Chapter 13 The ‘sociological turn’ in French liberal thought

William Logue
In the period before World War I, French liberals faced a daunting challenge: how to re-found the relations between the individual and society on the one hand and between society and the state on the other. These were hardly new issues and could be traced back to the dawn of Western political thought. But political upheavals during and after the French Revolution and the evolution of ideas spread during the Enlightenment – which Marcel Gauchet calls the ‘sortie de religion’ – had given these ancient problems a newfound urgency.1 In France, the justification of the social and political order based on the teachings of religious tradition and doctrine was losing its authority. Initially, philosophy had made an attempt – while not presenting itself as a substitute for religion – to fill this gap, which was beginning to worry the educated classes. When it became clear that philosophy was not up to the task, the emerging field of sociology was called upon to stand in its stead. This ‘sociological turn’, which took place in the early decades of the Third Republic, would not provide the solutions its makers promised, but it nonetheless retains its relevance for contemporary discussion of these issues.2
Both philosophy and sociology saw as their major social utility the presumed ability to furnish a new basis for moral obligation in an age of increasing individualism. They both sought to found this obligation on reason and science, replacing the role previously played by revealed religion. With the advent of the Third Republic they both sought to move from theory to practice by reshaping and amplifying the role of public education – both elementary education for the masses and secondary education for the elites.

The Eclectics: philosophical liberalism

The focus of philosophical liberalism in nineteenth-century France was on how to defend individual liberty against what were seen as its three major enemies: the state, religious orthodoxy and the passions of the masses. While the concept of the value of the individual clearly had roots in Christianity, some eighteenth-century thinkers had nonetheless tried to dispense with God and religion in the philosophical defence of the individual. But the upheavals of the French Revolution encouraged nineteenth-century liberals to hope that religion, the state and freedom could at last be reconciled. This hope was embodied in the work of Victor Cousin (1792–1867) and his followers, known as the Eclectics.4 The Eclectics argued that liberty needed the state and the church to defend it against the passions of the mob and the tyranny of dictators, but only a state and church purged of their absolutist claims would be compatible with liberty.
A leading Eclectic, the philosopher and politician Jules Simon (1814–96), summed up the conditions necessary for political liberty in three principles: ‘first, written law replaces arbitrary authority in all matters; second, law consecrates and respects the natural and inalienable rights of man; and third … government never regards itself as having rights and interests of its own’, but serves the general interest.5 Simon’s emphasis on written law reflected the Enlightenment’s illusion that all political problems could be resolved by devising the right constitution and the right laws. This preference for the legislative over the executive would persist in French liberalism through the Third and Fourth Republics, and separated the Eclectics from their contemporary François Guizot (1787–1874) whose liberalism stressed the role of the executive.
The philosophical character of the Eclectics’ political philosophy showed itself most clearly in their devotion to the concept of ‘natural and inalienable rights of man’. They were the direct heirs of the philosophy of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen.6 Like the authors of the Declaration they recognized that rights were not absolutes, but needed to be domesticated to the needs of civil society. Their error was to assume that the civil society of their time was mature, and indeed ‘natural’. Nature had given men – and only men of property and education – the qualities needed for public life; their rights were thus necessarily superior to those of the propertyless and to those of women and children. Although a restricted suffrage seems in contradiction with the Eclectics’ ideal of the free and responsible individual, it was deemed necessary because the majority, even of males, remained uneducated and ignorant. Nonetheless, because democracy clearly had its roots in the liberal ideal of equal rights, the Eclectics were better able than Guizot, who saw suffrage as a function, not a right, to accept a gradually broadened franchise.7
Like Guizot and the Doctrinaires, the Eclectics believed in the importance of property rights and a free economy. They did not, however, share the laissez-faire economists’ blind faith in the justice and efficiency of the market.8 Unfortunately for French liberalism, the Eclectics’ individualism did not provide a strong bulwark against an economic libertarian interpretation of individual rights. The Eclectics’ roots in Judeo-Christian ethics and the historical French tradition of social regulation gave birth to a liberalism attentive to what seemed possible in their society, but they were unable to reconcile it with their philosophical individualism. Hence, the Eclectics’ philosophical liberalism remained an effective basis on which to attack the authoritarian rule of Napoleon III, but seemed anachronistic in the face of the social conflicts of the Third Republic.

