The aura that continues to grace the name of Georg Lukács, even outside the Soviet bloc, he owes to the writings of his youth—to the volume of essays Soul and Form, to The Theory of the Novel, and to the studies collected as History and Class Consciousness, where, writing as a dialectical materialist, he first systematically applied the category of reification to philosophical problematics. Originally inspired by figures like Simmel and Kassner and then trained under the southwest-German school, he soon opposed psychological subjectivism with an objectivist philosophy of history that exercised significant influence. Through the depth and élan of its conception as well as the density and intensity of its presentation, extraordinary for its time, The Theory of the Novel in particular established a standard for philosophical aesthetics that still holds today. In the early 1920s, when Lukács’ objectivism yielded, not without initial conflicts, to official communist doctrine, he followed the Eastern custom and repudiated those writings. Misusing Hegelian motifs, he accepted the party hierarchy’s servile criticisms of him and for decades tried in his books and essays to accommodate his obviously indestructible intellectual powers to the dismal level of Soviet pseudo-intellectual production, which had in the meantime degraded the philosophy it mouthed to a mere means to the ends of domination. It is only on account of his early works, however, repudiated and condemned by his party, that anyone outside the Eastern bloc has paid attention to the things Lukács has published during the last thirty years, which include a thick book on the young Hegel, even though one still sensed the old talent in some of the individual works on nineteenth-century German realism, as for instance in his writings on Keller and Raabe. It was probably in his The Destruction of Reason that the destruction of Lukács’ own reason manifested itself most crassly. In that work the certified dialectician lumped together, most undialectically, all the irrationalist tendencies in recent philosophy under the category of reaction and fascism, without pausing to consider that in those tendencies—in contrast to academic idealism—thought was combating the very same reification of existence and thinking that Lukács was in the business of criticizing. For him, Nietzsche and Freud became fascists pure and simple, and he even managed to speak of Nietzsche’s “more than ordinary ability” in the tone of a provincial Wilhelminian schoolmaster. Under the guise of an ostensibly radical critique of society he smuggled back the most pitiful clichés of the conformism to which that critique had once been directed.
But the book Wider den missverstandenen Realismus* [literally, Against Misunderstood Realism], which came out in the West with Claassen Verlag in 1958, shows signs of a different attitude on the part of the seventy-five-year-old Lukács. The change is probably connected with the conflict in which Lukács became involved through his participation in the Nagy regime. Not only is there reference to the crimes of the Stalin era, but there is positive talk about a “general advocacy of the freedom to write,” a formulation that would previously have been unthinkable. Lukács discovers posthumous merit in his perennial opponent Brecht, and praises the latter’s “Ballade vom toten Soldaten” [“Ballad of the Dead Soldier”], which must be a cultural-bolshevist abomination in the eyes of the East German powers-that-be, as a work of genius. Like Brecht, Lukács would like to broaden the concept of socialist realism, which for decades has been used to strangle every unruly impulse, everything the apparatchiks find unintelligible and suspect, to make room in it for more than the most miserable trash. He ventures a timid opposition, crippled from the outset by a consciousness of his own impotence. His timidity is no mere tactic. Lukács as a person is above suspicion. But the conceptual structure to which he sacrificed his intellect is so constricted that it suffocates anything that would like to breathe more freely in it; the sacrifizio dell’intelletto does not leave the intellect unscathed. This puts Lukács’ obvious nostalgia for his early writings in a melancholy perspective. The “Lebensimmanenz des Sinnes” [“life-immanence of meaning”], from the Theory of the Novel, is back, but reduced to the dictum that life under the construction of socialism simply is meaningful—a dogma just right for a philosophical-sounding justification of the rosy positiveness required of art in the people’s republics. The book offers a sherbet—something between the so-called thaw and a renewed freeze. Despite emphatic protestations to the contrary, Lukács continues to share with the commissars of culture a subsumptive modus operandi which operates from above with labels like critical and socialist realism. Hegel’s critique of Kantian formalism in aesthetics is reduced to the oversimplified assertion that in modern art style, form, and technique are vastly overrated (see especially p. 19)—as if Lukács did not know that it is through these moments that art as knowledge is distinguished from scientific knowledge, that works of art which were indifferent to their mode of presentation would negate their own concept. What looks like formalism to Lukács aims, through the structuring of the elements in accordance with the work’s own formal law, at the same “immanence of meaning” that Lukács is pursuing, instead of forcing the meaning into the work from the outside by fiat, something he himself considers impossible and yet objectively defends. He willfully misinterprets the form-constitutive moments of modern art as accidentia, contingent additions to an inflated subject, instead of recognizing their objective function in the aesthetic substance. The objectivity he misses in modern art and which he expects from the material and its “perspectivist” treatment devolves upon the methods and techniques he would like to eliminate, which dissolve the purely material aspect and only thereby put it into perspective. He takes a neutral stance on the philosophical question whether the concrete substance of a work of art is in fact identical to the pure “reflection of objective reality” (101), an idol to which he clings with stubborn vulgar materialism. His own text certainly shows no respect for the norms of responsible presentation that his early writings helped to establish. No bearded privy councillor could pontificate about art in a manner more alien to it. He writes in the tone of one who is accustomed to the podium and permits no interruptions, one who does not shrink from lengthy digressions and has obviously renounced the sensitivity he criticizes as aestheticist, decadent, and formalistic, the very sensitivity that permits a relationship to art in the first place. While the Hegelian concept of the concrete rates high with Lukács, as it always did, especially when it is a question of holding literature to the depiction of empirical reality, his argumentation itself is largely abstract. His text is hardly ever subjected to the discipline of a specific work of art and its immanent problems. Instead, he issues decrees. The pedantry of his manner is matched by sloppiness in the details. Lukács does not shrink from such worn-out bits of wisdom as “Speaking is not the same thing as writing.” He repeatedly uses the expression Spitzenleistung [peak performance], which derives from the sphere of commerce and sports records, he calls the elimination of the distinction between abstract and concrete possibility “appalling” [verheerend], and he points out that “from Giotto on a new secularity…triumph [s] more and more over the allegorizing of an earlier period” (40). We whom Lukács would call decadent may seriously overvalue form and style, but so far that has preserved us from expressions like “from Giotto on,” just as it has preserved us from praising Kafka for being a “marvelous observer” (45). Nor will members of the avant-garde have spoken very often of the “series of extraordinarily numerous emotions which together combine to structure the inner life of man.” In the face of these peak performances, which follow one another as in the Olympics, one might well ask whether someone who writes like this, ignorant of the métier of the literature he treats so cavalierly, has any right to particpate in serious discussion of literary matters. But in the case of Lukács, who at one time could write well, one senses the method of justament—malice aforethought—at work in his mixture of pedantry and irresponsibility, the resentful will to write badly, which he believes will have the magical sacrificial force of demonstrating polemically that anyone who does otherwise and takes pains with his writing is a good-for-nothing. In any case, stylistic indifference is almost always a symptom of dogmatic rigidification of the content. The exaggerated lack of vanity in a presentation that thinks of itself as objective when in fact it is only failing to engage in self-reflection, only disguises the fact that the objectivity has been removed from the dialectical process along with the subject. The dialectic is paid lip service, but for this kind of thought the dialectic has been determined in advance. Thought becomes undialectical.
