1
I begin with three fundamental features of the idea of secularism. I will want to make something of them at different stages of the passage of my argument in this chapter for the conclusion—among others—that the relevance of secularism is contextual in very specific ways.
If secularism has its relevance only in context, then it is natural and right to think that it will appear in different forms and guises in different contexts. But I write down these opening features of secularism at the outset because they seem to me to be invariant between the different forms that secularism may take in different contexts. It is hard to imagine that one hasn’t changed the subject from secularism to something else, something that deserves another name, if one finds oneself denying any of the features that I initially list here.
First, secularism is
a stance to be taken about religion. At the level of generality with which I have just described this, it does not say anything very specific or precise. The imprecision and generality have two sources. One obvious source is that
religion, regarding which it is supposed to take a stance, is itself, notoriously, not a very precise or specifically understood term. But to the extent that we have a notion of religion in currency with some meaning—however imprecisely elaborated—secularism will have a parasitic meaning partially elaborated as a stance regarding it. Should we decide that there is no viability in any notion of religion, and should the notion pass out of conceptual currency, secularism too would lapse as a notion with a point and rationale. The other source of imprecision is that I have said nothing specific or precise about
what sort of stance secularism takes toward religion. One may think that it has to be in some sense an adversarial stance since surely secularism, in some sense, defines itself against religion. This is true enough, but, still, the very fact that I find the need to keep using the qualifier “in some sense” makes clear that nothing much has been said about the kind of opposing stance this amounts to. Part of the point of this essay is to add a little precision to just this question.
Second, for all this generality just noted, secularism—unlike secular and secularization—is quite specific in another regard. It is the name of a political doctrine. So to the extent that it takes a stance vis-à-vis religion, it does so only in the realm of the polity. It is not meant—as the terms secular and secularization are—to mark a highly general and dispersed social and intellectual and cultural phenomenon and process. Unlike the term secularization, it is not so capacious as to include a stance against religion that requires redirection of either personal belief or, for that matter, any range of personal and cultural habits of dress or diet or … Thus it is not a stance against religion of the sort that atheists and agnostics might wish to take or a stance that strikes attitudes (to say nothing of policies) about the hijab. The increase in a society of loss of personal belief in God or the decrease in church- or synagogue- or mosque-going or the surrender of traditional religious habits of dress or prohibitions against pork may all be signs of increasing secularization, but they are irrelevant to the idea of secularism. And unlike the term secular, which is often said to refer innocuously and indiscriminately to all things that are “worldly” in the sense of being outside the reach of religious institutions and concerns (outside the cloister, in the mundiality of the world at large, as it were), secularism aspires to be more concentrated in its concern—to not merely refer to anything that is outside of that reach, but to focus on something specific (the polity) and attempt to keep it or steer it outside of some specified aspects of that reach.
Third, secularism, as a stance regarding religion that is restricted to the polity, is not a good in itself. It seeks what is conceived, by those who favor it, to promote certain other moral and political goods, and these are goods that are intended to counter what are conceived as harms, either actual or potential. This third feature may be considered too controversial to be regarded as a defining feature, but its point becomes more plausible when we contrast secularism with a more cognitive (rather than political) stance regarding religion, such as atheism. For atheists, the truth of atheism is sufficient to motivate one to adhere to it and the truth of atheism is not grounded in the claim that it promotes a moral or political good or the claim that it is supported by other moral or political values we have. By contrast, secularists, to the extent that they claim “truth” for secularism, claim it on grounds that appeal to other values that support the ideal of secularism or other goods that are promoted by it. Secularism as a political doctrine arose to repair what were perceived as damages that flowed from historical harms that were, in turn, perceived as owing, in some broad sense, to religion. Thus, when it is said that secularism had as its vast cradle the prolonged and internecine religious conflicts in Europe of some centuries ago, for instance, something like this normative force of serving goods and correcting harms is detectably implied. But if all this is right, then it follows that one would have to equally grant that, should there be contexts in which those goods were not seen necessarily to be goods, or to the extent that those goods were being well served by political arrangements that were not secularist, or to the extent that there were no existing harms, actual or potential, that secularism would be correcting, then one could take the opposing normative stance and fail to see the point and rationale for secularism.
2
I want to now turn from features that define or characterize secularism to features of its justification and basis of adoption.
