experience,” those forms of appropriation of the power of words, do not work by providing definite messages or conveying specific forms of energy. They work by disrupting the way in which bodies fit their functions and destinations. They don’t frame a collective body. Instead, they produce a multiplicity of folds and gaps in the fabric of common experience that change the cartography of the perceptible, the thinkable, and the feasible. As such, they allow for new modes of political construction of common objects and new possibilities of collective enunciation. The aesthetic effect is an effect of dis-identification. As such, it is political because political subjectivization proceeds via a process of dis-identification. The “voice of the workers” is the voice of workers who no longer feel and speak the way they did as dominated workers, when they were verifying the inequality that pinned them down to their place.
* * *
This is what I call a verification of equality, the implementation of a method of equality: a way of reconstructing a given form of everyday sensible experience so as to tip the balance of equality and inequality that is at work in every situation. Now I’d like to emphasize a key aspect of this method. In order to construct his new gaze, the joiner had to borrow the perspective and the gaze that were the privilege of the masters or of the artists. In order to voice his experience in a newspaper that is the voice of the workers, he had to exchange the everyday pain of those who are exploited at work for the immaterial pain of the literary characters who have “nothing to do” in society. He had to cross the boundaries separating forms of experience, modes of visibility, and also usages of language—such as the boundary separating the language of everyday experience and the language of literature or the boundaries separating literary fiction, social, knowledge and political statement. The method of equality goes across the boundaries of genres and levels of discourse. Now my point is that this condition for a verification of equality is also the condition for the discourse that sets out to make sense of that verification. It has to verify equality itself, that is to say, it has to refuse to set itself in a genre or level of discourse different from the discourse it is dealing with. It has to practice what I called a poetics of knowledge.
A poetics of knowledge does not mean that all knowledge is mere fiction. It has nothing to do with any kind of skepticism or relativism in relation to truth. On the contrary, it means that, to deal with the truth of a discourse, we must turn down the position of the scientist and reinscribe one’s descriptions and arguments in the equality of common language and the common capacity of thinking, the common capacity to invent stories and arguments. This means that we have to undo the logic of inequality that is at work in the discourse of science, that is, in the discourse of the disciplines that purport to make sense of those narrations. For those disciplines, “making sense” of a discourse means “giving the meaning of it” or explaining it. By grabbing hold of the narrative of the joiner, the sociologist or the social historian undoes his egalitarian performance. They annul the dissociation between the gaze and the arms of the joiner. They replace it with another one, an inegalitarian one: they draw a line of separation between what the phrases of the joiner say and what they mean, between their raw materiality and the social situation that they express. By so doing, they deny this discourse the possession of its own sense. For instance, social history restages the egalitarian operation by which the joiner reframed the place and job involved in his work. It explains it as the expression of the ambiguous situation and contradictory consciousness of the artisans of his time. Cultural sociology, for its part, explains his way of borrowing the writing of the writers and the feelings of their characters as the mark of his being ensnared in the forms of dominant culture. It turns the “disinterested” look into a philosophical and petty-bourgeois illusion that can only cheat the poor artisan, and so on and so forth. Disciplinary discourses then reinstate the boundary between two ways of using language: a way of using it to express a situation, and a way of using it to explain what this situation is and why it expresses itself in this or that way. They reinstate the presupposition of inequality between two uses of language, two kinds of intelligence, and two classes of souls. They don’t do so by any kind of malevolence. They do so because the presupposition of inequality is the condition of their exercise. They want, for the sake of their own validity, what Plato wanted for the sake of good social order: that the bodies composing society have the perceptions, sensations, and thoughts that correspond to their space and time, to their situation and their occupation. In order to establish themselves as scientific disciplines, they have to cut inside the fabric of common thought and common language to divide it in two parts: on one side, modes of thought and language that are the “object” of science; on the other one, modes of thought and language that are the forms of scientific description and argumentation. A discipline, in effect, is not merely the exploitation of a territory and the definition of a set of methods appropriate to a certain domain or a certain type of object. The very division between disciplines is first and foremost a way to say, you must not go there, unless you have the qualification for doing so. It inscribes the presupposition of competence or incompetence in the very landscape of the perceptible and the thinkable. The so-called division of labor between disciplines is in reality a war. It is a war for fixing boundaries, starting with the strategic boundary separating those who know from those who don’t know.
