‘Why should I act morally?’ is a different type of question from those that we have been discussing up to now. Questions like
‘Why should I treat people of different ethnic groups equally?’ or ‘Why is abortion justifiable?’ seek ethical reasons for
acting in a certain way. These are questions within ethics. They presuppose the ethical point of view. ‘Why
should I act morally?’ is on another level. It is not a question within ethics, but a question about ethics.
‘Why should I act morally?’ is therefore a question about something normally presupposed. Such questions are perplexing. Some
philosophers have found this particular question so perplexing that they have rejected it as logically improper, as an attempt
to ask something that cannot properly be asked.
One ground for this rejection is the claim that our ethical principles are, by definition, the principles we take as overridingly
important. This means that whatever principles are overriding for a particular person are necessarily that person's ethical
principles, and a person who accepts as an ethical principle that she ought to give her wealth to help the poor must, by definition,
have actually decided to give away her wealth. On this definition of ethics, once a person has made an ethical decision no
further practical question can arise. Hence, it is impossible to make sense of the question: ‘Why should I act morally?’
It might be thought a good reason for accepting the definition of ethics as overriding that it allows us to dismiss as meaningless
an otherwise troublesome question. Adopting this definition cannot solve real problems, however, for it leads to correspondingly
greater difficulties in establishing any ethical conclusion. Take, for example, the conclusion that the rich ought to aid
the poor. Although the argument for this conclusion in Chapter 8 drew on the intuitive appeal of our readiness to rescue the
child drowning in the pond, we saw that if that intuition were rejected, it could still rest on the assumption that suffering
and death are bad things, even when they are not your suffering and death. If we define ethical principles as whatever principles one takes as overriding, then someone could say
that her overriding principle is an egoistic one, and the suffering and death of strangers doesn't matter at all. We could not invoke universalizability in order to deny that this could be an ethical principle, because if anything anyone
takes as overriding counts as that person's ethical principle, there can be no requirement that one's ethical principles be
universalizable. Thus, what we gain by being able to dismiss the question ‘Why should I act morally?’ we lose by being unable
to use the universalizability of ethical judgments – or any other feature of ethics – to argue for particular conclusions
about what is morally right. Taking ethics as in some sense necessarily involving a universal point of view seems to me a
more natural and less confusing way of discussing these issues.
Other philosophers think that ‘Why should I act morally?’ must be rejected for the same reason that we must reject ‘Why should
I be rational?’ Like the question ‘Why should I act morally?’, the question ‘Why should I be rational?’ questions something
that we normally presuppose. But to question rationality – not the use of reason in any specific context, but in general –
really is logically improper because in answering it we can only give reasons for being rational. Thus, the person asking
the question must be seeking reasons and, hence, is herself presupposing rationality. The resulting justification of rationality would have to be circular – which shows, not that rationality lacks a necessary
justification, but that it needs no justification, because it cannot intelligibly be questioned unless it is already presupposed.
(Note that some questions about whether to use reason to reach a decision are intelligible. For example, ‘When deciding whether
to trust someone I’ve just met, should I use my reason or my instincts?’ is an intelligible question, because it questions
the use of reason in a specific context. It is possible that our instincts will do better than our reason in that context,
and if so, the best answer would be to use your instincts. To say this, however, is itself to give reasons for not using reason
in that context, so the question poses no challenge to reason as such.)
Is ‘Why should I act morally?’ like ‘Why should I be rational?’ in that it presupposes the very point of view it questions?
It would be, if we interpreted the ‘should’ as a moral ‘should’. Then the question would ask for moral reasons for being moral.
This would be absurd. Once we have decided that an action is morally obligatory, there is no further moral question to ask.
It is redundant to ask why I should, morally, do the action that I morally should do.
There is, however, no need to interpret the question as a request for an ethical justification of ethics. ‘Should’ need not
mean ‘should, morally’. It could simply be a way of asking for reasons for action, without any specification about the kind
of reasons wanted. We sometimes want to ask a very general practical question from no particular point of view. Faced with
a difficult choice, we ask a close friend for advice. Morally, he says, we ought to do A, but B would be more in our interests,
whereas etiquette demands C and to do D would be just
so cool! This answer may not satisfy us. We want advice on which of these standpoints to adopt. If it is possible to ask such a question,
we must ask it from a position of neutrality between all these points of view, not of commitment to any one of them. ‘Why
should I act morally?’ is this sort of question. If it were not possible to ask practical questions without presupposing a
point of
view, we would be unable to say anything intelligible about the most ultimate practical choices. Whether to act according
to considerations of ethics, self-interest, etiquette or aesthetics would be a choice ‘beyond reason’ – in a sense, an arbitrary
choice. Before we resign ourselves to this conclusion, we should at least attempt to interpret the question so that the mere
asking of it does not commit us to any particular point of view.