Renouvier: bringing Kant down To earth

The sociologists of the Third Republic would reject the Eclectics’ attempt to establish a doctrine of human rights founded on the presumed nature of the individual person. Instead they proposed that rights should be founded on the nature of society as it had evolved in modern times. But before this sociological approach could become dominant there was a period of transition in which philosophers attempted to give the philosophical defence of liberty a more solid and ‘scientific’ foundation than the Eclectics had achieved. This effort reached its pinnacle in the work of Charles Renouvier (1815–1903) and Alfred Fouillée (1838–1912).
Renouvier set out to build a comprehensive philosophical system based on his heterodox version of Kant’s critical philosophy. He believed in the possibility of constructing a system of morals, both public and private, that would not only compel intellectual acceptance, but also influence behaviour. Like Kant, he believed that morality was meaningless without free will. And in his attempt to demonstrate that free will really existed, despite the doctrine of universal determinism proclaimed by contemporary science, Renouvier examined the social and psychological forces that seem to constrain freedom of thought and action in order to find those interstices where free will might live. Human beings, he observed, are born into a world that already exists; the formation of their minds is shaped by genetic inheritance, but even more powerfully by a social inheritance. Our ideas of right and wrong, at all levels, from the individual to international relations, are shaped by what we are taught and by what we observe (which often contradicts what we are taught). Some people, however, at specific times in their lives, are able to transcend these determining forces. If this were not the case human society would have stagnated long ago. Human decisions, free not predetermined, have been able to alter the course of individual lives and, in some cases, that of the larger society. This analysis of free will (much more sophisticated than I can show here) shaped Renouvier’s approach to social and political questions, and was the foundation of his liberalism.9
After the failure of the 1848 Revolution, Renouvier turned away from the utopian hopes of his youth and devoted himself to rebuilding the intellectual foundations of liberalism. Liberals, he thought, had long been content with the question-begging doctrine of the automatic harmony between individual desires and social good. Renouvier concluded that the solution to the problem of the relations between the individual and society was to be found in moral philosophy, for which he attempted to provide a more solid foundation in his Science de la morale.10 His goal was to develop a moral philosophy independent of any religious creed or metaphysical doctrine – one that stood on reason alone.
Renouvier thought that any practical morals or politics had to rest ultimately on sound theory, even though that theory could never be directly applied to everyday life. Theory was necessary to guarantee the validity of our highest aspirations as well as to serve as a yardstick of our progress towards achieving them. The gap between the ideal and the real could never be closed because, in contrast to the faith of utopians and revolutionaries, we can never cut ourselves free from the past. While the sociologists believed that the scientific study of present society would satisfy both our practical needs and higher aspirations, Renouvier was persuaded that humans needed a transcendental ideal and that it was possible to find that transcendence within immanence, that is, without reference to anyone or anything outside of nature.
Without a rational measure of moral truth – a rational absolute – human beings would risk sinking into a relativism that accepts whatever is as right. But moral philosophy had also to provide practical guidance for ordinary people, an applied right viable in the ‘state of war’, as Renouvier called any society that ever existed or could exist, in contrast to the ideal but unrealizable ‘state of peace’, in which all men behaved rationally. Moral autonomy à la Kant was unattainable, but the individual could at least seek to preserve as much of her own autonomy and as much respect for the autonomy of others as the real world permitted. Renouvier called these practical morals the ‘right of defence’. Liberalism required a kind of political casuistry parallel to this casuistry of ‘defence’ required by practical morals.
One element of the right of defence is the right of property, which was essential both to outer liberty and inner autonomy. Renouvier thought that the most pressing social problem of his time was the question of how to extend the benefits of property to the mass of society without undermining existing property rights. Collectivism would destroy hard-won existing rights without safeguarding the workers’ inner autonomy. Society had an obligation, however, to limit the growth of inequalities and to create social guarantees which would provide workers with a kind of security equivalent to that provided to the bourgeoisie by property. Like most liberals, Renouvier placed his hope in the work of voluntary associations and worried about using the coercive power of the state.
In considering the state, Renouvier applied the same approach he had used to questions of private morality. At the level of theory persons were morally obliged to obey only that government which had their rational consent, but in practice such a requirement would lead to the dissolution of society. For Renouvier the form of government that most closely approximated the requirement of individual consent was the liberal democratic republic.11 Majority rule was the best that could be achieved in real societies, and the form most likely to let individuals develop their inherent possibilities. Majorities could be oppressive, but the right of resistance to that oppression was conditional, not absolute. In the long run, the best one could do was to try to educate majorities to respect the rights of minorities, but also to teach the rich minority to respect the rights of the poor majority. None of this would be easy – it would take generations – but it would give the republic a moral purpose which transcended the individual egoism of its citizens. Renouvier’s individualist philosophy thus recognized the individual’s obligation to participate in the collective purposes of society.
Liberalism would perhaps have fared better in the twentieth century if it had taken the lesson of Renouvier’s understanding of free will more seriously. People will always be free to choose the wrong as well as the right, and because they do not make those choices in a vacuum but in society, the wrong can always be propagated and society can regress as well as progress.
Philosophy was often criticized for rehashing the same questions over and over again without being able to resolve them. Science seemed to be providing enduring answers, permanently erasing old errors. It was not surprising that at the turn of the century many believed that the accomplishments of the natural sciences could be replicated by the social sciences. Yet many efforts to create a social science were far from liberal – those of Comte and Marx, for example. And, on the liberal side, there were several divergent paths, drawing on different foundations. One of the more remarkable projects was that of Alfred Espinas, who drew on the novel science of evolutionary biology.