In an essay written in the days immediately following the fatwa pronounced against Salman Rushdie, called “What Is a Muslim?,”
1 I argued that secularism had no justification that did not appeal to substantive values, that is to say, values some may hold and others may not. It was not justifiable on purely rational grounds that anyone (capable of rationality) would find convincing, no matter what substantive values they held. I had invoked the notion, coined by Bernard Williams as “internal reasons,” to describe these kinds of grounds on which its justification is given.
2 Internal reasons are reasons that rely on specific motives, values, and commitments in the moral psychologies of individuals (or groups, if one takes the view that groups have moral-psychological economies). Internal reasons are contrasted with “external reasons,” which are reasons that someone is supposed to have quite independent of her substantive values and commitments, that is, independent of elements in the psychologies that motivate people. Bernard Williams, recapitulating Humean arguments against Kantian forms of externalist rationality and the universalism that might be expected to emerge from it, had claimed that there are no such things as “external reasons.” Whether that general claim is true or not, my more specific claim had been that there are no external reasons that would establish the truth of secularism. If secularism were to carry conviction, it would have to be on grounds that persuaded people by appealing to the specific and substantive values that figured in their specific moral psychological economies.
3 Such a view might cause alarm in those who would wish for secularism on a more universal basis. Internal reasons, by their nature, do not provide such a basis. As, I said, internal reasons for some conclusion that will persuade some people, may not persuade others of that conclusion, since those others may not hold the particular substantive values to which those reasons appeal and on which those reasons depend. Only external reasons could persuade everyone since all they require is a minimal rationality possessed by all (undamaged, adult) human minds and make no appeal to substantive values that may be variably held by human minds and psychologies. Alarming though it might seem to some, there is no help for this. There are no more secure universal grounds on which one can base one’s argument for secularism.
Charles Taylor has convincingly argued that in a religiously plural society secularism should be adopted on the basis of what Rawls called an “overlapping consensus.”
4 An overlapping consensus, in Rawls’s understanding of that term, is a consensus on some policy that is arrived at by people with very different moral and religious and political commitments who sign on to the policy from within their differing points of view and therefore on possibly very different grounds from each other. It contrasts with the idea that when one converges on a policy one must all do so for the
same reason.
What is the relation between the idea that secularism should be adopted on the basis of an overlapping consensus and the idea presented in the earlier paragraph about internal reasons being the only reasons available in justifying secularism? A very close one. The latter idea yields (it lies behind) the former. The relation is this: internal reasons, unlike external reasons, may vary from person to person, group to group. This may give the impression that there simply cannot be a consensus if we were restricted to the resources of internal reasons. But that does not follow. Or, at any rate, it only follows if we assume that a consensus requires that all sign onto something (some policy or political position such as secularism) on the same grounds or for the same reason. In other words, on the basis of an external reason or reasons. But such an assumption is a theoretical tyranny. Without that assumption one could say this. If there is to be a consensus on some political outcome on the basis, not of external but of internal reasons, it will presumably only be because different persons or groups subscribe to the policy on their own, different, grounds. This just is the idea of an overlapping consensus. If there were external reasons for a policy, one could get a consensus on it of a stronger kind and would not need to hold out hope for a merely “overlapping” consensus.
Perhaps all this is obvious. However, for reasons having to do with Rawls scholarship, I have been a little wary of this use of the notion of overlapping consensus since in Rawls it has always been a notion embedded in the framework of his celebrated idea of the “original position,” i.e., the idea that one contract into policies to live by without knowledge of one’s substantive position in society. I find myself completely baffled by why the idea of the original position is not made entirely redundant by the notion of an overlapping consensus. If one did not know what one’s substantive position in society is, one presumably does not know what one’s substantive values are. If so, the very idea of internal reasons can have no play in the original position. It follows that if one were to adopt an overlapping consensus on the basis of divergent internal reasons that contractors may have for signing onto a policy, then the original position becomes altogether irrelevant to the contractual scenario. Of course, if one were to completely divorce the idea of an overlapping consensus from Rawls’s conceptual apparatus within which it has always been formulated (even in his last published work,
The Law of Peoples),
5 then it would be exactly right to say, as Taylor does, that secularism should be adopted in pluralistic society on the basis of an overlapping consensus. But now the only apparatus one has to burden the contractors with is the capacity for internal reasoning, that is, with psychological economies of substantive values that yield internal reasons. Rawls would not be recognizable in this form of contractualist doctrine. Indeed, one would be hard-pressed to say that one was any longer theorizing within the contractualist tradition at all, which is a tradition in which serious constraints of an “original position” or a “state of nature” were always placed as methodological starting points in the making of a contract. Shorn of all this, one is left with something that is the merest common sense, which would be bombastic to call a social contract. We now need only say this: assuming no more than our capacity for internal reasoning, i.e., our capacity to invoke some substantive values we hold (whatever they may differentially be in all the different individuals or groups in society), we can proceed to justify on its basis another substantive value or policy—for example, secularism—and so proceed to adopt it for the polity. If this path of adoption by consensus, invoking this internalist notion of justification, works in a religiously pluralist society, it will be just as Taylor presents it, an overlapping consensus, with none of Rawls’s theoretical framework.