The core of the theory remains dogmatic. The whole of modern literature, except where it fits the formula of critical or socialist realism, is rejected and immediately stigmatized as decadent, a word of abuse that covers all the atrocities of persecution and extermination, and not only in Russia. The use of that conservative term is incompatible with the theory whose authority Lukács, like his superiors, would like to appropriate for his national community through it. Talk about decadence cannot be separated from its positive counterimage of a nature bursting with strength; natural categories are projected onto things that are socially mediated. The tenor of Marx and Engels’ critique of ideology, however, is directed against precisely that. Even associations with Feurbach’s notion of healthy sensuality would hardly have procured this social Darwinist term access to their texts. Even in the rough draft of the Grundrisse of the Critique of Political Economy dating from 1857–58, that is, during the phase in which Capital was being written, we find the following:
As much, then, as the whole of this movement appears as a social process, and as much as the individual moments of this movement arise from the conscious will and particular purposes of individuals, so much does the totality of the process appear as an objective interrelation, which arises spontaneously from nature; arising, it is true, from the mutual influence of conscious individuals on one another, but neither located in their consciousness, nor subsumed under them as a whole. Their own collisions with one another produce an alien social power standing above them, produce their mutual interaction as a process and power independent of them…. The social relation of individuals to one another as a power over the individuals which has become autonomous, whether conceived as a natural force, as chance or in whatever other form, is a necessary result of the fact that the point of departure is not the free social individual.1
This kind of critique does not stop at the sphere in which the affectively charged illusion of naturalness on the part of what is social dies the hardest, the sphere in which all the indignation about degeneracy arises: that of relations between the sexes. Somewhat earlier, Marx had reviewed G. F. Daumer’s Religion des neuen Weltalters [Religion of the New Age] and skewered the following passage: “Nature and women are what is truly divine, in contrast to humanity and man…. The devotion of the human to the natural, of the masculine to the feminine is the genuine and the only true humility and self-sacrifice, the highest and in fact the only virtue and piety there is.” To which Marx adds the following commentary: “We see here how the insipid ignorance of this speculative founder of a religion is transformed into a very pronounced cowardice. In the face of the historical tragedy that approaches him menacingly, Herr Daumer flees to what is allegedly nature, that is, into a stupid idyll of rural life, and preaches the cult of woman in order to disguise his own womanish resignation.”2 Wherever there is blustering about decadence this flight is being repeated. Lukács is forced into it by a situation in which social injustice continues after it has been officially declared to have been eliminated. The responsibility is shifted from a situation for which human beings are responsible to nature or a degeneracy conceived as its opposite in terms of the same model. Granted, Lukács tried to weasel out of the contradiction between Marxist theory and official Marxism by forcibly turning the concepts of healthy and sick art back into social concepts:
Men’s relationships are subject to historical change, and intellectual and emotional evaluations of these relationships change accordingly. Recognition of this fact, however, does not imply an acceptance of relativism. In a particular time, a certain human relationship is progressive, another is reactionary. Thus we find that the conception of what is socially healthy is equally and simultaneously the basis of all really great art, for what is socially healthy becomes a component of man’s historical self-awareness.3
The weakness of this attempt is obvious: If it is a question of historical relationships, words like sick and healthy should be avoided altogether. They have nothing to do with the progress/reaction dimension; they are brought in purely for the sake of their demagogic appeal. The dichotomy between healthy and sick, moreover, is as undialectical as that between a rising and a declining bourgeoisie, which itself derives its norms from a bourgeois consciousness that did not keep pace with its own development. I will not deign to stress the fact that Lukács groups completely disparate figures under the concepts of decadence and avantgardism (for him they are the same thing)—not only Proust, Kafka, Joyce, and Beckett but also Benn, Jünger, and perhaps Heidegger; and as theoreticians, Benjamin and myself. It is all too easy to resort to the currently fashionable ploy of pointing out that something under attack does not really exist but it actually several divergent things, in order to soften the concept in question and evade the argument being advanced with a gesture that says “that doesn’t apply to me.” At the risk, then, of simplifying by my opposition to simplification, I will stay with the central thread of Lukács’ argument and not differentiate among those he attacks any more than he does, except where he makes gross distortions.