Alfred Espinas: biology, sociology, and liberalism

Alfred Espinas (1844–1922) believed that Comte had failed to establish sociology on a scientific basis and turned for his inspiration to Herbert Spencer’s evolutionary biology. While he rejected Spencer’s extreme individualism, Espinas agreed that philosophy and sociology had to develop out of biology if they were to become scientific.12 The principle which bound biology and sociology together was that of evolutionary development: differentiation and organization. Societies, like other organisms, were products of evolutionary development out of simpler forms. The science of society had to begin by retracing this development. Espinas set out to do this in his celebrated thesis Des sociétés animales (1877), in which he argued that all organisms beyond the simplest are really societies, and higher organisms are societies of societies.13 An individual of a higher species was really a society of lesser individuals, and the society of higher individuals was itself an individual.
For Espinas the individual consciousness is a sort of conscience collective, which lacks the absolute unity and distinctiveness attributed to it by philosophy. The defence of liberty could not, therefore, be based on the concept of the autonomous individual. Strongly contested in its day, this view of the human mind gained considerable support a century later. His idea that society itself possesses a conscience collective has encountered a more durable resistance because of its elitist assumption that this consciousness was physically resident in society’s intellectual elite, society’s ‘brain’. Espinas thought this a necessary consequence of evolutionary development, forgetting perhaps that similar views were to be found as far back as Plato. That modern societies possess a higher degree of differentiation and a more complex form of organization than their pre decessors was hard to dispute, but the consequences of this evolution for freedom were less evident and subject to much dispute.
At a time when liberalism was increasingly under attack from many directions – socialism, nationalism, religion, caesarism – philosophical liberalism no longer provided a credible defence. By giving liberalism a scientific foundation Espinas believed it might be saved. Yet sociology would begin to find its way forward only when it succeeded in breaking free from its roots in biology. Human society would then be viewed as sui generis and not to be explained by looking at animal societies.