We can now formulate the question more precisely. It is a question about the ethical point of view, asked from a position
outside it. What is ‘the ethical point of view’? I have suggested that a distinguishing feature of ethics is that ethical
judgments are universalizable. Ethics requires us to go beyond our own personal point of view to a standpoint like that of the impartial spectator.
Given this conception of ethics, ‘Why should I act morally?’ is a question that may properly be asked by anyone wondering
whether to act only on grounds that would be acceptable from this universal point of view. It is, after all, possible to act –
and some people do act – without thinking of anything except one's own interests. The question asks for reasons for going
beyond this personal basis of action and acting only on judgments one is prepared to prescribe universally.
There is an ancient line of philosophical thought that attempts to demonstrate that to act rationally is to act ethically.
The argument is today associated with Kant and is mainly found in the writings of modern Kantians, though it goes back at
least as far as the Stoics. The form in which the argument is presented varies, but the variations tend to have a common structure,
as follows:
1. Some requirement of universalizability or impartiality is essential to ethics.
2. Reason, whether theoretical or practical, is universally or objectively valid. If, for example, it follows from the premises
‘All humans are mortal’ and ‘Socrates is human’ that Socrates is mortal, then this inference must follow universally. It cannot
be valid for me and invalid for you.
Therefore:
3. Only a judgment that satisfies the requirement described in (1) as a necessary condition of an ethical judgment will be an
objectively
rational judgment in accordance with (2). For I cannot expect any other rational agents to accept as valid for them a judgment
that I would not accept if I were in their place; and if two rational agents could not accept one another's judgments, they
could not be rational judgments, for the reason given in (2). To say that I would accept the judgment I make, even if I were
in someone else's position and they in mine is, however, simply to say that my judgment is one I can prescribe from a universal
point of view. Ethics and reason both require us to rise above our own particular point of view and take a perspective from
which our own personal identity – the role we happen to occupy – is unimportant. Thus, reason requires us to act on universalizable
judgments and, to that extent, to act ethically.
Is this argument valid? I have already argued for the first point, that ethics involves universalizability. The second point
also seems undeniable. Reason must be universal. Does the conclusion therefore follow? Here is the flaw in the argument. The
conclusion appears to follow directly from the premises; but this move involves a slide from the limited sense in which it
is true that a rational judgment must be universally valid, to a stronger sense of ‘universally valid’ that is equivalent
to universalizability.
The difference between these two senses can be seen by considering a non-universalizable imperative, like the purely egoistic:
‘Let everyone do what is in my interests.’ This differs from the imperative of universalizable egoism – ‘Let everyone do what is in her or his own interests’ – because it contains an ineliminable reference to a particular person. It therefore cannot be an ethical imperative.
Does it also lack the universality required if it is to be a rational basis for action? Surely not. Every rational agent could
accept that the purely egoistic activity of other rational agents is rationally justifiable. Pure egoism could be rationally
adopted by everyone.
Let us look at this more closely. It must be conceded that there is a sense in which one purely egoistic rational agent –
call him Jack – could not accept the practical judgments of another purely egoistic rational agent – call her Jill. Assuming
Jill's interests differ from Jack's, Jill may be acting rationally in urging Jack to do A, while Jack is also acting rationally
in deciding against doing A.
This disagreement is, however, compatible with all rational agents accepting pure egoism. Though they accept pure egoism,
it points them in different directions because they start from different places. When
Jack adopts pure egoism, it leads him to further his interests; and when Jill adopts pure egoism, it leads her to further
her interests. Hence, the disagreement over what to do. On the other hand – and this is the sense in which pure egoism could
be accepted as valid by all rational agents – if we were to ask Jill (off the record and promising not to tell Jack) what
she thinks it would be rational for Jack to do, she would, if truthful, have to reply that it would be rational for Jack to
do what is in his own interests rather than what is in her interests.
So when purely egoistic rational agents oppose one another's acts, it does not indicate disagreement over the rationality
of pure egoism. Pure egoism, though not a universalizable principle, could be accepted as a rational basis of action by all
rational agents. This shows that the sense in which rational judgments must be universally acceptable is weaker than the sense
in which ethical judgments must be. ‘Let everyone do what is in my interests’ could be a valid reason for Jack to do what is in his interests, although it could not be an ethical reasons for
him to do it.
A consequence of this conclusion is that rational agents may rationally try to prevent one another doing what they admit the
other is rationally justified in doing. There is, unfortunately, nothing paradoxical about this; on most theories of rationality,
it is just a fact of everyday life. Salespeople competing for an important sale will accept one another's conduct as rational,
though each aims to thwart the other. The same holds of rivals in love, enemy soldiers meeting in battle, or footballers vying
for the ball.
