The Onto-theo-logical Nature of Metaphysics
In this seminar we made an attempt to engage Hegel in conversation. A conversation with a thinker can only deal with the object of thought. By “object” we mean, depending on the given situation, the case in dispute, the thing to be argued about which alone is for thought
the case which concerns thought. However, strife over this thing which is in dispute was by no means started by thought without good reason, as it were. Object for thought is that which is the disputable proper in a strife. The word strife
31 means principally not discord but distress. The object of thought bothers thinking in such a manner as to lead thought first to its object and, thence, to itself.
For Hegel the object of thought is thought as such. In order not to misinterpret circumscribing the object under consideration, that is, thought as such, either psychologically or epistemologically, we are obliged to add by way of explanation: Thought as such, in the developed fullness of the suchness of what is thought. What we mean here by suchness of thought can only be understood through Kant, from the nature of the transcendental which Hegel, however, thinks as absolute, which in turn means speculative to him. This is what Hegel had in mind when he spoke of the thinking of thought as such that it is developed “purely in the element of thought.”
32 If we are to interpret this tersely and topically—which scarcely does justice in our thinking to the matter under consideration—we would have to say: The object of thinking for Hegel is “thought.” However, unfolded to the depths of its essential freedom, this is “the absolute Idea.” Hegel says of it toward the end of the
Science of Logic33: “The absolute Idea alone is
Being, imperishable
Life, Truth knowing itself, and it is
Truth complete.” Thus, Hegel himself bestows that name which is written over the whole object of occidental thinking, and he bestows it expressly on the object of his own thinking, the name of
Being.
In the seminar
34 we discussed the severalfold and yet unified use of the word “Being.” For Hegel, Being means, first of all, but
never exclusively, “indefinite immediacy.” Being is looked upon from the point of view of determining mediation, that is, from absolute notion and, hence, in relation to it. “The Truth of Being is Essence,”
35 in other words, absolute reflection. The Truth of Essence is Notion in the sense of an in-finite knowing-itself. Being is absolute thought thinking itself. Absolute thought alone is the Truth of Being, it “is” Being. Truth, in Hegel, everywhere is equivalent to self-assured knowledge of what-may-be-known as such.
Hegel, however, thinks the object of his thinking topically at first in a conversation with the history of previous thinking. Hegel is the first one who can and must think in that way. Hegel’s relationship to the history of philosophy is speculative and historic only in so far as it is speculative. The characteristic movement in history is an event in the sense of a dialectical process. Hegel writes:
36 “The same development of thought which is treated in the history of philosophy is being portrayed in every philosophy, yet emancipated from that historic externality,
purely in the element of thinking.”
At this we are startled and stymied. Philosophy as such and the history of philosophy are, according to Hegel’s own words, supposed to stand in relation of externality to each other. Yet, the externality of which Hegel thinks is by no means external in the sense of mere superficiality and indifference. Externality in this context refers to “outside of.” “Outside” is where all history and every real process has its domicile as contrasted with the movement of the absolute Idea. The externality of history as explained in relation to the Idea is the result of the self-alienation of the Idea. Externality is itself a dialectical determination. We are, therefore, way off in our understanding of the real thought of Hegel’s if we note as a fact that Hegel has welded into a unity historic conceptions and systematic thought in philosophy. For in Hegel’s case it is neither a matter of an academic concept of history nor a system in the sense of a theoretical structure.
What is on our mind as we make these remarks about philosophy and its relation to history? We intend to show that the object of thinking is, for Hegel, historical as such; but historical must be taken in the sense of a happening whose character as process is determined by the dialectic of Being. Object of thinking, for Hegel, is Being as self-thinking thought which ultimately becomes self-conscious in the process of its speculative development. Thus, thought runs through stages of various developments and, hence, must of necessity pass through previously undeveloped phases.
Thus there arises ultimately in Hegel’s experience of the object of thinking a peculiar maxim, the authoritative way and manner in which he speaks to the thinkers preceding him.
Therefore, if we wish to attempt a conversation with Hegel’s thought, we must talk to him not only about the same topic, but about the same topic in the same way. Nevertheless, the Same is not the identical. In identity difference disappears. In the Same difference appears. It appears the more urgently the more determinately we engage in thinking about the same object in the same manner. Hegel thinks of the Being of Existence speculative-historically. Now, in so far as Hegel’s thinking belongs into a period of history (this does not by any stretch of the imagination mean to the past), we shall attempt to think about Hegel’s Being in the same way, that is, historically.