A poetics of knowledge thus is a practice of “indisciplinary” thinking. It refuses the “disciplinary” logic, its alleged specialization in fields, objects, and methods and the presupposition of the separation between those who know and those who don’t know. The poetics of knowledge starts from the presupposition of equality. The presupposition of equality does not claim that all discourses are equally valuable. It claims that there is a capacity for thinking that does not belong to any special group, a capacity that can be attributed to anybody. There is therefore a way of looking at all forms of discourse from the point of view of that capacity. This means that no positive boundary severs the field of sociology from the field of philosophy, or the field of history from the field of literature, and so on. All disciplines contend that they have their objects and the methods fitting them. The poetics of knowledge responds to this: your objects belong to everybody, your methods belong to anybody. They are made of narrations and descriptions that are told in a language that is the language of anybody and of arguments that are relevant to the intelligence of anybody. This also means that no positive boundary separates the texts that make up the discourse of science from those that are merely the objects of science. Ultimately no positive boundary separates those who are fit for thinking from those who are not fit for that. What we deal with are different performances of the “literary animal.” To make sense of them, the point is not “explaining” them. It is weaving a fabric of language within which they can experience egalitarian connections with other performances situated in different historical contexts pertaining to different fields. This is what I decided to do, for my part: to weave a kind of poetic fabric of writing that was not identifiable either with philosophy or with history, with science or with literature. I was dealing with a material made of workers’ pamphlets, poems, letters, and narratives as well. I decided to extract those texts from the context of social history, in which they were treated as expressions of a certain workers’ culture. Those texts were dealing with matters of work, time and space, voice and speech, visibility and invisibility. They were dealing with issues of capacity and incapacity, of who is able or unable to decide about matters of work and community. So they were narrations, statements, and arguments about the distribution of the sensible and interventions in that distribution. As such, they could be connected with other narratives and other interventions, borrowed from literary or philosophical texts, in other times and other contexts. Plato wrote about the necessity for workers to stay at their place because work does not wait. He explained that those workers had to do it because they were born with the aptitudes fitting that life. Nineteenth-century workers, for their part, wrote about the possibility or impossibility of escaping the constraint of time and the kind of life for which workers were born. Plato and those workers did not live in the same time and the same kind of society, nor are they dealing with the same kind of work, for sure. Nevertheless it was possible to make the hypothesis that they were dealing with one common issue, namely, the relation between conditions and capacities, between being in a certain time and space and being endowed with certain capacities and incapacities. It was possible to verify it by stepping across the differences of times, genres, and levels. This is an exercise in the method of equality that draws the treatise of the philosopher, the verse of the poet, the narration of the historian, and the article of the worker out of their “specific” territory and status and considers them as performances of speaking beings about what it means to be a speaking being. The poetics of knowledge gets to the point where even the statement of inequality must be formulated in an egalitarian way. This is the case for the Platonic statement about the inequality of the souls. It must be told as a story. It is when we speak of truth, Plato claims in the Phaedrus, that we are most obliged to say the truth. It is at that point also that he has recourse to the most extravagant tale: he tells us that the hierarchy of conditions rests on a hierarchy of souls and that such hierarchy depends on their respective capacity to follow the divine charioteer and look at divine beauty while traveling in the plain of truth. Those who have seen more fall into the bodies of philosophers or kings, those who have seen less into the bodies of artisans, peasants, or sophists. In this way, the social hierarchy is tantamount to the hierarchy of knowledge. But this equation, which most implacably prescribes the distribution of conditions, identities, and competences, can be told precisely only in the genre of discourse that denies any hierarchy, the genre of discourse that is practiced by the most “ignorant” ones, the genre of the tale. When it comes to truth and more particularly to the relation of truth to social hierarchy, all hierarchies of genres and levels of discourse are abolished. The poetics of knowledge deals with this knot between equality and inequality, it deals with the way in which it is tied and untied to the advantage of equality or inequality. It does not purport to provide a better knowledge than the knowledge provided by the disciplines. Rather, it tries to question how this or that form of knowledge deals with the circulation of words by which human animals are pinned down to their place or get away from it. It does not purport to provide instructions or forms of energy for any specific struggle. Rather, it tries to foster forms of intellectual indiscipline, forms of sensitivity and intolerance toward the multiple ways in which the method of inequality is at work in arguments, stories, or images and most notably in those that purport to lead us on the path of equality.