3
The last two sections have respectively presented points of definition of secularism and points of its justification and basis of adoption. I think it is important to keep these two things separate on the general ground that one needs to have a more or less clear idea of what we are justifying and adopting before we justify and adopt it.
In a very interesting recent essay, Charles Taylor has argued that we need to
redefine “secularism.”
6 It is a complex essay with highly honorable political and moral motivations underlying it. But, speaking more theoretically, I don’t think it is quite as well motivated. It begins by saying that there have been two aspects to secularism—one, the idea of the
separation of church and state and the other that the
state maintain a neutral equidistance from different religions within a plural society. The essay wishes to correct an overemphasis on the first by stressing the importance of the second aspect and wishes to modify the second, too, along the following lines.
In modern societies, we seek various goods, and the three in particular (echoing the trio of goods expressed in a familiar slogan) that remain relevant to secular aspirations are the liberty of worship, the equality of different faiths, and, finally, more than just equality, we need to give each faith a voice in determining the shape of the society, so there must be fraternal relations within which negotiations, with each voice being equally heard, are crucial. What is more, because the first aspect’s stress on separation of church and state was too focused on religion, the second aspect’s stress on religious diversity should be modified and expanded to include the fact that in late modernity the diversity of pluralist societies contains not just a variety of religious people but nonreligious people as well. Their point of view must also be included in the mix. All this is now included in the idea and ideal of a redefined secularism.
So, to sum up his explicit motivations for seeking this more capacious definition of secularism: There is the importance of the state maintaining a neutrality and equal distance from each religion. There is the importance of a society allowing the democratic participation of all religious voices in shaping its polity’s commitments. And there is the need to turn one’s focus away from just religion to acknowledging and respecting wider forms of cultural diversity and a variety of intellectual positions, including nonreligious ones. These are all worthy motivations, and a society that pursues them would be measurably better than one that doesn’t. The question is how does thinking so make a difference to the way we theorize about the meaning or definition of secularism? There is no denying that it makes a difference to secularism, but it is not obvious to me that it is just as he presents it.
One of the things he finds distorted about secularism while defined along the unrevised lines that he is inveighing against is that, so defined, it has been too focused on “institutional arrangements.” Slogans such as “separation of church and state” become mantras, and, as they do, they suggest institutional arrangements that are fixed. Once done, it is hard not only to change the institutions but also to reconceptualize secularism. What is better in order to maintain both theoretical and institutional flexibility is to allow the ideals in questions (the echoes of liberty, equality, and fraternity) to determine what is needed rather than these slogans, which point to institutional arrangements and stop or preempt conversations about how to theorize secularism. In keeping with this point, he applauds Rawls for starting with certain ideals such as “human rights, equality, the rule of law, democracy” rather than anti-religious (or for that matter, religious principles) and then proceeding to consider the question of secularism to be in line with them.
7
This is just right, I believe, as are the general moral and political instincts that prompt Taylor’s appeal for a redefinition of secularism: the desire for greater flexibility, the desire not to tie secularism to the polemical sense of non- or antireligious, the desire to establish secularism on the basis of an overlapping consensus of internal reasons. The question is, is it wise or necessary to redefine secularism to pursue these instincts and motivations?
4
Let me then turn to a way of characterizing (I say characterizing because perhaps defining is too constricting a term for what both Taylor and I are interested in, but I will not always avoid talk of definition since it is the word Taylor himself uses) secularism that is, or to put it more cautiously, that may be, at odds with Taylor’s. (I add this caution because, despite what it seems to me at present, it may turn out that we are not much at odds and it is really a matter of emphasizing different things.)