Thinking can stay with a topic only by becoming more pertinent to the matter under consideration in the process of remaining-with-it, by having the same topic become more disputable. This being the case, the topic requires thought to put up with it in its idiosyncrasy, hold its ground by establishing a correspondence, and brings the matter to an issue. Thought, if it sticks to its topic, must, if the topic is Being, consent to an issue with Being. Accordingly, in our conversation with Hegel as well as in the interest of what has just been stated, we are obliged at the outset to clarify the sameness of the identical topic. In agreement with what we said it is incumbent on us to elucidate in our discourse with the history of philosophy the difference in the topic of thinking concomitantly with the difference in historical reality. In this lecture such a clarification has to be necessarily brief and sketchy.
For the purpose of shedding light on the disparity which obtains between Hegel’s thinking and the thinking we shall attempt, let us consider three things.
Our questions are:
1. What is the object of thinking in his and in our case?
2. What is the criterion in a discourse involving the history of thought in his and in our case?
3. What is the character of the discourse in his and in our case?
Concerning the First Question
For Hegel, the object of thought is Being in view of the suchness of existential thought in and as absolute Thought. For us, the object of thinking is the Same, hence, Being, but Being in view of its difference from Existence. Expressed even more precisely, for Hegel the object of thinking is Thought as absolute Notion. For us, the object of thinking is, by way of a first statement, difference as difference.
37
Concerning the Second Question
For Hegel, the criterion for the discussion involving the history of philosophy is the degree of penetration into the vigor and milieu of that which was thought by former thinkers. It is not by chance that Hegel establishes his maxim in the course of his conversation with Spinoza and prior to a discussion with Kant.
38 In Spinoza Hegel discovers the perfect “point of view of substance,” which, however, cannot be the highest because Being has not been thought of as yet to the degree and absolutely fundamentally as self-thinking Thought. Being, as substance and substantiality, has not yet unfolded itself as subject in its absolute subjectivity. Nevertheless, Spinoza is stimulating the entire thinking of German idealism again and again and immediately generates a contradiction because he has Thought start with the Absolute. The way of Kant, on the contrary, is different and one that is by far more decisive for absolutistic idealistic thought and for philosophy in general than the system of Spinoza. Hegel sees in Kant’s idea of the original synthesis of apperception “one of the profoundest principles for speculative development.”
39 The relative influence of thinkers Hegel discovers in what they thought in so far as it may be raised to the appropriate stage of absolute Thought. Thought becomes absolute only by virtue of the fact that it moves in its dialectic-speculative process and requires for it an appropriate graduation.
For us, the criterion in our discussion involving historical tradition is the same in so far as it is a matter of penetrating the vigor of prior thinking. However, we are not looking for vigor in what has already been thought, but in something that has not yet been thought. It is in this something which provides thought with the sphere in which it has its being. Still it is what has been thought that first prepares the way for the not-yet-thought which enters again and again with its overabundance. The standard for that which has not yet been thought does not lead to an incorporation of what has previously been thought into a still higher development and systematization which outdistances it, but demands the release of traditional thinking into the past which is still preserved. Originally, the past controls tradition throughout and constitutes its anterior being without being thought of specially as and in terms of a beginning.
Concerning the Third Question
For Hegel, the discussion involving the previous history of philosophy has the character of a cancellation,
40 that is, of mediating understanding in the sense of finding absolute Reason.
For us, the character of the discussion involving the history of thought no longer signifies cancellation, but “backtracking.”
41
Cancellation leads to the high-level gathering realm of the absolutely posited truth in the sense of a perfectly unfolded certainty of self-knowing knowledge.
The “back track” reveals the realm thus far skipped on the basis of which the essence of truth becomes for the first time worthy to be thought.
After this brief characterization of the difference between Hegel’s thinking and our own regarding the object, criterion, and character of a discussion involving the history of thought, we shall attempt to promote our discussion with Hegel, which we have already begun, a trifle more in the direction of clarity. By this we mean that we shall dare to make an attempt at “backtracking.”