Alfred Fouillée: a liberal synthesis

Rather than abandon philosophy for sociology, Alfred Fouillée (1838–1912) believed that it was possible to extract what was true from humanity’s whole intellectual past, arguing that humanity is headed towards an era in which the theological, philosophical and scientific ages would be synthesized.14 He set out confidently to show that Comte, Darwin, Spencer, Kant and Hegel could be reconciled. The key to his synthesis was the concept of ‘idée-force’ which he employed to analyse all the major philosophical questions in the Western tradition. Fouillée believed that all ideas contain elements of volition and emotion, and are inseparable from action, but idées-forces are special cases – ideas like beauty, justice, freedom – which drive humans to realize them.
Fouillée separated himself from Renouvier by arguing that it was not necessary to show that freedom is inherent in human nature and the phenomenal world since the idea of freedom is a sufficient basis for morals. He used the concept of evolution to introduce a teleological element into his understanding of freedom, but it was a finalism whose origin lay within humanity, not in the subjective consciousness of the individual, since self-consciousness is inseparable from the consciousness of others like ourselves. The idées-forces of reason and freedom were present in all humans and made truly human society possible.
In defence of his view of a free society, Fouillée carried out a devastating critique of Marxist socialism, unrivalled in his time and perhaps not surpassed in ours.15 Historical materialism led to overstating the role of material and unconscious factors in history and provided no means to measure their true role; class struggle doctrine led to the illusion that changing institutions would transform human beings; the labour theory of value simply repeated the errors of the liberal economists. Socialist utopianism would thus inevitably lead to tyranny. Where socialism was closer to the truth than the individualist philosophers of liberalism was in the stress it laid on the social nature of human beings. But their materialism prevented the socialists from giving an adequate explanation of this social nature. Importantly, Fouillée believed that the idealism of the philosophical liberals also failed this test.
Fouillée called his own political synthesis a libéralisme réformiste. He believed that it offered a reconciliation of individual freedom and social necessity which rested on a scientific understanding of human being and society and which at the same time responded most directly to pressing present needs. Reformist liberalism would rest on the intellectual base of a sociologie réformiste, which was the application to the study of society of his philosophy of idées-forces. The mere fact of social solidarity – stressed by socialists and sociologists – was an inadequate ground for political and social obligation and indeed dangerous because it undervalued the individual and took a mechanistic view of society. Reformist liberalism embodied the idée-force of social solidarity more as an aspiration than as a reality; it was an expression of human moral interdependence and could thus furnish a needed ground of obligation.
Fouillée believed that society transcends the individual and yet is within him. Individual wills do matter, and yet society is not simply the aggregate of individual wills as so many philosophers and economists claimed. Society is a sort of ‘organisme contractuel’. Fouillée’s concept of the ‘quasi-contract’ implied that the individual had obligations to society by virtue of belonging to it.16 Social welfare programmes were thus compatible with individual liberty. He also offered a defence of the nation against the internationalism of both the economic libertarians and the socialists. The national state was not an enemy of liberty; society is not a zero-sum game in which everything gained by the state is a loss for the individual and vice versa. People are freer in advanced societies. He offered an updated version of Adam Smith’s view on the proper role of the state: ‘Intervention by the state is therefore justified in those cases where private initiative and voluntary association show themselves radically impotent to assure the exercise of individual rights or to perform an indispensable work of social justice and collective social interest.’17 This observation is clearly sociological and reflects Fouillée’s conviction that public policy cannot be a simple matter of deduction from philosophical principles, but has to take into account the actual evolution of society.
One of the problems with philosophical liberalism was that its atomistic individualism was incompatible with its practitioners’ resistance to democracy. While liberals largely agreed on the need for a moral and intellectual elite to guide democratic government, they struggled to provide a rationale for that elite which would appear acceptable to the majority who did not belong to it. Though conscious that sociology was a rather young science to be claiming to offer solutions to contemporary social and political problems, Fouillée believed that it could nonetheless show the direction to follow while counselling the need for gradual steps and the avoidance of utopian solutions. Like many sociologists he argued that the mode of representation needed to be modified so that government could be more representative of society. While such remedies were popular in intellectual circles in France, they never (with the exception of proportional representation) gained much ground in political circles, which would become increasingly divided between individualist and collectivist parties. Unfortunately for French liberalism, Fouillée’s synthetic approach would appear too philosophical to the sociologists and too sociological to the philosophers.