Lukács’ attempt to provide the Soviet verdict on modern literature—that is, literature that shocks the naive-realistic normal consciousness—with a good philosophical conscience uses a restricted set of instruments, all of Hegelian origin. For his attack on avant-garde literature as deviation from reality, Lukács works over the distinction between “abstract” and “real” possibility:
These two categories, their interrelation and opposition, are rooted in life itself. Potentiality—seen abstractly or subjectively—is richer than actual life. Innumerable possibilities for man’s development are imaginable, only a small percentage of which will be realized. Modern subjectivism, taking these imagined possibilities for actual complexity of life, oscillates between melancholy and fascination. When the world declines to realize these possibilities, this melancholy becomes tinged with contempt. (21–22)
The percentage notwithstanding, one cannot simply shrug off this objection. When Brecht, for instance, tried, using an infantile simplification, to crystallize out the pure archetypes, so to speak, of fascism as gangsterdom by portraying the resistible dictator Arturo Ui as the representative of an imaginary and apocryphal cauliflower trust rather than the representative of the groups with the greatest economic power, the unrealistic device did not work to the advantage of his play. As the enterprise of a criminal group that is to a certain extent socially extraterritorial and thereby easily “stoppable,” “resistible” at will, fascism loses its horror, which is the horror of its large-scale social significance. The caricature thereby loses its force and becomes silly by its own criterion: the political rise of the petty criminal loses its plausibility even within the play itself. Satire that does not characterize its object adequately loses its bite, even as satire. But the requirement of pragmatic fidelity can apply only to the basic experience of reality and to the membra disjecta of the motifs from which the writer constructs his conception—in the case of Brecht, then, to his knowledge of the empirical relationships between economics and politics and the accuracy of the initial social facts, but not to what becomes of them within the work. Proust, in whose work the most precise “realistic” observation is so intimately connected with the formal aesthetic law of involuntary memory, provides the most striking example of the unity of pragmatic fidelity and—in terms of Lukács’ categories—unrealistic method. If the intensity of this fusion is diminished; if “concrete possibility” is interpreted in the sense of an unreflected overall realism that rigidly contemplates the object from the outside, while the aspect that is antithetical to the material is tolerated only as “perspective,” that is, only as something that lets meaning shine through, without being able to force its way into the center of the portrayal, into the elements of reality, the result of a misuse of Hegelian distinctions in the service of a traditionalism whose aesthetic backwardness is the index of its historical untruth.
The central charge Lukács raises, however, is that of ontologism, a charge through which he tries to link all of avant-garde literature to Heidegger’s archaistic existential categories. Granted, Lukács himself, in line with current fashion, accepts the notion that one must ask “What is man?” (19), without being put off by the direction the question implies, but at least he modifies the question by referring to Aristotle’s familiar definition of man as a social animal. From that definition he derives the hardly debatable assertion that the “human significance,” the “specific individuality” of the characters in great literature “cannot be separated from the context in which they were created” (19). “The ontological view governing the image of man in the work of leading modernist writers,” he continues, “is the exact opposite of this. Man, for these writers, is by nature solitary, asocial, unable to enter into relationships with other human beings” (20). He supports this with a rather silly statement by Thomas Wolfe, one which is in any case not definitive for his literary work, about man’s solitude as an inescapable fact of his existence. But certainly Lukács, who claims to think in radically historical terms, ought to see that in an individualistic society that solitude is socially mediated and essentially historical in substance. In Baudelaire—and all categories like decadence, formalism, and aestheticism ultimately date back to him—it was not a question of an invariant human essence, of man’s solitude or “thrownness” [Geworfenheit] but of the essence of modernity. In Baudelaire’s poetry essence is not some abstract thing in itself but something social. The idea that is objectively dominant in his work aims at what is historically most advanced, what is newest, as the Ur-phenomenon it wants to conjures up; it is, to use Benjamin’s term, a “dialectical image,” not an archaic image. Hence the Tableaux Parisiens. Even in Joyce, the foundation of the work is not the timeless man-as-such that Lukács would like to assume it is but a most historical man. All the Irish folklore that appears in it notwithstanding, Joyce does not create a fictional mythology beyond the world he represents but rather tries to conjure up that world’s essence, or its essential horror, by mythifying it, as it were, through the stylistic principle the Lukács of today holds in contempt. One is almost tempted to judge the stature of avant-garde writing by the criterion of whether historical moments become essential in them as historical moments rather than being flattened out into timelessness. Presumably Lukács would dismiss the use of concepts like essence and image in aesthetics as idealistic. But their status in the realm of art is fundamentally different from their status in philosophies of essence or archetypes, from any refurbished Platonism. The most fundamental weakness of Lukács’ position may be that he cannot maintain this distinction and applies categories that refer to the relationship between consciousness and reality to art as though they simply meant the same thing there. Art exists within reality, has its function in it, and is also inherently mediated with reality in many ways. But nevertheless, as art, by its very concept it stands in an antithetical relationship to the status quo. Philosophy reflected this in the term “aesthetic semblance.” Even Lukács will hardly be able to get around the fact that the content of works of art is not real in the same sense as social reality. If this distinction were eliminated all work in aesthetics would lose its foundation. But art’s illusory character, the fact that it became qualitatively distinct from the immediate reality from which it sprang in the form of magic, is neither its ideological fall from grace nor an index imposed upon it from the outside, as though it were merely reproducing the world without claiming to be immediately real itself. This kind of subtractive conception would be a mockery of dialectics. Rather, the difference between empirical existence and art concerns the intrinsic structure of the latter. If art offers essences, “images,” that is not an idealistic sin; the fact that some artists were adherents of idealist philosophies says nothing about the substance of their works. Rather, vis à vis what merely exists, art itself—where it does not betray its own nature by merely duplicating it—has to become essence, essence and image. Only thereby is the aesthetic constituted; only thereby and not by gazing at mere immediacy, does art become knowledge, does it, that is, do justice to a reality that conceals its own essence and suppresses what the essence expresses for the sake of a merely classificatory order of things. Only in the crystallization of its own formal law and not in a passive acceptance of objects does art converge with what is real. In art knowledge is aesthetically mediated through and through. In art even what Lukács considers to be solipsism and a regression to the illusionary immediacy of the subject does not signify a denial of the object, as it does in bad epistemologies, but rather aims dialectically at reconciliation with the object. The object is taken into the subject in the form of an image rather than turning to stone in front of it like an object under the spell of the alienated world. Through the contradiction between this object that has been reconciled within an image, that is, spontaneously assimilated into the subject, and the real, unreconciled object out there in the world, the work of art criticizes reality. It represents negative knowledge of reality. In analogy to a current philosophical expression, we might speak of “aesthetic difference” from existence: only by virtue of this difference, and not by denying it, does the work of art become both work of art and correct consciousness. A theory of art that refuses to acknowledge this is philistine and ideological at the same time.