The phrase “backtracking” easily makes for several misinterpretations. To “backtrack” does not imply taking an isolated step in one’s thinking, but a kind of thought movement, and a rather long way. In so far as “backtracking” determines the character of our discussion involving the history of occidental thought, thinking leads us, in a manner of speaking, out of what has up to now been thought in philosophy. Thought steps aside from its object, Being, and thus changes what is thought into the opposite wherein we glimpse it especially in view of what constitutes the source of all this thinking because basically it makes the realm of its abode available. This is, in contrast to Hegel, not a traditional, already posed problem, but it is the problem which has never even been asked throughout the history of thought. For the time being and unavoidably we designate it in the language of tradition. We speak of a
difference between Being and Existence. The “back track” starts with what has not yet been thought, from difference as such, to proceed toward what is yet to be thought. That is the
oblivion of difference. The oblivion we have in mind here is that of an enshrouding
42 of difference as such—we are thinking of a
Léthe (concealment). This enshrouding originally went unnoticed. Oblivion belongs to difference because the latter belongs to the former. It is not as if oblivion overcame subsequently difference in consequence of the forgetfulness of man’s thinking.
The difference of Existence and Being is the realm within which metaphysics, that is, occidental thinking in the totality of its essence can be what in effect it is. “Backtracking” hence goes from metaphysics into the essence of metaphysics. The remark concerning Hegel’s use of the severally interpreted main term “Being” permits us to recognize that any use of the word Being and Existence can never be fixed for a particular epoch of history during which clarity has been introduced into the concept “Being.” Moreover, if we speak of “Being” we never take this word in the sense of a species under whose empty generality the doctrines concerning existence, historically considered, belong as individual cases. “Being,” as the case may be, proclaims destiny and, hence, control of tradition.
Now, the “back track” from metaphysics into its essence requires, however, duration and endurance whose limits are known to us. Only one thing is clear: The “Back track” needs preparation which must be hazarded now and here. We do this, however, in view of Existence as such in the Whole, as it now is and begins to show itself more unambiguously as time goes on. What now is has been given the stamp by the domineering nature of modern technology. This hegemony has already found its expression in all areas of life in characteristics going by various names, such as functionalization, perfection, automatization, bureaucratization, information. Just as we call our concept of living reality biology, we could call the presentation and structuralizing of the thoroughly technically-permeated existence technology. This term may serve as a designation for the metaphysics of the atomic age. The “back track” from metaphysics into the essence of metaphysics is—seen as of now and based on insight into the present—the trek from technology, from the present age with its description and interpretation geared to technology, into the essence of modern technology which we will yet have to master in thought.
Let this suggestion also suffice to keep away the other natural misinterpretation of the term “back track,” meaning the opinion that the trek consists in going back in history to the earliest thinkers of occidental philosophy. Of course, the whereto of the “back track” unfolds and becomes apparent only when the “backtracking” has been accomplished.
In order to obtain a comprehensive view of the Hegelian metaphysics
43 in our seminar, we chose expediently a discussion of the section with which the first book of the
Science of Logic, “The Doctrine of Being,” begins. Even the title of the section furnishes enough food for thought in every word. It says: “Wherewith must we start science?” Hegel’s answer to this question consists in the demonstration that the beginning is of a “speculative nature.” This means that the beginning is neither something immediate nor something mediate. The nature of this beginning we then endeavored to express in one speculative statement: “The beginning is the result.” According to the plural interpretation of the dialectic, the “is” in this sentence indicates several things. For once, it conveys that the beginning is—taking the
resultare literally
44—the rebounding of thought reflecting upon itself from the perfection of dialectical movement. The perfection of this movement, the absolute Idea, is the unfolded closed Whole, the fullness of Being. The rebound from this fullness results in the emptiness of Being. Science (the absolute self-knowing knowledge) must begin here. Beginning and end of the movement, and prior to them the movement itself, remains everywhere Being. Being asserts itself as internally gyrating movement from fullness to extreme alienation and from alienation to self-perfecting fullness. Object of thought is, hence, for Hegel thought thinking itself as internally gyrating Being. Were we to reverse the speculative statement concerning the beginning, which is not only justifiable but necessary, it would read: “The result is the beginning.” Actually, we ought to start with the result in so far as the beginning evolves from it.
This says the same as does the remark which Hegel inserts casually and
parenthetically in the section dealing with the Beginning, toward the end:
45 “…
(and it would seem
God has the indisputable right that we
should begin with him).” According to the problem stated in the section-heading we
are concerned with the “beginning of science.” If science has to start with God,
then it is the science of God, theology. This designation suggests its later
significance. Accordingly, theo-logy is a statement made by representational
thinking about God.
Theólogos, theología, means, first and
foremost, the mythico-poetical legendizing about gods without any connection with a
doctrine of faith or a church doctrine.
Why is “science”—since Fichte the name for metaphysics—why is science theology? I reply, because science is the systematic development of knowledge, in which form the Being of Existence knows itself and thus is true. The scholastic title for the Science of Being, that is, the Science of Existence as such in general, as it emerged during the transition period from the Middle Ages to the present era, is ontosophy or ontology.