Accordingly, this attempted demonstration of a link between reason and ethics fails. Are there other ways of forging this
link? The chief obstacle to overcome is the nature of practical reason. Long ago David Hume argued that reason in action applies only to means, not to ends. The ends must be given by our wants and
desires. Hume unflinchingly drew out the implications of this view:
‘Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger. ‘Tis not contrary
to reason for me to choose my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian or person wholly unknown to me. ’Tis
as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledged lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent affection
for the former than the latter.
Extreme as it is, Hume's view of practical reason has stood up to criticism remarkably well. His central claim – that in practical
reasoning, we start from something we want – is difficult to refute; yet it must be refuted if
any argument is to succeed in showing that it is rational for all of us to act ethically irrespective of what we want.
In an attempt to refute Hume, several writers start by asserting that it is rational to take one's own future desires into account, whether or not one now happens to desire the satisfaction of those future desires. In The Possibility of Altruism, Thomas Nagel argued forcefully that not to take one's own future desires into account in one's practical deliberations would
indicate a failure to see oneself as a person existing over time, with the present being merely one time among others in one's
life. So it is, on Nagel's view, my conception of myself as a person that makes it rational for me to consider my long-term interests.
This holds true even if I have ‘a more ardent affection’ for something that I acknowledge is not really, all things considered,
in my own interest.
Derek Parfit provides a striking illustration of someone who fails to consider his or her interests over time in a way that
strikes most of us as obviously irrational. He asks us to imagine someone with a condition he calls ‘Future Tuesday Indifference’:
This man cares about his own future pleasures or pains, except when they will come on any future Tuesday. This strange attitude
does not depend on ignorance or false beliefs. Pain on Tuesdays, this man knows, would be just as painful, and just as much
his pain, and Tuesdays are just like other days of the week. Even so, given the choice, this man would now prefer agony on any
future Tuesday to slight pain on any other future day.
About such a person, Parfit comments:
That some ordeal would be much more painful is a strong reason not to prefer it. That this ordeal would be on a future Tuesday is no reason to prefer it. So this man's preferences are strongly contrary to reason, and irrational.
He adds that although no one has this attitude, it is similar to the bias many people have towards the near. It would be similarly
irrational, he suggests, for anyone to postpone a minute of agony today, knowing that this would mean an hour of the same
degree of agony tomorrow. Less extreme departures from a position of temporal neutrality – that is, an attitude of equal concern
for all moments of time, putting aside uncertainties about the future – are also, in Parfit's view, irrational.
Whether Nagel's or Parfit's arguments succeed in vindicating the rationality of prudence, or of temporal neutrality, is one
question; whether a similar argument can also be used in favour of a form of altruism based on taking the desires of
others into account is another question altogether.
Nagel attempted this analogous argument in
The Possibility of Altruism. The role occupied by ‘seeing the present as merely one time among others’
is, in this argument for altruism, taken by ‘seeing oneself as merely one person among others’. The problem is that whereas
it would be extremely difficult for most of us to cease conceiving of ourselves as existing over time, with the present merely
one time among others that we will live through, the way we see ourselves as a person among others is quite different.
Henry Sidgwick's observation on this point seems exactly right:
It would be contrary to Common Sense to deny that the distinction between any one individual and any other is real and fundamental,
and that consequently ‘I’ am concerned with the quality of my existence as an individual in a sense, fundamentally important,
in which I am not concerned with the quality of the existence of other individuals: and this being so, I do not see how it
can be proved that this distinction is not to be taken as fundamental in determining the ultimate end of rational action for
an individual.
So it is not only Hume's view of practical reason that stands in the way of attempts to show that to act rationally is to
act ethically; we might succeed in overthrowing that barrier, only to find our way blocked by the commonsense distinction
between self and others. Nagel no longer holds that the argument in The Possibility of Altruism succeeds, and Parfit is largely in agreement with Sidgwick about the rationality of acting to further one's own interests, even when this
is contrary to the greater interests of others. Largely, but not entirely, because he thinks that it is irrational to act
on your own interests where you have only minor interests at stake and others have a great deal at stake. So if you could
save yourself one minute of discomfort by doing something that would inflict an agonizing death on a million people, this
would, on Parfit's view, be an irrational thing to do, even if it were in your own interests. Still, this is very far from
establishing that doing what is impartially good, or what is right, is required by reason.
Hence, even if Hume's view of reason is wrong, the next most defensible view of reason – Sidgwick's, perhaps as modified by
Parfit – does not enable us to conclude that reason requires us to act morally.
If practical reasoning begins with something wanted, to show that it is rational to act morally would involve showing that
by acting morally we will achieve something we want.