Émile Durkheim: sociological liberalism

The efforts of Émile Durkheim (1858–1917) to convert sociology into an academic discipline are well known, but his role in the rise of a sociologically based new liberalism is less familiar.18 Durkheim rejected traditionalist conservatism, laissez-faire liberalism, and collectivist socialism, and much of his thought was occupied with the main problem of the new liberalism: how to combine adequate social integration with individual freedom. He aimed to produce a science of society which would support liberal values. Like Renouvier, he believed that the new urban, industrial, democratic and individualist society that was emerging in France needed a new science of morals. Durkheim recognized the achievements of the philosophers, but found them ineffective in changing human behaviour because they believed in a timeless and universal moral code. Sociology, he believed, would show that morals are historically variable and must be relevant to present conditions. He did not think this would lead to moral anarchy, but rather would bind individuals to their society more effectively than philosophy could.
Comparative sociological study convinced Durkheim that what all moral systems had in common was the obligation they imposed on the individual to obey rules of conduct whose source transcended her individual interests or will. Morals and religion both expressed an awareness that there is something that transcends the individual. Science could not banish the importance of transcendence in people’s lives; it could only lead us to understand that what transcends us, the source of the obligations that shape our moral lives, is not some God, but society. Sociology was thus the heir of both religion and philosophy, and could in the future play the role they had played in the past. Sociology would not replace biology and psychology, but neither could it be derived from them. Like other sociologists, Durkheim saw society as a being sui generis, distinct from the individuals that composed it, but at the same time inseparable from them. Society had to be studied directly, and the science that did so would be a science of the spirit and not of matter.
Society was thus for Durkheim both the empirical source and the moral foundation of individual liberty. All attempts to base a doctrine of liberty on the individual were therefore bound to fail in the future as they had in the past. The liberal tradition had tended to see the rights of the individual and of society as engaged in a kind a zero-sum game, while at the same time recognizing the importance of both. This contradiction could only be overcome by recognizing that social solidarity is one of the prerequisites of individual freedom. The rise of individualism was not caused by the rise of rationalism: rather, they were parallel growths having the same causes. The increasing variety of human experiences that resulted from the division of labour made the dictates of the conscience commune less and less imperative; people in ‘organic’ societies had to call on their reason for the guidance that had once come automatically from the group mind.
The nation loomed larger in sociological liberalism than in philosophical liberalism. Durkheim considered the nation to be the largest intelligible unit of social organization that had ever emerged, and therefore the main unit of study for sociology. This continuing importance of the nation was one reason why the new liberalism had to focus its attention on the role of the state, the only social institution which embraced the entire nation. The main problem of the existing French state in Durkheim’s view was the lack of intermediate bodies between the state and the individual.19 While the state had played the key historic role in freeing individuals from the oppressive power of intermediate bodies like the church and the guilds, it was not an adequate instrument of social solidarity, despite the valuable role of public education. What were needed were new intermediate bodies adapted to the character of modern society, which Durkheim thought should take the form of professional and occupational ‘corporations’.
Durkheimian sociology also showed liberals one way that acceptance of the apparent course of history could be combined with the determination to shape human existence through the pursuit of ideals. Durkheim was far from thinking that what is is right. He could with consistency describe the growth of the division of labour as a natural, inevitable, and indeed largely beneficial, social process and at the same time denounce the way that process had been going on in France and in the industrial West generally, as abnormal, as pathological. The Durkheimian effort to find a scientific bridge between the is and the ought was given its fullest expression in the work of his collaborator, Lucien Lévy-Bruhl (1857–1939), but the whole effort remained more philosophical than either would have liked.21
Durkheim’s sociology offered democratic liberalism intellectual weapons against those socialists who sought to use the argument of humans’ interdependence and debt to society as a justification for collectivism. It also offered a defence against those conservatives who sought to promote the social value of the family over that of the individual, or who insisted on human beings’ need for guidance which transcended rational understanding. It enabled liberalism to separate itself more clearly from the anarchism which held women and men accountable only to their own desires. And indeed sociology helped defend liberalism against some of its own internal weaknesses: simplistic rationalism, the tendency to an exaggerated individualism, the neglect of civic responsibility, a disregard for the fate of the less successful, a naive internationalism, a tendency to find reasons to be content with the status quo. Most importantly of all, it compelled liberals to take a new look at society and to realize that as society changed, so must liberalism change.