Now, occidental metaphysics, however, has been since its beginnings among the Greeks and still is uncommitted to these labels, especially those of ontology and theology. In my inaugural lecture What is Metaphysics? (1929) I, therefore, clarified metaphysics as a problem of Existence as such and Existence in the Whole. The totality of the Whole is the unity of Existence, which unity unites by virtue of being the productive ground. For him who can read this means that metaphysics is onto-theo-logic. Whoever has, through his own development, experienced theology, be it that of Christian faith, or that of philosophy, will prefer nowadays to be silent about God as an object of thought and thinking. For, the onto-theological character of metaphysics has become questionable to thinking persons, not by reason of some sort of atheism, but because of an intellectual experience in which the still unthought unity of the essence of metaphysics revealed itself within onto-theo-logic. However, the essence of this metaphysics will still remain to our minds as what is most worthy of giving thought to so long as thought does not break off arbitrarily and hence unappropriately the discussion involving its fateful tradition.
In the 5th edition of
What is Metaphysics? (1949) I made special reference in the supplemental Introduction to the onto-theological essence of metaphysics.
46 However, it would be rash to assert that metaphysics is theology because it is reputed to be ontology. We should begin by saying that metaphysics is theology, a statement about God, because God enters philosophy. In this way the problem becomes more acute as a problem regarding the onto-theo-logical character of metaphysics: How does God get into philosophy, not only into recent philosophy, but into philosophy as such? This problem can be answered only if, as a problem, it has previously been sufficiently developed.
The problem as to how God got into philosophy can only then be thought through and done justice to, if in the course of investigation the whither of God has become sufficiently clear. It is the problem of philosophy as such. So long as we scan the history of philosophy merely historically we shall find that God got everywhere into it. Let us suppose, however, that philosophy, as thought, is the free, spontaneously pursued involvement in Existence as such, then God can get into philosophy only in so far as philosophy as such autonomously and by virtue of its own essence demands it and lays down the that and the how of God entering her. The problem as to how God gets into philosophy, therefore, reverts to the problem: Whence comes the essential onto-theological constitution of metaphysics? Taking on the problem thus formulated means, however, that we are “backtracking.”
In doing this we now give serious thought to the original essence of the onto-theological structure of all metaphysics and ask the question: How does God get into metaphysics and along with him and correspondingly, theology and its onto-theological character? We are putting this question in a discussion involving the whole of the history of philosophy. At the same time, however, we ask with a special side glance toward Hegel, an occasion for us to first turn to something peculiar.
Hegel is thinking Being in its most complete emptiness, thus in terms the most universal. At the same time he thinks Being in its most perfect fullness. Nevertheless, he does not call speculative philosophy, i.e., philosophy proper, onto-theology, but “Science of Logic.” With this terminology Hegel brings something decisive to the fore. One could, of course, immediately explain why metaphysics is called “logic” by pointing out that, for Hegel, the object of thought is “Thought,” taking the word singulare tantum, in the singular plain and simple. Thought, thinking, is, as everyone knows and according to ancient practice considered the theme of logic. That much is certain. But it is just as incontrovertibly established that Hegel, true to tradition, discovers the object of thought in Existence as such and in the Whole, that is, in the movement of Being from emptiness to developed fullness.
Now, how is it possible that “Being” will undertake at all to represent itself as “thought”? How otherwise can it do it than by virtue of the fact that Being, as ground, is already impressed, while thinking—because it belongs together with Being—collects on Being as the ground, to fathom and understand it. Being manifests itself as thought which means that the Being of Existence reveals itself as self-fathoming and self-justifying ground. Ground and
ratio (reason) are in their original essence the
lógos in the sense of the collective problematic,
47 the
‘En Pánta.’ Thus, “science,” i.e., metaphysics, is for Hegel “logic” not really because science has thought for its object, but because the object of thought remains
Being. Being, however, privately engages thought for the purpose of understanding, and it has done so since the early stages of unmasking itself in the imprint of the
Lógos, which is the authenticating reason.
48
Metaphysics thinks Existence as such, in general. Metaphysics thinks Existence as such, that is, in the Whole. Metaphysics thinks the Being of Existence in the fathoming unity of the greatest generality, that is, the universal equivalence, as well as in the understanding unity of totality, which is highest above all else. Thus, we presuppose the Being of Existence as authenticating reason. Hence, all metaphysics is, basically, the fathoming from the very bottom, reasoning which renders account of the ground, replies, and finally calls it to account.