If, agreeing with Sidgwick rather
than Hume, we hold that it is rational to act in our long-term interests irrespective of what we happen to want at the present
moment, we could show that it is rational to act morally by showing that it is in our long-term interests to do so.
There have been many attempts to argue along these lines ever since Plato, in
The Republic, portrayed Socrates as arguing that to be virtuous is to have the different elements of one's personality ordered in a harmonious
manner, and this is necessary for happiness.
We shall look at these arguments shortly; but first it is necessary to assess an objection to this whole approach to ‘Why
should I act morally?’
People often say that to defend morality by appealing to self-interest is to misunderstand what ethics is all about. F. H.
Bradley stated this eloquently:
What answer can we give when the question Why should I be Moral?, in the sense of What will it advantage Me?, is put to us?
Here we shall do well, I think, to avoid all praises of the pleasantness of virtue. We may believe that it transcends all possible delights of vice, but it would be well to remember that we desert a moral point
of view, that we degrade and prostitute virtue, when to those who do not love her for herself we bring ourselves to recommend
her for the sake of her pleasures.
In other words, we can never get people to act morally by providing reasons of self-interest, because if they accept what
we say and act on the reasons given, they will only be acting self-interestedly, not morally.
One reply to this objection would be that the substance of the action, what is actually done, is more important than the
motive. People might give money to help those in extreme poverty because their friends will think better of them if they do,
or they might give the same amount because they think it is their duty. Those helped by the gift will benefit to the same
extent either way.
This is true but crude. It can be made more sophisticated if it is combined with an appropriate account of the nature and
function of ethics. Ethics is a social practice that has evolved among beings living in social groups, and it promotes ways
of living that are in the interests of individuals living in groups. Ethical judgments can do this by praising and encouraging
actions in accordance with these values. Ethical judgments are concerned with motives because this is a good indication of
the tendency of an action to promote what is considered desirable or undesirable, but also because it is here that praise
and blame may be effective in altering the tendency of a person's actions. In this respect, conscientiousness (that is, acting
for the sake of doing what is right) is a particularly useful motive. People who are conscientious will, if they accept the
values of their society (and if most people did not accept these values, they would not be the values of the society), always
tend to promote what the society values. They may have no generous or sympathetic inclinations, but if they think it their
duty to help the poor, they will do so. Moreover, those motivated by the desire to do what is right can be relied on to act
as they think right in all circumstances, whereas those who act from some other motive, like self-interest, will only do what
they think right when they believe it will also be in their interest. Conscientiousness is thus a kind of multipurpose gap-filler that can be used to motivate people towards whatever is valued,
even if the natural virtues normally associated with action in accordance with those values (generosity, sympathy, honesty, tolerance, humility, etc.) are lacking. (This needs some qualification: a conscientious mother
may provide as well for her children as a mother who loves them, but she cannot love them because it is the right thing to
do. Sometimes conscientiousness is a poor substitute for the real thing.)
On this view of ethics, it is still results, not motives, that really matter. Conscientiousness is of value because of its
consequences. Yet, unlike, say, benevolence, conscientiousness can be praised and encouraged only for its own sake. To praise a conscientious
act for its consequences would be to praise not conscientiousness but something else altogether. If we appeal to sympathy
or self-interest as a reason for doing one's duty, then we are not encouraging people to do their duty for its own sake. If
conscientiousness is to be encouraged, it must be thought of as good for its own sake.
It is different in the case of an act done from a motive that people act on irrespective of praise and encouragement. The
use of ethical language is then unnecessary. We do not normally say that people ought to do, or that it is their duty to do,
whatever gives them the greatest pleasure, for most people are sufficiently motivated to do this anyway. So, whereas we praise
good acts done for the sake of doing what is right, we withhold our praise when we believe the act was done from some motive
like self-interest.
This emphasis on motives and on the moral worth of doing right for its own sake is now embedded in our notion of ethics. To
the extent that it is so embedded, we will feel that to provide considerations of self-interest for doing what is right is
to empty the action of its moral worth.
My suggestion is that our notion of ethics has become misleading to the extent that moral worth is attributed only to action
done because it
is right, without any ulterior motive. It is understandable, and from the point of view of society perhaps even desirable,
that this attitude should prevail; nevertheless, those who accept this view of ethics, and are led by it to do what is right
because it is right, without asking for any further reason, are falling victim to a kind of confidence trick – though not,
of course, a consciously perpetrated one.