Lukács contents himself with Schopenhauer’s insight that the principle of solipsism is “only really viable in philosophical abstraction,” and even then “only with a measure of sophistry” (21). But his argument defeats itself: if solipsism cannot be maintained, if what it initially “bracketed out,” to use the phenomenological expression, is reproduced within it, then there is no need to fear it as a stylistic principle either. For objectively, in their works, the avant-garde writers moved beyond the position Lukács ascribes to them. Proust decomposes the unity of the subject by means of the subject’s introspection: the subject is ultimately transformed into an arena in which objective entities manifest themselves. Proust’s individualistic work becomes the opposite of what Lukács criticizes it as being: it becomes anti-individualistic. The monologue intérieur, the worldlessness of modern art that Lukács is so indignant about, is both the truth and the illusion of a free-floating subjectivity. The truth, because in a world that is everywhere atomistic, alienation rules human beings and because—as we may concede to Lukács—they thereby become shadows. But the free-floating subject is an illusion, because the social totality is objectively prior to the individual; that totality becomes consolidated and reproduces itself in and through alienation, the social contradiction. The great avant-garde works of art cut through this illusion of subjectivity both by throwing the frailty of the individual into relief and by grasping the totality in the individual, who is a moment in the totality and yet can know nothing about it. In Joyce, Lukács thinks, Dublin, and in Kafka and Musil, the Hapsburg Monarchy, can be felt—hors programme, so to speak—as an atmospheric “backcloth” to the action (21), but that, he says, is a mere by-product; for the sake of his thema probandum, he turns the negative epic abundance that accumulates, the substantial, into a secondary issue. The concept of atmosphere is completely inappropriate for Kafka. It is derived from an impressionism that Kafka supersedes precisely through his objective tendency, which aims at historical essence. Even in Beckett—perhaps in Beckett most of all—where all concrete historical elements seem to have been eliminated and only primitive situations and modes of behavior are tolerated, the ahistorical facade is the provocative antithesis of the Being-as-such idolized by reactionary philosophy. The primitivism which is the abrupt point of departure for his works reveals itself to be the final phase of a regression; this is only too clear in Endgame, where a terrestrial catastrophe is presupposed, as from the far reaches of the self-evident. Beckett’s Ur-humans are the last humans. He makes thematic something that Horkheimer and I, in the Dialectic of Enlightenment, called the convergence between a society totally in the grips of the culture industry and the reactions of an amphibian. The substantive content of a work of art can consist in the accurate and tacitly polemical representation of emerging meaninglessness, and that content can be lost when it is stated positively and hypostatized as existing, even if this occurs only indirectly, through a “perspective,” as in the didactic antithesis between the right and the wrong way to live in Tolstoy’s work after Anna Karenina. Lukács’ old pet idea of an “immanence of meaning” refers to the same dubious preoccupation with the status quo that his own theory says ought to be destroyed. Conceptions like Beckett’s, however, are objectively polemical. Lukács falsifies them in describing them as the “adoption of perversity and idiocy as types of the condition humaine” (32)—following the practice of the film censor who blames the presentation for what it presents. Lukács’ conflation of Beckett with the cult of Being in particular, or even with Montherlant’s inferior version of vitalism (32), demonstrates his blindness to the phenomenon under consideration. It derives from the fact that he stubbornly refuses to accord literary technique its rightful central place. Instead, he sticks indefatigably to what is narrated. But it is only through “technique” that the intention of what is presented—to which Lukács assigns the concept, itself disreputable, of “perspective”—can be realized in literature at all. One would like to know what would become of Greek tragedy, which Lukács, like Hegel, canonizes, if one made its plots, which were available to everyone, the criterion of its success. Composition and style are no less constitutive of the traditional and—in terms of Lukács’ schema—“realistic” novel: Flaubert. Now that mere reliance on empirical reality has degenerated to superficial reportage, the relevance of technique has increased tremendously. Constructive technique can hope for immanent mastery of the contingency of what is merely individual, the contingency Lukács rails against. Lukács does not draw the full consequences from the insight that emerges in the last chapter of his book: that to resolutely take a presumably more objective standpoint is of no help against chance. Lukács ought to be genuinely familiar with the idea of the crucial significance of the development of the technical forces of production. Of course this idea was developed with reference to material and not intellectual production. But can Lukács seriously oppose the idea that artistic technique too develops according to a logic of its own? Can he talk himself into believing that to affirm abstractly that different aesthetic criteria would hold automatically and en bloc in a different society is enough to cancel out the development of technical forces of production and restore other forces to validity, older forces that the inherent logic of the matter has made outmoded? Under the dictates of socialist realism does he not become the advocate of a doctrine of invariance that differs from the one he rightly rejects only in being cruder?
Although Lukács, following the tradition of classical philosophy, rightly conceives art as a form of knowledge and does not contrast it to science and scholarship as something purely irrational, in doing so he becomes trapped in the same mere immediacy that he shortsightedly accuses avant-garde production of: the immediacy of the established fact. Art does not come to know reality by depicting it photographically or “perspectivally” but by expressing, through its autonomous constitution, what is concealed by the empirical form reality takes. Even the assertion that the world is unknowable, which Lukács never tires of faulting in authors like Eliot or Joyce, can become a moment of knowledge, knowledge of the gulf between the overwhelming and unassimilatable world of objects, on the one hand, and experience, which glances helplessly off that world, on the other. Lukács simplifies the dialectical unity of art and science so that it becomes a pure identity, as though works of art merely anticipated something perspectivally which the social sciences then diligently confirmed. What essentially distinguishes the work of art as knowledge sui generis from scientific or scholarly knowledge is that nothing empirical remains unaltered, that the contents become objectively meaningful only when fused with subjective intention. Although Lukács differentiates his realism from naturalism, he fails to take into account that if the distinction is intended seriously, realism will necessarily be amalgamated with the subjective intentions he would like to banish from it. The opposition between realistic and “formalistic” approaches which he inquisitorially elevates to a criterion is simply unsalvageable. On the one hand, the formal principles that are anathema to Lukács as being unrealistic and idealistic prove to have an objective aesthetic function; conversely, the early nineteenth-century novels he unhesitatingly advances as paradigmatic, Dickens and Balzac, are not so realistic after all. Marx and Engels may have considered them realistic in their polemic against the commercial romanticism flourishing at their time. Today not only have archaic pre-bourgeois features become evident in both novelists, but Balzac’s whole Comédie humaine proves to be an imaginative reconstruction of an alienated reality, that is, a reality that can no longer be experienced by the subject.4 In this regard it is not so very different from the avant-garde victims of Lukács’ class justice, except that Balzac, in accordance with the sense of form in his works, considered his monologues to represent the fullness of the world, whereas the great novelists of the twentieth century enclose the fullness of their worlds within the monologue. Accordingly, Lukács’ approach collapses. His idea of “perspective” inevitably degenerates to the very thing he so desperately tries to distinguish it from in the last chapter of his book, to an engrafted politics or, in his words, “agitation.” His conception is aporetic. He cannot rid himself of his awareness that, aesthetically, social truth lives only in autonomously formed works of art. But today, in the concrete work of art, this autonomy necessarily brings with it everything that he can no more tolerate now than he could before, given the dictates of the prevailing communist doctrine. The hope that regressive artistic techniques which are inadequate in immanent aesthetic terms would legitimate themselves by assuming a different position in a different social system, that is, legitimate themselves from outside their immanent logic, is pure superstition. The fact that what under socialist realism has been declared an advanced state of consciousness serves up only the crumbling and insipid remnants of bourgeois art forms cannot simply be dismissed as an epiphenomenon the way Lukács dismisses it; it requires an objective explanation. Socialist realism originated not in a socially sound and healthy world, as the communist clerics would like to think, but in the backwardness of consciousness and of the social forces of production in their provinces. They use the thesis of a qualitative break between socialism and bourgeois society only to misrepresent that backwardness, which has long since become unmentionable, as something more progressive.