I have said that it is a good idea, as Taylor suggests, to
start with certain ideals that do not mention religion or opposition to religion and
then move on to talk of political and institutional arrangements involving the role of the state and its stances toward religion. So, just because it is what is most familiar to us in our tradition of political theory and philosophy, let us start within a liberal framework, let us start with some basic ideals and the fundamental rights and constitutional commitments that enshrine them, just as Rawls and Taylor propose. Starting with them as the basic, though tentative, givens, I suggest we embrace Taylor’s account only up to a point and then add something that does not seem to be emphasized by him, indeed something that he may even wish to be deemphasizing in his redefinition.
I propose, then, something like the following nonarbitrary stipulation as a characterization of secularism that contains all of the three features I had mentioned at the outset.
(S): Should we be living in a religiously plural society, secularism requires that all religions should have the privilege of free exercise and be evenhandedly treated except when a religion’s practices are inconsistent with the ideals that a polity seeks to achieve (ideals, often, though not always, enshrined in stated fundamental rights and other constitutional commitments) in which case there is a lexical ordering in which the political ideals are placed first.
Much commentary is needed on this minimal and basic characterization.
Here are some miscellaneous points of commentary, in no particular order, that help to situate and motivate (S), thereby showing why, as a stipulation, it is nonarbitrary and where it may seem to depart in emphasis and implication and significance from Taylor’s redefinition.
To begin with, (S) makes explicit mention of the sort of thing that Taylor thinks it is important to stress, the evenhanded, neutral distance between different religions in a religiously plural society. However, the “qualifier” that (S) opens with, “Should we be living in a religiously plural society … ,” is there to point out that secularism is a doctrine that may be relevant even in societies where there is no religiously plurality. If there is a monoreligious society, it is not as if secularism becomes irrelevant. In such a society there may still be point in a lexical ordering of the sort that characterizes secularism in (S). If there are ideals that form the starting point of one’s construction of the content of secularism, and one wishes to protect those ideals, then, should the single religion of such a society run afoul of them, the lexical ordering will have a point. Thus secularism has a broader relevance and meaning than one that—as in Taylor’s redefinition—only ties it to the idea of being neutral and evenhanded with a plurality of religions as well as various nonreligious points of view. Speaking more generally, though, Taylor applauds Rawls for adopting this starting point where the examples of ideals are basically those of a liberal polity in a society with plural social interests and concerns; there may be other societies in which there is less plurality and so the starting point may formulate other ideals.
The more important point of difference between (S) and the sort of redefinition Taylor is seeking is that, when characterizing secularism, (S) squares with his urge to be nonphobic and accommodating toward religion as well as with his idea to have the state keep a neutral and equal distance between all religions—but then emphasizes something else as well: the lexical ordering. The point of this latter essential element of the characterization is that (S) is a stance that can be adversarial against religious practices and laws, but only when, from the point of view of the ideals one starts with, it needs to be that, i.e., when those practices and laws go against the very thing Taylor himself thinks we should start with—the ideals and goals (formulated without reference to religious or antireligious elements) that a society has adopted.
The fact that one’s starting point lies in certain ideals helps (S) to avoid the charge that Taylor makes against some contemporary formulations of secularism, viz., that they start with an assertion of certain institutional arrangements with slogans or mantras such “the separation of church and state.” Rather, in the Rawlsian manner of which Taylor approves, (S) starts with certain ideals and goals that the society wishes to adopt, and the lexical ordering suggests that the institutions should be shaped and distributed in such a way that certain priorities articulated in the lexical ordering get implemented. There is certainly more of a stress than in Taylor on the priority over religion of certain goals and ideals formulated in terms independent of religion. Religion and its practices come second to these, if there is ever a clash between them. But, just as Taylor would have it, it is these goals rather than any institutional arrangements that form the starting point.
I had said that the first basic defining feature of secularism is that it is some sort of a stance regarding religion. What sort of stance is (S)? The point in the previous paragraph brings out how, as a stance, it is more adversarial than Taylor wishes secularism to be, but it is by no means obsessively seeking religion out as a target. It is certainly not trying to polemically remove it root and branch from public life, in all its social, cultural and intellectual aspects, in a way often suggested in recent writings by today’s doctrinaire atheists. This is because (S) keeps strict faith with the second elementary feature of secularism mentioned at the outset, viz., that it is only and precisely a political stance, a stance regarding religion as it affects the polity. It is not dismayed by or concerned with the presence of religiosity in the society at large or in the personal beliefs of the individual citizens as so much of the ideological urge for secularity in the modern period does. The lexical ordering merely says that if and when there is an inconsistency that arises between certain goals sought to be achieved in a polity that are formulated independently of religion, and the practices of a religion, the former must be placed first and the latter second.