Why should we mention this at all? Because we want to experience the stereotyped terms ontology, theology, and onto-theology in their core. At the start, however, and ordinarily, the terms ontology and theology strike us just like other well-known terms, such as psychology, biology, cosmology, archeology. The final syllable,—[o]logy, quite generally and readily suggests that we are dealing with the sciences of the soul, of living reality, of the cosmos, and of antiquities. Yet, in -ology there lies concealed not only the logical in the sense of the consistent and declaratory in general, which articulates, promotes, safeguards and communicates all scientific knowledge. The -logia is in every case the totality of a reticulated system of understandings wherein the objects of science are thought with a view to their rational basis, will say, are understood. Ontology and theology, by contrast, are “logia” in so far as they fathom Existence as such and seek its ground in the Whole. They render account of Being as the ground of the Existent. They are answerable to the Lógos and are, in quite an essential sense, conforming to the Lógos, that is, the logic of the Lógos. Accordingly, they should be called more properly onto-logic and theo-logic. More appropriately and more descriptively metaphysics should be thought of as onto-theo-logic.
Now we understand the term “logic” in essentially the sense which includes
also the designation used by Hegel and first really explains it. Logic is, to be
sure, the name for that particular thinking which everywhere tries to fathom and
comprehend Existence as such within the totality of Being as ground (Lógos). The basic character of metaphysics is onto-theo-logic. Thus we
are enabled to explain how God gets into philosophy.
To what extent are we successful with our explanation? Well, in so far as we
take notice that the object of thought is Existence as such, that is, Being, which
reveals itself in the essential nature of the ground. In accordance, the object of
thought, Being as ground, is thought through thoroughly only when we have before our
mental eye the idea of the ground as a primary ground, prōtē
‘arché. The original object of thought presents itself as the
proto-object, the causa prima (first Cause) which corresponds
in reasoning to the regress to the ultima ratio (Ultimate
Reason), the final account. The Being of Existence in the sense of the ground is
represented fully only as causa sui. But in these words we
have touched upon the metaphysical concept of God. Metaphysics is obliged to think
in the direction of God because the cause of thought is Being, while Being is ground
in a variety of ways: as Lógos, as Hypokeímenon, as Substance, as Subject.
This explanation presumably touches upon something that is correct. Still, it remains absolutely insufficient for an investigation of the essence of metaphysics. For, metaphysics is not only theo-logic, but also onto-logic. Metaphysics, above all, is not only one and/or the other. Rather, metaphysics is theo-logic because it is onto-logic. It is this because it is that. The essential onto-theological constitution of metaphysics cannot be explained either on the basis of theologic nor on that of ontologic, provided an explanation will ever suffice for what we still have to reflect on.
Let it be noted that we have not yet given thought to the problem as to the type of unity in which ontologic and theologic belong together, nor have we considered the origin of this unity, nor the difference of the differentia which unite ontologic and theologic. For, apparently, we are concerned not with bringing together two independently existing disciplines of metaphysics, but with the unity of what in ontologic and theologic is the object of enquiry and thought. That is Existence as such in the universal and primary at one with the Existent as such in the Highest and Ultimate. The unity of the One is such that the Ultimate understands the First in its own way and the First the Ultimate in its own way. The difference in both ways of understanding is part of the difference we have mentioned but not yet thought about.
It is in the unity of Existence as such in the most Universal and in the Highest that we find rests the essential constitution of metaphysics.
First of all we are obliged to discuss the problem of the onto-theological nature of metaphysics problematically pure and simple. Only the object of thought itself can usher us into the realm which is discussed in the problem as to the onto-theological constitution of metaphysics. We can accomplish this by thinking more objectively about the object of thought. The object of thought is traditionally known in occidental thinking by the name this object
49 just a trifle more objectively, should we pay more careful attention to the debatable in the object, then we should see that always and everywhere
Being means the Being of
Existence, in which phrase the possessive case is to be thought as a genitivus subjectivus. Of course, we speak with reservations about a possessive case as applied to object and subject, for these labels, subject and object, have on their part arisen from an imprint of Being. The only thing that is clear is that in the case of the Being of Existence and the Existence and the Existence of Being we are concerned every time with a difference.
We think of Being, therefore, as object only when we think it as different from Existence and think Existence as different from Being. Thus, difference proper emerges. If we attempt to form an image of it, we shall discover that we are immediately tempted to comprehend difference as a relation which our thinking has added to Being and to Existence. As a result, difference is reduced to a distinction, to a product of human intelligence.