Célestin Bouglé: practical sociological liberalism

The liberal implications of Durkheim’s sociology are even more evident in the work of his mildly heterodox disciple Célestin Bouglé (1870–1940). Bouglé devoted much of his work to demonstrating that a true science of society was not hostile to democracy.22 He lamented that liberals, like others, readily appealed to science to validate their positions, but lacked a true idea of science. One important role of education in a democratic society had to be to remedy this ignorance. ‘If you want to judge whether egalitarian demands are well or ill-founded’, Bouglé argued, ‘the right question to ask is not “do they conform to the laws of nature?” but “are they in conformity with the ends of society?”’23 Natural law, whether conceived in traditional philosophical terms or modernized in an effort to explain society on the basis of physical or biological laws, was not a sound foundation for a liberal-democratic society.
As the most successful activist of the Durkheimians in public affairs, Bouglé demonstrated that the practical implications of modern sociology do not have to be centralist, elitist and anti-democratic. In adapting Durkheimian sociology to the needs of public education under the Third Republic, as a professor at the Sorbonne and as director of the École Normale Supérieure, he made use not only of those elements in sociology that promoted stability in a disturbed society but also those elements that could help generate aspirations for a better future. He both promoted scholarly research into social questions and addressed popular audiences on contemporary social and political issues.
Bouglé thought that the greatest threat to liberalism in his day was an attack on freedom of thought from both right and left, made more dangerous by the inability of liberals to defend it on philosophical grounds. Frightened by the Dreyfus Affair, the rise of anarchist violence and ultramontane extremism, too many liberals were ready to put new constraints on freedom of thought. Most liberals had not seen the need to build any constraints on the exercise of liberty into liberalism itself; unlike conservatives they lacked intellectual arguments against laissez-faire economics, or indeed against anarchism. Traditional constraints on anti-social behaviour – often religious in origin – were an implicit part of the liberal vision of society, but not well integrated into their theory. Bouglé argued that only by recognizing the social foundations of liberalism could they learn how to reinforce the constraints that were essential to society, while at the same time preserving the liberties proclaimed by philosophical liberalism.
It is to Bouglé’s credit that he was sceptical of some sociologists’ claims that a knowledge of social facts could furnish a sure guide to social reform. Even so, through the intellectual support that it lent to the Solidarist movement in the early twentieth century, sociology helped prepare the way for the post-World War II welfare state in France. Finding a way between the spirit-crushing totalitarian impulse of communism and the equally soulless anarchy of laissez-faire capitalism was no small contribution to the health of Western societies. Bouglé gave clear expression to a new liberalism which supported both individual rights and the search for social justice.24 Of course, sociology, like philosophy, had its inherent weaknesses as a foundation for liberalism. A degree of moral relativism seems inherent in sociology, and, like the anarchism inherent in the old liberalism, is today no longer held in check as it was in Bouglé’s day by the moral absolutes of the Judeo-Christian tradition. This was a consequence which Bouglé had not expected, since he shared Durkheim’s conviction that the ‘unmasking’ character of sociology in relation to morals was not a practical danger. Still, we are better off with a sociology that does not claim to have final answers to ultimate questions, and which respects the stubborn intractability of the human condition. Sociological liberalism remains a valuable counter-weight to the libertarian anarchism derived from philosophical liberalism. By raising a high standard for a science of sociology, it strengthened liberalism’s defences against all sorts of pseudo-scientific doctrines – like biological racism – which ravaged the twentieth century.