Lukács combines the charge of ontologism with the charge of individualism, that is, a standpoint of unreflected solitude, on the model of Heidegger’s theory of “thrownness” from Being and Time. He criticizes the notion that the literary work proceeds from the subject in its contingency, on the same grounds on which Hegel once—stringently enough—criticized the notion that philosophy proceeds from the sense certainty of the individual. But precisely because this immediacy is already internally mediated, when given coherent form in the work of art it contains the moments Lukács claims are lacking, while on the other hand the literary subject must proceed from what is closest to it for the sake of the anticipated reconciliation of the material world with consciousness. Lukács extends his denunciation of individualism to Dostoevski. His Notes from the Underground, Lukács says, is “perhaps the first authentic description of the [decadent] isolation of modern bourgeois man” (62). But by coupling “decadent” and “isolation,” Lukács reevaluates the atomization that springs from the very principle of bourgeois society, making it a mere manifestation of decline. Furthermore, the word “decadent” suggests biological degeneration in individuals: a parody of the fact that this solitude presumably reaches back far beyond bourgeois society, for animals that live in herds are also, as Rudolf Borchardt said, a “lonely community”; the zoon politikon is something that has to be developed. Something that is a historical a priori of all modern art—and is transcended only where art acknowledges it in its full force—appears in Lukács as an error that could be avoided, or even a bourgeois delusion. Once Lukács turns to contemporary Russian literature, however, he discovers that the structural transformation he assumes did not take place. Except that that does not teach him to do without concepts like decadent solitude. In terms of the debate between conflicting positions, the position taken by the avant-garde writers he criticizes—in his earlier terminology, their “transcendental locus”—is historically mediated solitude, not ontological solitude. The ontologists of today all too readily accept ties that though ascribed to Being as such in fact endow all manner of heteronomous authorities with the semblance of eternity. In this regard they would get along quite well with Lukács. We must concede Lukács the point that, as an a priori of form, solitude is a mere illusion, that it is socially produced; it transcends itself once it reflects upon itself.5 But it is precisely here that the aesthetic dialectic turns against him. It is not up to the individual subject to go beyond a collectively determined solitude through his own choice and decision. That comes through clearly enough where Lukács settles accounts with the tendentiousness of the standardized Soviet novels. In general, reading his book, and especially the impassioned section on Kafka (49f.), one cannot escape the impression that he reacts to the literature he condemns as decadent the same way the legendary cab horse reacts to the sound of military music before it goes back to pulling its cart. To defend himself against its attractions, Lukács chimes in with the chorus of censors who have been hacking at what is “interesting” since Kierkegaard, whom Lukács himself classed with the avant-garde writers, if not since the uproar about Friedrich Schlegel and early Romanticism. That verdict should be reviewed. The fact that an idea or a depiction is “interesting” in character cannot simply be reduced to a matter of sensationalism and the intellectual marketplace, although of course they promoted the category. While not a guarantee of truth, that category has now become a necessary precondition of truth. It is what mea interest, what concerns the subject, as opposed to the subject being pieced off with the superior power of the powers that be, that is, with commodities.
It would be impossible for Lukács to praise what attracts him in Kafka and still put him on his index if he did not, like the skeptics of late Scholasticism, have a doctrine of two kinds of truth up his sleeve:
All this argues the superiority—historically speaking—of socialist realism (I cannot sufficiently emphasize that this superiority does not confer automatic success on each individual work of socialist realism). The reason for this superiority is the insights which socialist ideology, socialist perspective, make available to the writer: they enable him to give a more comprehensive and deeper account of man as a social being than any traditional ideology. (115)
In other words, artistic quality and the artistic superiority of social realism are two different things. What is valid in literary terms is distinguished from what is valid in terms of Soviet literature, which is to be dans le vrai through an act of grace, so to speak, on the part of the Weltgeist. This kind of double standard ill becomes a thinker who pathetically defends the unity of reason. But once he explains that that solitude is inevitable—and he almost acknowledges that it is prescribed by social negativity, by universal reification—and at the same time, in Hegelian fashion, becomes aware of its objective illusory character, then the inference is compelling that that solitude, taken to its logical conclusion, turns into its own negation, that when the solitary consciousness reveals itself in the literary work to be the hidden consciousness of all human beings, it has, potentially, to sublate itself. This is precisely what we see in works that are genuinely avant-garde. They become objectified through unqualified monadological immersion in their own formal laws, that is, aesthetically, and thereby mediated in their social basis as well. This alone gives Kafka, Joyce, Beckett, and the great works of modern music their power. The world’s hour has struck, and it resounds in their monologues: this is why they are so much more provocative than literature that simply depicts the world in communicative form. The fact that this kind of transition to objectivity remains contemplative and does not turn into action has its basis in a state of society in which the monadological condition continues on everywhere, concrete and ubiquitous, despite all assurances to the contrary. Moreover, the classicistically inclined Lukács could hardly expect works of art here and now to break through this contemplation. His proclamation of artistic quality is incompatible with a pragmatism that, when faced with advanced and responsible artistic production, contents itself with the summary verdict “bourgeois, bourgeois, bourgeois.”