That this view of ethics is unjustifiable has already been indicated by the failure of the argument discussed earlier in this
chapter for a rational justification of ethics. In the history of Western philosophy, no one has urged more strongly than Kant that our ordinary moral consciousness finds
moral worth only when duty is done for duty's sake. Yet Kant himself saw that without a rational justification this common
conception of ethics would be ‘a mere phantom of the brain’. This is indeed the case. If we reject – as in general terms we
have done – the Kantian justification of the rationality of ethics but try to retain the Kantian conception of ethics, ethics
is left hanging without support. It becomes a closed system, a system that cannot be questioned because its first premise –
that only action done because it is right has any moral worth – rules out the only remaining possible justification for accepting
this very premise. Morality is, on this view, no more rational an end than any other allegedly self-justifying practice, like
etiquette or the kind of religious faith that comes only to those who first set aside all sceptical doubts.
Taken as a view of ethics as a whole, we should abandon this Kantian notion of ethics. This does not mean, however, that we
should never do what we see to be right simply because we see it to be right, without further reasons.
Here once again, we need to appeal to the distinction Hare has made between intuitive and critical thinking. When I stand
back from my day-to-day ethical decisions and ask why I should act ethically, I should seek reasons in the broadest sense
and not allow Kantian preconceptions to deter me from considering self-interested reasons for living an ethical life. If my
search is successful, it will provide me with reasons for taking up the ethical point of view as a settled policy, a way of
living. I would not then ask, in my day-to-day ethical decision making, whether each particular right action is in my interests.
Instead, I do it because I see myself as an ethical person. In everyday situations, I will simply assume that doing what is
right is in my interests; and once I have decided what is right, I will go ahead and do it, without thinking about further
reasons for doing what is right. To deliberate over the ultimate reasons for doing what is right in each case would impossibly
complicate my life; it would also be inadvisable because in particular situations I might be too greatly
influenced by strong but temporary desires and inclinations and so make decisions I would later regret.
That, at least, is how a justification of ethics in terms of self-interest might work, without defeating its own aim. We can now ask if such a justification exists. I will here put aside one ancient justification that is still significant for
many religious believers: the belief that virtue will be rewarded and wickedness will be punished in a life after our bodily
death. To rely on such a justification, one would first have to show that we do survive death, in some form, and secondly
that we will be rewarded and punished in accordance with the extent to which we have lived an ethical life. I do not know
how this could be demonstrated.
In The Republic, Plato portrays Socrates as debating with skeptics who ask why they should be just and eventually reaching the conclusion
that ‘the just man is happy and the unjust man miserable.’ Socrates’ argument convinces few readers today, however, as he seems to operate with a concept of leading a good life that
assumes that to live well is both to do what is right or just and to prosper and be happy. That may have been what it meant
to live a good life in ancient Greece, but today we are sharply aware that living ethically is one thing and being prosperous
and happy is another – even if we remain open-minded on whether there is a link between them. Many other philosophers have
followed Socrates and Plato in trying to show that the good man will be happy: Aristotle, Aquinas, Spinoza, Butler, Hegel
and even – for all his strictures against prostituting virtue – Bradley. These philosophers made broad claims about human nature and the conditions under which human beings can be happy. Philosophers
are not empirical scientists, of course, and many of the factual claims made by past philosophers lack any sound basis in
evidence. But at this point it is relevant to draw on the growing body of modern research in what is sometimes called ‘positive psychology’ –
the part of psychology that explores the sources of happiness.
Here we do find evidence for at least a correlation between some aspects of living ethically and happiness.
Americans who give to charity were, in one large survey, 43 percent more likely to say that they were ‘very happy’ about their
lives than those who did not give. Those who did voluntary work for charities were similarly more likely to say that they
were happy than those who did not. In a separate study, those who give were 68 percent less likely to have felt ‘hopeless’
and 34 percent less likely to say that they felt ‘so sad that nothing could cheer them up’. Giving blood, another altruistic
act, also makes people feel good about themselves. Volunteering actually seems to improve the health of
elderly people and help them live longer.
Jonathan Haidt, a professor of psychology and author of
The Happiness Hypothesis, comments: ‘At least for older people, it really is more blessed to give than to receive.’
Is this more than just a correlation? Perhaps. In one experiment, researchers gave $100 to each of nineteen female students
and gave them the option of donating some of the money to a local food bank for the poor. To ensure that any effects observed
came entirely from making the donation, and not, for instance, from having the belief that others would think they were generous,
the students were informed that no one, not even the experimenters, would know which students made a donation. While the students
were deciding what to do, the researchers were using magnetic resonance imaging, which shows activity in various parts of
the brain. The research found that when students donated, the brain's ‘reward centres’ – the caudate nucleus, nucleus accumbens
and insulae – became active. These are the parts of the brain that respond when you eat something sweet or receive money.
This is a small-scale experiment and only more research will show whether this is a widespread phenomenon, and whether it
is part of the explanation for why those who give are more likely to say that they are happy.