Conclusion

Liberal political thought whether philosophical or sociological seemed ill equipped to deal with the dogmatic certainties of its opponents in the period after World War I. The disasters of the war had undermined the pre-war liberal faith in the nation-state as an agent of progress. And this loss of confidence came at a moment when liberalism was confronted with the authoritarian nationalism of Fascist Italy, the racial nationalism of Nazi Germany, and the faux-internationalism of the Soviet Union. Even in its weakened condition, liberalism did help France steer her own course during the crisis years of the 1920s and 1930s. The influence of the new liberalism shone most clearly in the ephemeral triumph of the Popular Front.
But what community was sufficiently attractive to counterbalance the appeal of individualism? Sociological liberals before 1914 believed that the nation-state was the community that had fostered individualism, but that smaller communities within the nation were also necessary for social solidarity. Most philosophical liberals shared this view in practice, but their belief that freedom stems from human nature rather than from the evolution of society meant that the logical context of individual freedom is not the nation but humanity as a whole. While nationalism was discredited by two catastrophic wars in thirty years, a globalization driven by economic rationalism also seemed to be a threat to the individual. Younger generations of French men and women describe themselves as ‘Europeans’, but the European Union today evokes little loyalty. The conflicts generated by substantial immigration, especially from non-European countries, has stimulated the widest variety of reactions from the most extreme individualism to the most reactionary nativism. An effective liberalism would have to realize that for historical reasons humanity is too diverse to provide the common beliefs and common aspirations needed by any viable community.
When I was writing From Philosophy to Sociology in the 1980s, I was still thinking in the context of the conflict between liberalism and Marxism. Now in 2011, the greatest threat to political liberalism appears to come from extremist economic liberalism, commonly dubbed ‘ultraliberalism’ or ‘neoliberalism’28 by the French, though it is only a parody of liberalism. What has not changed in the last thirty-odd years is the relevance of the discussion that went on between philosophy and sociology in late nineteenth-century France. Liberalism was born in the conviction that women and men could undertake, through reason, the control of their own affairs. Sociology helped to restore this original impulse by showing that the activities of society, led by, but not absorbed by, the state, could be expanded without the diminution of individual freedom. Over the past century we have learned that both Marxist collectivism and laissez-faire economism are simplistic, indeed utopian, efforts to cope with the problems generated by the rise of modern urbanized, industrialized society. French liberals, both philosophical and sociological, were committed to the search for a more nuanced understanding – one that would make it possible to uphold an ideal of human freedom and to deal pragmatically with the problems raised by the effort to create a society that embodied that ideal.
1 M. Gauchet, Un monde désenchanté (Paris: Éditions de l’Atelier, 2004).
2 I was initially startled by Raf Geenens’s use of the expression ‘sociological turn’ to describe the thesis of my From Philosophy to Sociology: The Evolution of French Liberalism, 1870–1914 (DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1983). It seemed to exaggerate the importance of that work and at the same time to overstate the neatness of the transition I had tried to describe, for certainly there were sociological elements in French political thought before the end of the nineteenth century and there are philosophical elements in the twenty-first century. But I remain convinced that something had changed in the way most French liberals saw the world, and I still see no better way of describing it.
3 Several phrases throughout this chapter are taken from my From Philosophy to Sociology. I have chosen not to identify them explicitly.