Lukács cites, and states his agreement with, my work on the aging of the new music in order to then use my dialectical reflections, which are paradoxically similar to Sedlmayr,* against modern art and against my own intentions. This much we should grant him: “Only those thoughts are true which fail to understand themselves,”6 and no author owns the title to them. But Lukács’ argumentation does not in fact take the title away from me after all. The idea that art cannot establish itself as pure expression, which is directly equivalent to anxiety, was expressed in the Philosophy of Modern Music,7 even though I do not share Lukács’ official optimism with its view that historically speaking there is less cause for anxiety today, that the “decadent intelligentsia” has less to be afraid of. But going beyond the pure ostensive “this” of expression can mean neither instituting a thinglike style devoid of tension, something I accused the aging new music of, nor making a leap into a positivity that in the Hegelian sense is not substantial and not authentic and does not constitute form prior to any reflection.8 The implication of the aging of the new music is not a return to the already aged old music but the emphatic self-critique of the new. From the outset, however, the unvarnished depiction of anxiety was also more than that; it meant resistance through expression, through the power of an undeviating act of naming: the opposite of all the associations the abusive term “decadent” evokes. Lukács does credit the art he disparages with responding negatively to a negative reality, to the domination of the “abominable.” “But since,” he continues, “modernism portrays the distortion without critical detachment, indeed it devises stylistic techniques which emphasize the necessity of distortion in any kind of society, it may be said to distort distortion further. By attributing distortion to reality itself, modernism dismisses as ontologically irrelevant the counter-forces at work in reality” (75f.). The official optimism of countervailing forces and tendencies forces Lukács to suppress the Hegelian thesis that the negation of the negation—the “distortion of the distortion”—is the positive. It is only this thesis that can illuminate the truth of the fatally irrationalistic term “Vielschichtigkeit” [multi-layeredness] in art: in authentic modern works of art, the expression of suffering and pleasure in dissonance, a pleasure that Lukács disparages as sensationalism, “a delight in novelty for novelty’s sake” (105), are indissolubly linked. This must be understood in connection with the dialectic of the relationship between the aesthetic sphere and reality, something Lukács avoids. Since the work of art does not have something immediately real as its subject matter, it never says, as knowledge usually does: “this is so” [“es ist so”]. Instead, it says, “this is how it is” [“so ist es”]. Its logicity is not that of a statement with subject and predicate but that of immanent coherence: only in and through that coherence, through the relationship in which it places its elements, does it take a stance. Its antithetical relationship to empirical reality, which falls within it and into which it itself falls, consists precisely of the fact that, unlike intellectual forms that deal directly with reality, it never defines reality unequivocally as being one thing or another. It passes no judgments; it becomes a judgment when taken as a whole. The moment of untruth contained, as Hegel showed, in every individual judgment, because nothing is completely what the individual judgment says it to be, is corrected by art in that the work of art synthesizes its elements without any one of those elements being stated by any other: the notion of Aussage [message] currently in vogue has no relation to art. What art, as synthesis without judgment, loses in specificity regarding detail it regains through its greater justice to what judgment usually eliminates. The work of art becomes knowledge only as a totality, only in and through all its mediations, not in its individual intentions. Individual intentions cannot be abstracted from it, nor can it be judged by them. But this is precisely the principle on which Lukács proceeds, despite his protests against the certified novelists who proceed this way in their writing. While he is well aware of what is inadequate in their standardized products, his own philosophy of art has no defense against the same short circuit, the effects of which—an idiocy decreed from above—then horrify him.
Faced with the essential complexity of the work of art, which cannot be sloughed off as an accidental individual case, Lukács shuts his eyes. When he does look at specific literary works, he emphasizes what is right in front of him and thereby misses the import of the whole. He laments about an admittedly modest poem by Gottfried Benn which reads:
O Daß wir unsere Ururahnen wären.
Ein Klümpchen Schleim in einem warmen Moor.
Leben und Tod, Befruchtung und Gebären
glitte aus unseren stummen Säften vor.
Ein Algenblatt oder ein Dünenhügel,
vom Wind geformtes und nach unten schwer.
Schon ein Libellenkopf, ein Mövenflügel
wäre zu weit und litte schon zu sehr.
[Oh, that we were our Ur-Ur-ancestors.
A glob of slime in a warm bog.
Life and death, fecundation and parturition
would slide forth from our mute juices.
A strand of seaweed or a dune,
formed by the wind and heavy at the bottom.
Even the head of a dragonfly or the wing of a gull
would be going too far and would suffer too much.]
Lukács sees in this poem “the opposition of man as animal, as a primeval reality, to man as social being”—à la Heidegger, Klages, and Rosenberg—and ultimately a “glorification of the abnormal and…an undisguised anti-humanism” (32), whereas even if one identified the poem with its content completely, the last line indicts the higher level of individuation as suffering in Schopenhauerian fashion, and the yearning for the prehistoric era merely reflects the intolerable pressure of the present. The moralistic coloration of Lukács’ critical concepts is the same as that of his lamentations about subjectivistic “worldlessness,” as though the avant-garde writers had literally practiced what in Husserl’s phenomenology is called, grotesquely enough, the methodological annihilation of the world. Thus Lukács denounces Robert Musil: “Ulrich, the hero of his novel The Man Without Qualities, when asked what he would do if he were in God’s place, replies: ‘I would be compelled to abolish reality.’ The abolition of outward reality is the complement of a subjective existence ‘without qualities’ ” (25). Yet the sentence Lukács incriminates is obviously intended to convey despair, runaway Weltschmerz, love in its negative form. Lukács says nothing about all that and instead operates with a truly “unmediated,” completely unreflected concept of the normal and its complement, the notion of pathological distortion. Only a mental state blissfully purged of every trace of psychoanalysis can fail to recognize the connection between that normality and the social repression that proscribed the partial instincts. A critique of society that continues to talk unabashedly about the “normal” and the “perverse” is itself still under the spell of what it portrays as having been overcome. Lukács’ Hegelian and manly chest-beatings about the primacy of the substantive universal over the illusory and untenable “bad existence” of mere individuation call to mind those of district attorneys who demand the extermination of deviants and those unfit to live. Their comprehension of lyric poetry is to be doubted. The first line of Benn’s poem, “O Daß wir unsere Ururahnen waren,” has a completely different value in the context of the poem than it would if it expressed a literal wish. There is a grin built into the word “Ururahnen.” Through the stylization, the impulse of the poetic subject—which, incidentally, is more old-fashioned than modern—presents itself as humorously inauthentic, as a melancholy game. The repulsive quality of what the poet pretends to wish himself back to and what one cannot in fact wish oneself back to lends emphasis to his protest against a suffering that is socially produced. All that, along with the montage-like “alienation effect” produced by Benn’s use of scientific words and themes, is intended to be felt in the Benn poem. Through exaggeration, he suspends the regression that Lukács immediately ascribes to him. The person who fails to hear these overtones is like the junior writer who assiduously and expertly imitated Thomas Mann’s mode of writing and of whom Mann once said, laughing: “He writes exactly like I do, but he means it.” Simplifications like the one Lukács makes in his excursus on Benn not merely fail to recognize the nuances; rather, along with the nuances they fail to recognize the work of art itself, which becomes a work of art only by virtue of the nuances. Such simplifications are symptomatic of the stultification that befalls even the most intelligent when they fall in line with directives like those ordaining socialist realism. Even earlier, in an attempt to convict modern literature of fascism, Lukács triumphantly sought out a bad poem by Rilke and rampaged around in it like a bull in a china shop. It remains an open question whether the regression one senses in Lukács, the regression of a consciousness that was once one of the most advanced, is an objective expression of the shadow of a regression threatening the European mind—the shadow that the underdeveloped nations throw across the more developed ones, which are already beginning to align themselves with the former; or whether it reveals something of the fate of theory itself—a theory that is not only wasting away in terms of its anthropological presuppositions, that is, in terms of the intellectual capacities of the theoreticians, but whose substance is also objectively shriveling up in a state of existence in which less depends on theory than on a practice whose task is identical to the prevention of catastrophe.
