154 Chapter 13
Let me try to give you a taste of the kind of objections that I have seen raised. In some
messages, perhaps with some needlessly complex notation, the person proposes that in-
stead of the Cantor’s diagonalization, we should instead define a different diagonal real
number y, whose nth digit agrees with the nth digit of r
n
, rather than disagreeing with it.
With this way of arguing, they say, Cantor’s argument does not work, and so the real num-
ber y could be on the list after all; they conclude that the real numbers could be countable
after all. But this is clearly a baseless objection, and the conclusion does not follow. If a
modified version of a correct argument does not succeed, it does not mean that the original
argument is wrong; it just means that the modified argument does not constitute a proof.
Another objection one sees is that, after having constructed Cantor’s diagonal real num-
ber z, if it does not appear on the original list r
1
, r
2
, r
3
, and so on, which was supposed
to include all real numbers, then one should simply add it to the list! Put the diagonal
real number z in front, they say, and everything is fine. And furthermore, if one should
diagonalize against this new list, then that real also could simply be added to the list. This
objection, of course, is without merit, since the claim was not that the diagonal real num-
ber z could not appear on any list at all; rather, the claim was that the original list did not
already contain all real numbers, since it did not contain the diagonal real z. This contra-
diction shows that it is impossible to make a list containing all real numbers, and that is
precisely what it means to say that the set of real numbers R is uncountable.
Another common objection is that people sometimes try to prove directly that the set of
real numbers is countable. For example, sometimes they start by proving that the set of real
numbers with finite terminating decimal expansions is countable. This part is correct, since
these real numbers are precisely the rational numbers expressible with a denominator that
is a power of 10. Next, they point out that every real number is a limit of a sequence of such
rational numbers, which approximate it ever more closely. And that part also is correct.
Finally, they attempt to conclude, usually without any proof or with erroneous proof, that
this implies that the set of real numbers is countable. But this step of their argument is
simply not correct. The set of real numbers does indeed have a countable dense set, but
this does not mean that the real numbers themselves are countable.
Shall we leave these silly objections behind and aim for more mathematics?
13.4 Transcendental numbers
Cantor used his theorem to prove the following corollary, giving a new proof of Joseph
Liouville’s 1844 theorem that transcendental numbers exist, while also strengthening the
conclusion. Recall from chapter 1 that a real number is algebraic if it is the root of a
polynomial with integer coefficients; a number is transcendental if it is not. It had been
an open question whether there were any transcendental numbers at all, until Liouville’s
celebrated theorem that they exist. Cantor’s goes further, showing that indeed, most real
numbers are transcendental.