The research cited focuses on giving and helping behaviour. Would something similar apply to living ethically in general?
There seems to be little or no research on this broader topic. A. H. Maslow, an American psychologist, asserted that human beings have a need for self-actualization that involves growing
towards courage, kindness, knowledge, love, honesty and unselfishness. When we fulfill this need, we feel serene, joyful,
filled with zest, sometimes euphoric and generally happy. When we act contrary to our need for self-actualization, we experience
anxiety, despair, boredom, shame, emptiness and are generally unable to enjoy ourselves. It would be nice if Maslow should
turn out to be right; unfortunately, the data Maslow produced in support of his theory consisted of very limited studies of
selected people and cannot be considered anything more than suggestive.
Human nature is so diverse that one may doubt if any generalization about the kind of character that leads to happiness could
hold for all human beings.
What, for instance, of those we call ‘psychopaths’?
Psychiatrists use this term as a label for a person who is asocial, impulsive, egocentric, unemotional, lacking in feelings
of remorse or shame or guilt, and apparently unable to form deep and enduring personal relationships. Psychopaths are certainly
abnormal, but whether it is proper to say that they are mentally ill is another matter. At least on the surface,
they do not
suffer from their condition, and it is not obvious that it is in their interest to be ‘cured’.
Hervey Cleckley, the author of a classic study of psychopathy entitled
The Mask of Sanity, notes that since his book was first published he has received countless letters from people desperate for help – but they
are from the parents, spouses and other relatives of psychopaths, almost never from the psychopaths themselves. This is not
surprising, for although psychopaths are asocial and indifferent to the welfare of others, they have an inflated opinion of
their own abilities. When interviewed they say things like:
A lot has happened to me, a lot more will happen. But I enjoy living and I am always looking forward to each day. I like laughing
and I’ve done a lot. I am essentially a clown at heart – but a happy one. I always take the bad with the good.
There is no effective therapy for psychopathy, which may be explained by the fact that psychopaths see nothing wrong with
their behaviour and often find it rewarding, at least in the short term. Of course, their impulsive nature and lack of a sense of shame or guilt means that some psychopaths end up in prison, though
it is hard to tell how many do not, because those who avoid prison are also more likely to avoid contact with psychiatrists.
Studies have shown that a surprisingly large number of psychopaths are able to avoid prison despite grossly anti-social behaviour,
probably because of their well-known ability to convince others that they are truly repentant, that what they did will never
happen again, and that they deserve another chance.
The existence of psychopaths – or more broadly, of people with psychopathic tendencies – counts against the contention that
benevolence, sympathy and feelings of guilt are present in everyone. It also appears to count against attempts to link happiness
with the possession of these inclinations. Let us pause before we accept this latter conclusion. Must we accept psychopaths’
own evaluations of their happiness? They are, after all, notorious liars. Moreover, even if they are telling the truth as
they see it, are they qualified to say that they are really happy when they seem unable to experience the emotional states
that play such a large part in the happiness and fulfillment of others? Admittedly, a psychopath could use the same argument
against us: how can we say that we are truly happy when we have not experienced the excitement and freedom that comes from
complete irresponsibility? We cannot enter into the subjective states of psychopathic people, nor they into ours, so the dispute
is not easy to resolve.
Cleckley suggests that the behaviour of psychopaths can be explained as a response to the meaninglessness of their lives.
It is characteristic of psychopaths to work for a while at a job and then, just when their ability and charm have taken them
to the crest of success, commit some petty and easily detectable crime. A similar pattern occurs in their personal relationships. They live largely in the present and lack any coherent life plan.
Sometimes their failure to consider the future consequences of their acts – even to themselves – is breathtaking. Here is
an example from a study by R. D. Hare:
One of our subjects, who scored high on the Psychopathy Checklist, said that while walking to a party he decided to buy a
case of beer, but realized that he had left his wallet at home six or seven blocks away. Not wanting to walk back, he picked
up a heavy piece of wood and robbed the nearest gas station, seriously injuring the attendant.
We can find support here for Thomas Nagel's account of imprudence as an irrational failure to see oneself as a person existing
over time, with the present merely one among other times one will live through. Psychopaths have an extreme form of this failure.
Cleckley explains their erratic and inadequately motivated behaviour by likening the psychopath's life to that of a child
forced to sit through a performance of King Lear. Children are restless and misbehave under these conditions because they cannot enjoy the play as adults do. They act to
relieve boredom. Similarly, Cleckley says, psychopaths are bored because their emotional poverty means that they cannot take
interest in, or gain satisfaction from, what for others are the most important things in life: love, family, success in business
or professional life and so on. These things simply do not matter to them. Their unpredictable and anti-social behaviour is
an attempt to relieve what would otherwise be a tedious existence. These claims are speculative, and Cleckley admits that
it may not be possible to establish them scientifically. They do suggest, however, an aspect of the psychopath's life that undermines the otherwise attractive nature of the psychopath's
free-wheeling life. Most reflective people, at some time or other, want their life to have some kind of meaning. Few of us
could deliberately choose a way of life that we regarded as utterly meaningless. For this reason, most of us would not choose
to live a psychopathic life, however enjoyable it might be.