Even the much-praised Thomas Mann is not proof against Lukács’ neo-naiveté; Lukács plays him off against Joyce with a philistinism that would have horrified Mann, the chronicler of disintegration and decline. The controvery about time started by Bergson is treated like the Gordian knot. Since Lukács is a good objectivist, objective time must always be in the right, and subjective time must be a mere distortion caused by decadence. It was the unbearableness of the reified, alienated, meaningless time the young Lukács described so forcefully in Flaubert’s Éducation sentimentale that led Bergson to his theory of lived time and not a spirit of subjective disintegration, as pious stupidity of all forms may imagine. In his Magic Mountain, Thomas Mann also paid his tribute to Bergson’s temps durée. In order to salvage Mann for his thesis of critical realism, Lukács gives many of the characters in the novel good grades because even subjectively, their “experience of time is normal and objective” (51). Then he writes, and I quote word for word: “Indeed, Ziemssen is aware that the modern experience of time may be simply a result of the abnormal mode of life in the sanatorium, hermetically sealed off from everyday life” (51). The irony governing the figure of Ziemssen escapes the aesthetician; socialist realism has blunted his sensitivity to the critical realism he praises. For Lukács, Ziemssen, the narrow-minded officer, a kind of post-Goethean Valentin who dies bravely and like a soldier, if in bed, is the direct spokesman of an authentic mode of life, much as Tolstoy’s Levin was planned to be but failed. In actuality, Thomas Mann represented the relationship between the two concepts of time—without reflection but with the utmost sensitivity—as conflicting and ambiguous, in a manner consistent with his approach as a whole and his dialectical relationship to everything bourgeois. Right and wrong are distributed between the reified consciousness of the philistine who escapes in vain from the sanatorium into his profession, and the phantasmagorical time of those who remain in the sanatorium, an allegory of Bohemianism and romantic subjectivism. Wisely, Mann neither reconciled the two kinds of time nor took a stand for one or the other in the construction of his work.
The fact that Lukács can philosophize right past the aesthetic import of even his favorite text so drastically has its cause in his pre-aesthetic parti pris is favor of the material and the communicated content of literary works, which he confuses with their artistic objectivity. He fails to concern himself with stylistic devices like irony, which is by no means so hidden, to say nothing of the more obvious ones, and is not rewarded for this abstention with the truth content of the works, purged of subjective illusion. Instead he is put off with the works’ meager leavings, their material content [Sachgehalt], which is of course necessary to reach the truth content. As much as Lukács would like to prevent the novel from regressing, he parrots articles of the catechism like socialist realism, the ideologically sanctioned copy theory of knowledge, and the dogma of a mechanistic progress on the part of humankind, that is, one independent of a spontaneity that has been stifled in the meantime—even though this “belief in the world’s rationality and in man’s ability to penetrate its secrets” (43) is expecting a lot, in view of the irrevocable past. Lukács thereby involuntarily comes close to the infantile conceptions of art that embarrass him in bureaucrats less well-versed than he. His attempts to break out are futile. The extent of the damage to his own aesthetic consciousness can be seen in a passage on allegorical interpretation in Byzantine mosaics: in literature, he says, works of art of this quality could only be “exceptional cases” (40). As though there were such a thing as a distinction between the rule and the exception in art, except in academies and conservatories; as though everything aesthetic, being something individuated, were not always an exception by virtue of following its own principle and its own universality, whereas everything that corresponds directly to universal rules thereby disqualifies itself as having aesthetic form. The term “exceptional cases” is derived from the same vocabulary as “peak performances.” The late Franz Borkenau once said, following his break with the Communist Party, that he could no longer stand hearing people talk about municipal regulations in the categories of Hegelian logic and Hegelian logic in the spirit of the city council. Such contaminations, which admittedly date back to Hegel himself, tie Lukács to the level he would like to raise to his own. In Lukács’ hands, Hegel’s critique of the “unhappy consciousness,” speculative philosophy’s impulse to rise above the illusory ethos of isolated subjectivity, becomes an ideology for narrow-minded party officials who have not yet reached the level of subjectivity. He dignifies their aggressive ignorance, a residue of the nineteenth-century petit bourgeoisie, as the limitedness of adaptation to reality that has had all mere individuality removed from it. But the dialectical leap is not a leap out of the dialectic that would transform the unhappy consciousness into happy complicity through sheer conviction and at the expense of the objective social and technical moments of artistic production. In accordance with a Hegelian doctrine that Lukács would scarcely question, the allegedly higher standpoint must necessarily remain abstract. Nor does the desperate profundity that Lukács offers to oppose the idiocy of “boy meets tractor” literature preserve him from declamations that are both abstract and childish: “The more the content dealt with is common to them, the more writers from different sides probe the same conditions of development and the same developmental tendencies in the same reality, and the more reality, and with it all the distinctions depicted, is transformed into a largely or purely socialist reality, the closer critical realism will have to come to socialist realism, and the more its negative (non-rejecting) perspective will be transformed, through many transitions, into a positive (affirmative), a socialist perspective” (114). The jesuitical distinction between the negative, that is, not rejecting, and the positive, that is, affirming, perspective shifts questions of literary quality directly into the sphere of regulated convictions from which Lukács would like to escape.