4 In From Philosophy to Sociology I deal with the Eclectics in ch. II: ‘Eclecticism and Individualism’, pp. 17–50. A bibliography of the works of the principal Eclectics (Adolphe Franck, Elme-Marie Caro, Paul Janet and Jules Simon) can be found on pp. 261–2.
5 J. Simon, La liberté (Paris: Hachette, 1859), v. ii, p. 231.
6 Cf. M. Gauchet, La révolution des droits de l’homme (Paris: Gallimard, 1989).
7 Claude Lefort persuasively tied the eighteenth-century foundation of the Rights of Man to the emergence of democratic society, a connection which he sees as a necessary barrier to totalitarianism. C. Lefort, Essais sur le politique (XIXe–XX siècles) (Paris: Seuil, 1986), pp. 31–58.
8 See B. E. Harcourt, The Illusion of Free Markets (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2011).
9 See ch. II, ‘The Philosophical Defense of Liberty’, in W. Logue, Charles Renouvier: Philosopher of Liberty (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1993), pp. 84–121.
10 C. Renouvier, Science de la morale (Paris: Ladrange, 1869). One of the summits of nineteenth-century French philosophy, this work remains underappreciated.
11 On Renouvier’s republicanism the essential work is M.-C. Blais, Au principe de la république: le cas Renouvier (Paris: Gallimard, 2000); see also special issue of Corpus: revue de philosophie 45 (2003), on ‘Renouvier: philosophie politique’; and K. Steven Vincent, ‘The Republican Moment(s) in Modern France’, European Journal of Political Theory 6 (2007), 239–48.
12 On Espinas, see Logue, From Philosophy to Sociology, pp. 100–10, 264. On Espinas and the Eclectics, see J. I. Brooks III, The Eclectic Legacy: Academic Philosophy and the Human Sciences in Nineteenth-Century France (Dover: University of Delaware Press, 1998).
13 ‘It’s now widely agreed in progressive social circles that all humankind constitutes a single superorganism’, says a Soviet secret policeman in William T. Vollmann’s novel Europe Central (New York: Penguin, 2006), p. 95.
14 See, for example, Robert Good’s Ph.D. dissertation ‘The Philosophy and Social Thought of Alfred Fouillée’ (McGill University, 1993).
15 A. Fouillée, Le socialisme et la sociologie réformiste, 2nd edn (Paris: Alcan, 1909).
16 See M. C. Mirow, ‘The Social-Obligation Norm of Property: Duguit, Hayem and Others’, Florida Journal of International Law 22 (August 2010), 191–266. Also the recent edition of Fouillée’s La propriété sociale de la démocratie presented by Jean-Fabien Spitz (Lormont: Le Bord de l’Eau, 2008).
17 Fouillée, Le socialisme, p. 300.
18 The best analysis of Durkheim’s politics is B. Lacroix, Durkheim et la politique (Paris: Fondation Nationale des Sciences Politiques, 1981). See also the astute work of Anthony Giddens: e.g. A. Giddens, ‘Durkheim’s Political Sociology’, Sociological Review, new series 19 (1971), 477–519, and Capitalism and Modern Social Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971).
19 See A. Greve, ‘Emile Durkheim Revisited: Les corps intermediaires’, Citizenship Studies 2 (1998), 313–28.
20 Parts of this paragraph are taken from Logue, From Philosophy to Sociology, p. 176.
21 L. Lévy-Bruhl, La morale et la science des mœurs (Paris: Alcan, 1903), another neglected masterpiece.
22 His thesis was published as Les idées égalitaires: étude sociologique (Paris: Alcan, 1899).
23 C. Bouglé, ‘Anthropologie et démocratie’, Revue de métaphysique et de morale 5 (1897), 443–61.
24 See W. Logue, ‘Sociologie et politique: le libéralisme de Célestin Bouglé’, Revue française de sociologie 20 (1979), 141–61.
25 C. Lefort, ‘Les droits de l’homme et l’État-Providence’, Revue interdisciplinaire d’études juridiques 13 (1984), reprinted in Lefort, Essais sur le politique, pp. 31–58.
26 See M. Gauchet, ‘Les droits de l’homme ne sont pas une politique’, Le débat 3 (July–August, 1980), reprinted in M. Gauchet, La démocratie contre elle-même (Paris: Gallimard, 2002), pp. 1–26; see also Samuel Moyn’s contribution to this volume.
27 D. Brooks, ‘Human Nature Today’, New York Times (26 June 2009).
28 See S. Audier, Le Colloque Lippmann: aux origines du néo-libéralisme (Lormont: Le Bord de l’Eau, 2008); see also Serge Audier’s contribution to this volume.