Yet if we are to reject the psychopath's claim to be living an enjoyable life on the ground that it is a meaningless life,
we have to face the question of whether we can find meaning in our own lives. If we are not religious
believers, don't we have to accept that life really is meaningless, not just for the psychopath but for all of us? And if
this is so, why should we not choose – if it were in our power to choose our personality – the life of a psychopath? Is it
true, though, that, religion aside, life is meaningless? Now our pursuit of reasons for acting morally has led us to what
is often regarded as the ultimate philosophical question.
In what sense does rejection of belief in a god imply rejection of the view that life has any meaning? If this world had been
created by some divine being with a particular goal in mind, it could be said to have a meaning, at least for that divine
being. If we could know what the divine being's purpose in creating us was, we could then know what the meaning of our life
was for our creator. If we accepted our creator's purpose (though why we should do that would need to be explained), we could
claim to know the meaning of life.
When we reject belief in a god, we must give up the idea that life on this planet has some preordained meaning. Life as a whole has no meaning. Life began, as the best available theories tell us, in a chance combination of molecules; it then evolved
through random mutations and natural selection. All this just happened; it did not happen for any overall purpose. Now that
it has resulted in the existence of beings that prefer some states of affairs to others, however, it may be possible for particular
lives to be meaningful. In this sense, atheists can find meaning in life.
Let us return to the comparison between the life of a psychopath and that of a more normal person. Why should the psychopath's
life not be meaningful? We have seen that psychopaths are egocentric to an extreme: neither other people, nor worldly success,
nor anything else really matters to them. Why is their own enjoyment of life not sufficient to give meaning to their lives?
Most of us would not be able to find full satisfaction by deliberately setting out to enjoy ourselves without caring about
anyone or anything else. The pleasures we obtained in that way would seem empty and soon pall. We seek a meaning for our lives
beyond our own pleasures and find fulfilment and happiness in doing what we see to be meaningful. If our life has no meaning
other than our own happiness, we are likely to find that when we have obtained what we think we need to be happy, happiness
itself still eludes us.
That those who aim at happiness for happiness's sake often fail to find it, whereas others find happiness in pursuing altogether
different goals, has been called ‘the paradox of hedonism’. It is not, of course, a logical paradox but a claim about the
way in which we come to be happy. Like other generalizations on this subject, it lacks empirical confirmation. Yet it matches
our everyday observations and is consistent with our nature as evolved, purposive beings. Human beings survive and reproduce
themselves through purposive action. We obtain happiness and fulfillment by working towards and achieving our goals. In evolutionary
terms, we could say that happiness functions as an internal reward for our achievements. Subjectively, we regard achieving
the goal (or progressing towards it) as a reason for happiness. Our own happiness, therefore, is a by-product of aiming at
something else and is not to be obtained by setting our sights on happiness alone.
The psychopath's life can now be seen to be meaningless in a way that a normal life is not. It is meaningless because it looks
inward to the pleasures of the present moment and not outward to anything more long-term or far-reaching. More normal lives
have meaning because they are lived to some larger purpose.
All this is speculative. You may accept or reject it to the extent that it agrees with your own observation and introspection.
My next – and final – suggestion is more speculative still. It is that to find an enduring meaning in our lives it is not
enough to go beyond psychopaths who have no long-term commitments or life plans; we must also go beyond more prudent egoists who have long-term plans concerned only with their own interests. The prudent
egoists may find meaning in their lives for a time, for they have the purpose of furthering their own interests; but what,
in the end, does that amount to? When everything in our interests has been achieved, do we just sit back and be happy? Could
we be happy in this way? Or would we decide that we had still not quite reached our target, that there was something else
we needed before we could sit back and enjoy it all? Most materially successful egoists take the latter route, thus escaping
the necessity of admitting that they cannot find happiness in permanent holidaying. People who slave to establish small businesses,
telling themselves they would do it only until they had made enough to live comfortably, keep working long after they have
passed their original target. Their material ‘needs’ expand just fast enough to keep ahead of their income.