There can, however, be no doubt that he wants to escape it. To do justice to his book one must bear in mind that in countries where the crucial things cannot be called by name, the marks of official terror have been branded onto everything said in their place. But conversely, because of this even ideas that are weak and deflected, half-ideas, acquire a force in that constellation that their literal content does not have. The whole third chapter of the book must be read in this light, despite the disproportion between intellectual expenditure and the questions dealt with. There are numerous formulations where the line of thought need only be extended to reach open space. The following, for example:
A study of Marxism (not to speak of other activity in the Socialist movement, even Party membership) is not of itself sufficient. A writer may acquire useful experience in this way, and become aware of certain intellectual and moral problems. But it is no easier to translate “true consciousness” of reality into adequate aesthetic form than it is bourgeois “false consciousness.” (96–97)
Or, attacking the sterile empiricism of the reportage novel which flourishes everywhere these days: “In critical realism, as Zola’s example shows, the ideal of a documentary totality, more suitable to the scientific monograph, was the product of certain inherent problems. I shall show that similar, and perhaps even greater, problems are inherent in socialist realism” (100). In this context Lukács, using the terminology of his youth, pleads for the primacy of intensive over extensive totality. He would need only to take his demand farther, into the literary work itself, to assert the very thing he reproaches avant-garde writers with in his ex cathedra pontifications; it is grotesque that despite this he still wants to “vanquish” the “anti-realism of the decadent movement.” At one point he even comes close to seeing that the Russian Revolution by no means brought about conditions that would require and support a “positive” literature: “We must bear in mind that, however violent the political break, people (including writers) will not be automatically transformed” (104–5). Then, although in muted form, as though he were discussing a mere aberration, he lets slip what is really going on with socialist realism: “The result will be a diluted, inferior version of bourgeois realism, lacking the virtues of that tradition” (116). In such literature, he says, the “real nature of the artist’s perspective” is misunderstood. In other words, “many writers identify tendencies that point toward the future but exist only in that form—and precisely because of that could provide a decisive standpoint for evaluating the current period, if correctly understood—with reality itself; they represent tendencies present only in embryonic form as fully developed realities; in other words, they mechanically equate perspective and reality” (116). Once the terminological husk is removed, this means simply that the procedures of socialist realism and the socialist romanticism that Lukács recognizes as its complement are ideological transfigurations of a bad status quo. For Lukács, the official optimism of the totalitarian view of literature proves to be merely subjective in its own right. He contrasts it with a more humane notion of aesthetic objectivity: “Art too is governed by objective laws. An infringement of these laws may not have such practical consequences as do the infringement of economic laws; but it will result in work of inferior quality” (117). Here, where thought has the courage of its own convictions, Lukács’ judgments are far more accurate than his philistine evaluations of modern art: “The break-up of these mediating elements leads—in theory and in practice—to a false polarization. On the one hand, theory, from being a guide to practice, becomes a dogma, while, on the other hand, the element of a contradiction between the two is eliminated” (118). He states the central issue succinctly: In such works, “literature ceased to reflect the dynamic contradictions of social life; it became the illustration of an abstract ‘truth’” (119). Responsible for this, he says, is “agitation” as the “point of departure,” as a model for art and thought, which then shrivel up, turn rigid, and become schematic and ideologically fixated on practice. “Instead of a dialectical structure we…get a static schematism” (121). No avant-garde writer could add anything to that.
In all this we are left with the feeling of a person who rattles his chains hopelessly, imagining that their clanking is the march of the Weltgeist. He is blinded not only by the powers that be, which will scarcely take Lukács’ insubordinate ideas to heart in their cultural politics, if indeed they tolerate them at all. In addition, Lukács’ critique is caught up in the delusion that contemporary Russian society, which is in fact oppressed and bled dry, is contradictory but not antagonistic, to use a distinction worked out in China. All the symptoms Lukács is protesting are themselves the product of the need on the part of dictators and their adherents to hammer into the masses a thesis that Lukács implicitly endorses in his notion of socialist realism, and to banish from awareness anything that might cause them to stray from it. The authority of a doctrine that fulfills real functions of this kind cannot be destroyed simply by demonstrating that it is false. Lukács quotes a cynical sentence from Hegel which expresses the social meaning of the process described in the classical bourgeois Bildungsroman: “For the end of such apprenticeship consists in this, that the subject sows his wild oats, builds himself with his wishes and opinions into harmony with subsisting relationships and their rationality, enters the concatenation of the world and acquires for himself an appropriate attitude to it” (112). Lukács adds this comment:
In one sense, many of the great bourgeois novels contradict Hegel; in another, they confirm him. They contradict him inasmuch as the educational process does not always culminate in acceptance of, and adaptation to, bourgeois society. The realization of youthful convictions and dreams is obstructed by the pressures of society; the rebellious hero is broken, and driven into isolation, but the reconciliation with society of which Hegel speaks is not always extracted. On the other hand, since the individual’s conflict with society often ends in resignation, the end-effect is not so different from what Hegel suggests. (112)
The postulate of a reality that must be represented without a breach between subject and object and which must be “reflected”—the term Lukács stubbornly adheres to—for the sake of that lack of a breach: that postulate, which is the supreme criterion of his aesthetics, implies that that reconciliation has been achieved, that society has been set right, that the subject has come into its own and is at home in its world. This much Lukács admits in an anti-ascetic digression. Only then would there disappear from art the moment of resignation that Lukács perceives in Hegel and that he would certainly have to acknowledge in Goethe, the prototype of his concept of realism, who preached renunciation. But the division, the antagonism, continues, and to say that it has been overcome in the nations of the Eastern bloc, as they call it, is simply a lie. The spell that holds Lukács in its power and bars his longed-for return to the utopia of his youth reenacts the extorted reconciliation he himself detected in absolute idealism.