However, let us assume for once that difference is an addition of our forming a mental image, then the problem arises: An addition to what? And the answer we get is: to Existence. Well and good. But what do we mean by this “Existence”? What else do we mean by it than such as is? Thus we accommodate the alleged addition, the idea of a difference, under Being. Yet, “Being” itself proclaims: Being which is Existence. Wherever we would introduce difference as an alleged addition, we always meet Existence and Being in their difference. It is as in Grimm’s fairy tale of the rabbit and the hedgehog: “I’s all here.” Now, we could treat this odd state of affairs that Existence and Being, each in its own way, are to be discovered through and in difference, in a pompous fashion and explain it as follows. “It cannot be helped that our representational thinking is so organized and constituted that prior to any operation it establishes difference everywhere between Existence and Being, above one’s head, as it were, and again in one’s head where it seems to originate.” Much could be said anent this apparently natural yet all too ready explanation. Still more problems could be posed, above all this. Where do we get this “between” from in which difference is, as it were, to be intercalated?
Let us be done now with opinions and explanations. Instead let us make the
following observation. What we call difference we find everywhere and at all times
in the object of thought, in Existence as such, and we come up against it in a
manner so free of doubt that we do not pay any particular attention to it. Nothing
moreover, seems to compel us to take particular notice. We are at liberty in our
thinking not to give any thought to difference or to reflect on it specifically.
Yet, this liberty does not hold for all cases. By chance it may occur that thought
will find itself called upon to answer the question: What is the meaning of this
oft-mentioned Being? If under these conditions Being exhibits itself as a being of
…, in the genitive of difference, then the question just asked would be more to the
point if rephrased: What in your opinion is difference if both Being as well as
Existence each in their own way appear through difference? In
order to do justice to this question we must first of all maneuver ourselves into an
objective opposition to difference. This opposition appears when we “backtrack.” For
it is only through the dis-tance brought about by “backtracking” that the close-by
as such presents itself, that proximity appears for the first time. In
“backtracking” we release the object of thought, Being as difference, into its
opposite. The opposite may remain absolutely objectless.
Still with an eye to difference, yet releasing it in “backtracking” into that which is
to-be-thought
50 we can assert the following. Being of Existence means the type of Being which Existence is. The “is” in this case is to be taken transitively, as implying passage. Being asserts its nature
51 here in the manner of a transition to Existence. However, Being does not go over toward or into Existence by leaving its place or position, as if Existence, previously devoid of Being, could be contacted by Being for the first time. Being transcends and covers, while revealing itself, what is encountered in open presence by such enthrallment. Encounter means seeking refuge in open presence, thus, being in sheltered presence, being an Existent.
52
Being exhibits itself as revealing enthrallment. Existence as such manifests itself as an encounter fleeing into unmasked presence.
Being in the sense of revealing enthrallment and Existence as such in the sense of refuge-seeking encounter have their being as elements that have been differentiated from the Same, that which underlies difference.
53 What underlies distinction is what originally is responsible for yielding and keeping apart the between, wherein enthrallment and encounter are conjoined and mutually supported in their fluctuating relationships. The difference of Being and Existence as the ground of distinction between enthrallment and encounter lies in the
unmasking-enshrouding issue of both. Light is shed throughout the issue on the self-enshrouding occlusion. It is this pervading luminosity which is responsible for the reciprocity of enthrallment and encounter.
In our attempt to reflect on difference as such we do not cause its disappearance but we are following it through to its essential origin. En route there we had to give thought to the issue between enthrallment and encounter. What is at stake is really the object of thought more objectively considered in the “backtracking.” In other words, it is Being thought of as emerging from difference.
To be sure, at this point we have to intersperse a remark which has to do with our speaking of the object of thought and will engage our attention again and again. Supposing we mention “Being,” then we are using the word in the widest possible and most indeterminate generality. Even when speaking only of a generality, have we thought of Being in an inappropriate manner. We visualize Being in a way in which It (Being) never presents itself. The manner in which the object of thought, that is, Being, behaves remains unique. The habitual mode of thought can forever enlighten us about this unique situation only insufficiently in the beginning. Let us illustrate this by an example. From the outset we should be aware of the fact, however, that nowhere in Existence is there an example of the essence of Being, presumably because the essence of Being is the play itself.
In order to characterize the universality of the general, Hegel at one time gave the following illustration: Someone wanted to buy fruit in a store. He asked for fruit. They gave him apples, pears, they handed him peaches, cherries, grapes. But the customer rejected what was offered him. He wanted fruit, and wanted it at any cost. Now, what was offered him was, indeed, every time fruit. Nevertheless, we come to the conclusion that fruit cannot be bought.