In recent years, we have had plenty of examples of the insatiable nature of the desire for wealth – and where it leads. For
the 1980s, it was
summed up in Oliver Stone's movie
Wall Street starring Michael Douglas as a convincingly unpleasant Gordon Gekko, a financial wheeler-dealer whose manner of operation
resembles that of the real-life financier Ivan Boesky who famously pronounced ‘Greed is good.’ The critical voice in the film
is provided by Bud Fox, played by Charlie Sheen. While Gekko attempts his usual takeover and asset-stripping procedure on
the airline for which Fox's father works as a mechanic, an angry Fox asks: ‘Tell me, Gordon, when does it all end, huh? How
many yachts can you water-ski behind? How much is enough?’ For Boesky, it seems, $150 million was not enough, because his
fortune was at least that when he sought to boost it even further by insider trading, a crime for which he eventually lost
his fortune, his reputation and his liberty. With the man who had given the decade its tagline in prison, people began talking
about finding fulfilment and satisfaction rather than just accumulating wealth. When economic good times returned in the first
decade of the twenty-first century, however, ostentatious spending reached new heights, with the founders of equity firms
competing to throw lavish birthday party bashes that cost upwards of $5 million.
When the global financial crisis hit in 2007, and Bernard Madoff's Ponzi scheme became the equivalent of Boesky's insider
trading, the talk once again turned to finding meaning and fulfilment – and it seems safe to predict that, in time, the cycle
will repeat itself.
For anyone seeking to escape this cycle of accumulation and ruin, ethics can provide a more durable alternative. If we are
looking for a purpose broader than our own interests, something that will allow us to see our lives as possessing significance
beyond the narrow confines of our wealth or even our own pleasurable states of consciousness, one obvious solution is to take
up the ethical point of view. The ethical point of view does, as we have seen, require us to go beyond a personal point of view to the standpoint of an
impartial spectator. Thus, looking at things ethically is a way of transcending our inward-looking concerns and identifying ourselves with the
most objective point of view possible – with, as Sidgwick put it, ‘the point of view of the universe’.
The point of view of the universe is a lofty standpoint. In the rarefied air that surrounds it, we may get carried away into
talking, as Kant does, of the moral point of view ‘inevitably’ humbling all who compare their own limited nature with it.
I do not want to suggest anything as sweeping as this.
Earlier in this chapter, in rejecting Thomas Nagel's argument for the rationality of altruism, I agreed with Sidgwick and
Parfit that there is nothing irrational about being concerned with the quality of one's own
existence in a way that one is not concerned with the quality of existence of other individuals.
Without going back on this, I am now suggesting that rationality, in the broad sense that includes self-awareness and reflection
on the nature and point of our own existence, may push us towards concerns broader than the quality of our own existence;
but the process is not a necessary one, and those who do not take part in it – or who, in taking part, do not follow it all
the way to the ethical point of view – are not irrational or in error. Some people find collecting stamps or following their
favourite football team an entirely adequate way of giving purpose to their lives. There is nothing irrational about that;
but others again seek something more significant as they become more aware of their situation in the world and more reflective
about their purposes. To this third group, the ethical point of view offers a meaning and purpose in life that one does not
grow out of. At least, one cannot grow out of the ethical point of view until all ethical tasks have been accomplished. If
that utopia were ever achieved, our purposive nature might well leave us dissatisfied, much as egoists might be dissatisfied
when they have everything they need to be happy. There is nothing paradoxical about this, for we should not expect evolution
to have equipped us, in advance, with the ability to find satisfaction in a situation that has never previously occurred.
Nor is this going to be a practical problem in the near future.
I will conclude by making these abstract speculations more personal and concrete. Henry Spira was one of the most effective twentieth-century American activists for animals. (To give just one example, it
is due to Spira more than anyone else that the words ‘not tested on animals’ appear on so many cosmetic products today.) In
addition to his many campaigns that saved an immense amount of animal suffering, Spira marched for civil rights in the South,
fought against corruption in the National Maritime Union, and taught underprivileged kids in New York high schools. I had
the good fortune to count him as my friend, staying with him many times in the sparsely furnished, rent-controlled New York
apartment that served as his home and his office. When he had cancer and knew that the end was not far away, I asked him what
had driven him to spend his life working for others. He replied:
I guess basically one wants to feel that one's life has amounted to more than just consuming products and generating garbage.
I think that one likes to look back and say that one's done the best one can to make this a better place for others. You can
look at it from this point of view: what greater motivation can there be than doing whatever one possibly can to reduce pain
and suffering?
That answer will not provide everyone with overwhelming reasons for acting morally. It cannot be proven that we are all rationally
required to reduce pain and suffering and make the world a better place for others. Ethically indefensible behaviour is not
always irrational. We will probably always need the sanctions of the law and social pressure to provide additional reasons
against serious violations of ethical standards. On the other hand, those reflective enough to ask why they should act ethically
are also those most likely to appreciate the reasons Spira offered for taking the ethical point of view.