This leads me back to my starting point: the way in which inequality was indefinitely reproduced in the process that was said to lead to a future of equality, that is, the way in which the idea and practice of emancipation have been historically blended with a quite different idea of domination and liberation and, in the end, subjected to it, the one that made emancipation the end point of a global process that could be handled only by those who knew the logic of social evolution and the way to put this knowledge at work. On this basis, emancipation was no longer conceived as the construction of new capacities. It was the promise of science to those whose illusory capacities could be nothing but the reverse side of their real incapacity. But the very logic of science was that of an endless deferment of the promise. The science that promised freedom was also the science of the total process whose effect is to endlessly generate its own ignorance. That is why it constantly had to set about deciphering deceptive images and unmasking the illusory forms of self-enrichment, which could only enclose individuals in the trap of illusion, subjection, and misery each time a bit more.
It might be said that this scenario of the promises of science is a scenario of another age, a scenario whose final death was recorded in 1989. We are said to live in a postmodern era in which the critique of domination and the narrative of the revolutionary promise have come to an end with all modernist scenarios and illusions. But what died in 1989 is the promise of emancipation linked with the endless critique of the illusions produced by the system of domination. It is the promise of equality linked with the method of eternally reproducing inequality, not the method itself. The method itself is still at work. Day after day, we are told about the ways in which the global system of domination grabs hold of us and cheats us. We are told about the illusions of freedom and equality that hide the reality of domination by global capitalism, about the progress of all the technologies of power and biopower that take control of our bodies and our minds, about the frenzy of consumption that enslaves us all to the law of the global market, about the empire of the spectacle that transforms any reality into illusion, and so on and so forth. All those themes were present in the culture of Western critical and progressive thought in the 1960s. At the time, they were supposed to provide those who challenged the system with weapons for their struggle. What happened in the meantime is that those themes have been severed from any horizon of emancipation. The demonstration of incapacity has been stripped of any promise of liberation through knowledge. On the contrary, it tends more and more to tell us why emancipation is impossible by depicting for us a world where the forces of domination are omnipotent, a world of narcissist individuals whose desires, even the desires of protest and rebellion, are entirely caught in the machine of domination, recuperated as instruments of subjection. The critique of domination ends up as a critique of liberation. In the end, the revolutionary denunciation of social mechanisms becomes the apocalyptic prophecy of the impending catastrophe. What remains the core of the method, through all its shifts and reversals, is the presupposition of inequality, the presupposition of the radical separation between a world doomed to ignorance and the very few who know about the way either toward a new society or toward an impending disaster.
I am certainly not willing to deny the force of all the machineries of domination today. Nor am I willing to propose any optimistic view of the future in reaction to that apocalyptic mood. My point is that any attempt at resisting those forces starts with the rejection of the assumptions of the method of inequality: the assumptions of the global process, the idea of the mechanism of domination as a mechanism of illusion, in short, the presupposition of inequality. The apocalyptic mood is a consequence of the very faith in a global process revealing in the end a truth hidden to its subjects. That is why a method of equality does not propose a countermodel of the future. It does not construct a model showing how to go from the present to an already-known goal. Rather, it insists on the division that is at work at every point of every process. There is no global process creating its own machinery and absorbing all rebellious energies. Rather, there is a multiplicity of forms and scenes of dissensus. Every situation can be cracked open on the inside, reconfigured in a different regime of perception and signification, altering the landscape of what can be seen and what can be thought, along with the field of the possible and the distribution of capacities and incapacities. The method of equality is at work everywhere at any time. It is true that it promises no definite future. But new horizons are not defined by the planning of the future. On the contrary, it is from the division at work in the present, from the inventions of the method of equality, that unpredictable futures can emerge.