Impossible to the nth degree would be imagining “Being” as the universal belonging to every case of Existence. Being we meet only occasionally in this or that fate-enmeshed formulation: Phýsis, Lógos, ‘En, Idéa, Enérgeia, substantiality, objectivity, subjectivity, Will, Will to Power, Will to Will. But such examples from the fateful history of man we shall not find neatly arranged like apples, pears, and peaches, displayed on the counter of historical ideas.
Nevertheless, didn’t we learn of Being in the historic order and sequence of the dialectical process which Hegel thought? Certainly. But in this case too Being reveals itself only in the light in which it made itself manifest for Hegel. By this we mean that the manner in which Being presents itself must assuredly be determined by the manner in which it manifests itself. The peculiar manner, however, is the impress of destiny, the stamp of the prevailing epoch which as such assumes being for us only to the extent to which we permit it to rejoin what it properly has been. It is only in the sudden impact of a moment of remembrance that we gain access to destiny. This is likewise true in the experience of a special modal difference between Being and Existence to which an individual interpretation of Existence as such corresponds. What has been stated is true above all also for our attempt to think of difference as the issue between revealing enthrallment and enshrouding encounter as we are “backtracking” from forgetfulness of difference as such. To be sure, as we are listening more attentively we receive documentation of the fact that in the verbal formulation of this we have already permitted the past to speak its piece in as much as we are thinking of revealing and enshrouding, of passage (transcendence) and of encounter (presence). By pursuing this discussion of the difference of Being and Existence into the issue as a preliminary to its essence, it is perhaps possible that something diffusive comes to the fore which pervades the destiny of Being from its beginning to its consummation. Nevertheless, it is still difficult to describe how we are to think of this pervasiveness when it is neither a universal valid for all cases, nor a law which assures the necessity of a process in the dialectic sense.
What we are now primarily concerned with in our undertaking is gaining an insight into the possibility of thinking of difference as an issue which is to clarify in how far the onto-theological constitution of metaphysics derives its original essence from the issue which we meet at the beginning of the history of metaphysics, runs through its periods and yet remains everywhere hidden, and hence forgotten, as the issue in an oblivion which escapes even us.
In order to facilitate the insight mentioned above, let us reflect on Being, and within it on difference, and within difference on the issue from the point of view of that cast of Being through which Being became exposed as Lógos, or, Reason. Being manifests itself in revealing enthrallment by letting the encountering reality remain problematic, by authentication in the manifold methods of assembling and discovering. Existence, as such—the encounter seeking refuge in overtness—is what is authenticated. That which is authenticated and consequently effected, then authenticates in its own way, to be sure, by effecting, will say, causing. The issue between fathoming and authentication as such not only keeps both apart, it keeps them also in a state of togetherness. The points at issue are so interlaced in the issue that not only Being as ground authenticates Existence, but Existence, in turn, and by its own methods, authenticates Being, that is, causes it. Such, Existence can accomplish only in so far as it “is” the fullness of Being or, in other words, as Existence par excellence.
At this point our reflection carries us into an exciting nexus. Being has its essence in Lógos, in the sense of Reason, of the problematic. Thought of collectively, the same Lógos is the unifying agent, the ‘En. However, this ‘En is twofold. For once, it is the Unifying One in the sense of the ubiquitous First and, hence, the Most Universal; at the same time it is the One Unifying One in the sense of the Highest (Zeus). Lógos, by virtue of finding reasons, gathers everything into the universal and by understanding gathers everything from the Unique. That, moreover, the same Lógos harbors within itself the essential origin of linguistic formulation and thus determines the mode of speaking as logical in the widest sense, may only be mentioned by the way.
In so far as Being has its essence in the Being of Existence, in difference, in an issue, do authentication and understanding in their joining issues and dropping them continue, does Being authenticate Existence, does Existence fathom Being as Existence par excellence. The One enthralls the Other, the One is encountered in the Other. Enthrallment and encounter appear alternatingly one in the other in reflection. Speaking from the point of view of difference this means that the issue is a circling, a revolving, one around the other, of Being and Existence. The act of authentication itself appears within the clearing of the issue as something which is, hence on its own initiative demands, as Existence, the corresponding understanding by something existing. This something is causation, a causation, to be sure, by the highest Cause.
One of the classical proofs for this fact in the history of metaphysics may be found in a text of Leibniz’s which has hardly been noticed, a text which we tersely describe as “The 24 Theses of Metaphysics.”
54
Metaphysics corresponds to Being as Lógos and is, accordingly, in its main feature at all events logic. But it is a logic which thinks the Being of Existence; therefore, it is the logic which is determined by the different: It is onto-theo-logic.
In so far as metaphysics thinks Existence as such in terms of the Whole, it visualizes Existence from the point of view of the different in the difference without paying attention to difference as difference.
The different exhibits itself as the Being of Existence in the Universal and as the Being of Existence in the Highest.
Because Being appears as the ground,
55 Existence is that which is authenticated. However, Existence
par excellence is that which understands
56 in the sense of being the First Cause. If metaphysics thinks Existence with an eye toward its basis which is common to every individual Existent as such, then metaphysics is logic in the form of onto-logic. If metaphysics thinks Existence as such in terms of the Whole, that is, with an eye toward the highest all-understanding Existence, then metaphysics becomes logic in the form of theo-logic.
Because metaphysical thinking remains imbedded in difference which as such is not the object of thought, metaphysics is at one and the same time uniquely ontology and theology by virtue of the unifying oneness of the issue.
The onto-theological constitution of metaphysics hails from the pervasive influence of difference which joins and separates as ground and Existence, both authenticating and understanding, and is sustained by the issue in carrying the action through.
These novel terms which we have been using are meant to guide our thinking into realms which to designate the common terms of metaphysics, Being and Existence, ground-grounded, no longer suffice. For whatever these terms designate, whatever is represented by the mode of thinking stimulated by them, stems from difference as that which is different; their origin may no longer be included in the purview to metaphysics.
Insight into the onto-theological constitution of metaphysics shows a possible way of answering the question as to how God entered philosophy by going to the essence of metaphysics.
God entered philosophy through the issue which we think first of all as being the advance point in the essence of the difference between Being and Existence. Difference represents the ground plan in the essential structure of metaphysics. The issue yields and cedes Being as the pro-duc-tive ground, which ground in itself requires an appropriate understanding on the part of what it helped found. The appropriate understanding is equivalent to causation by the ultimate and original reality. This is the Cause as causa sui, and this is the just and proper name for God in philosophy. Man may neither pray to this God, nor may be sacrifice to him. Confronted by causa sui man may neither sink onto his knees nor could he sing and dance.
Accordingly, this thinking-less-God which must abandon the God of philosophy, God as causa sui, is, perhaps, closer to God the divinity. In our context this means merely that thinking-less-God is less restricted in dealing with him than onto-theo-logic would acknowledge.
With this remark we may have shed a little light on the path on which we find the type of thinking which is “backtracking” from metaphysics into the essence of metaphysics, from oblivion of difference as such into a fateful concealment of the issue which we no longer understand.
Nobody can possibly know whether, when, where and how this step thought is taking will open up into a true (event-bound) path, and lead to a passage and road construction. It could be that the sway of metaphysics will consolidate sooner than expected. We are thinking of the rise of modern technology and its developments, swift and limitless to the eye. It could also be that everything that is taking place while “backtracking” will only be utilized and incorporated in a continuing metaphysics in ways appropriate to itself and as the result of imaginative thinking.
In such a case the “back track” itself would not be accomplished and the path which has been opened up and pointed out would not be used.
Easily such reflections impinge upon our minds, but they have no weight in relation to a difficulty of quite a different nature which we have to negotiate in “backtracking.”
The difficulty is one of language. Our western languages are languages variously suited to metaphysical thinking. Whether the nature of western languages bears only the stamp of metaphysics and, hence, ultimately, that of onto-theo-logic, or whether these languages offer other possibilities of expressing and at the same time saying without expressing, must remain an open question. During the exercises in our seminar often enough difficulties arose to which verbal expression of thought was exposed. The little word “is” which is met everywhere in our language and tells of Being even where it does not come to the fore, harbors the entire fate of Being, from the éstin gar einai of Parmenides to the “is” of the speculative principle of Hegel and still further to the dissolution of the “is” in the positing of a will to power by Nietzsche.
A look into the difficulties originating in language should save us from prematurely recasting the language in which our present attempts in thinking have been couched. It should caution us to speak of an issue in the offing on the morrow instead of devoting all our efforts to thinking what we have formulated in language all the way through. For what we did say was said in a seminar. A seminar is, as the word indicates, a place and an occasion for disseminating here and there a grain, a seed of reflection which sometime or other will germinate as it may and bear fruit.