Quite apart from the fact that it is restricted to political matters, the antecedent in the conditional “if and when there is an inconsistency” makes it clear that even within this restricted domain, there is no harm to be found in the presence of religion, so long as it does not clash with certain fundamental ideals and commitments of the polity.
What sorts of things are clear examples of the political domain and of the priority being proposed within it, by the lexical ordering? The examples are hardly exotic.
Take a society in which the commitment to free speech is a fundamental ideal of its polity. Assume that it is our starting point, in just the way Taylor urges. Let’s, then, also assume that there are religions and religious practices in that society, those of Christianity and Islam, say, but not Buddhism, which have strict commitments to censorship of blasphemy. (S) says that it is important to see secularism as requiring the state to be evenhanded toward religions in general, but not in any case when the lexical ordering comes to have application. And this is such a case. In this case the lexical ordering requires one to spoil the neutrality by favoring Buddhism over Christianity and Islam since the state must place the commitments to blasphemy in these religions second and the commitment to free speech first, in the context, say, of the publication of novels such as
The Last Temptation of Christ or
The Satanic Verses in a society such as Britain’s with a polity defined upon basic liberal commitments. (It is interesting to note that Britain took a non-neutral stance in a quite different sense than the one I am recommending, weighing down on Islam but, as a result of Mary Whitehouse’s campaigns, not on Christianity. It is a question whether this hints at the extent to which established religion is more than merely nominal in Britain.) I will discuss free speech and another example involving gender equality again later, but, for now, I offer this as a rather straightforward example of the occasion on which (S) seems to depart from Taylor’s understanding of secularism, by emphasizing the “lexical ordering” ideal over the “neutral and equidistant” ideal of secularism that he favors.
I think in late modern societies committed to liberal ideals of this sort it is a theoretical loss rather than gain to allow that a polity has been impeccably secular in any case in which it capitulates to the banning of a novel on the grounds that it is blasphemous by the lights of a religion’s customs or laws. One may—even in late modern liberal societies—find good moral and political reasons to ban the novel. That is not the theoretical issue I am focusing on. What is theoretically questionable is only that we should describe the ban as falling well within the secular ideal. It may well be that good politics or morals sometimes requires us to put the secularist policy aside. But it is secularist policy that we would be putting aside. If a redefinition of secularism were to deny this, that would be a questionable theoretical outcome of the redefinition. The stress on the neutral equidistance ideal over the lexical ordering ideal in a characterization of secularism may well lead to just such a questionable theoretical outcome in cases such as this. A society whose polity banned both the Kazantsakis and the Rushdie novel, on grounds of their being blasphemous by the lights of two different religions that were being treated neutrally in this twin banning, meets the neutral and equidistant state ideal of secularism but fails to meet (S).
It cannot really be argued on Taylor’s behalf that such a twin and symmetrical banning does
not satisfy the state-neutralist ideal of secularism by pointing out that he has allowed into the groups that the state must be neutral toward, nonreligious people as well. What these religions find blasphemous are not just the expression of a point of view, described innocuously as “nonreligious,” it is the expression of views that trash and cartoon and satirize their most cherished and deep commitments with contempt as Rushdie or Kazantzakis (or Buñuel of Arrabal …) did. So a state that decided to keep all these things (evenhandedly for both—indeed all—offended religions) out of circulation in bookstores and cinemas would not be failing to be neutral and fair toward a group under the description “nonreligious” people. It would be failing to be fair toward “blasphemers,” not exactly a natural or routine category or grouping by any pluralist count of society. So, I assume that the only protection that
blasphemers can properly expect to get is from secularists who believe in (S), not secularists who wish to be neutral and equidistant between religious and “nonreligious” people. Those last two or three words of the last sentence are too bland a description in the state-neutralist ideal to warrant our saying that such an ideal has the very particular focus needed to count the censorship of something so specific as hurtful and contemptuous writing against a religion as antisecular.
8 What is clearly moving Taylor is that a genuine pluralism in many
contemporary societies has to acknowledge as a natural grouping in the plural mix not only Hindus, Muslims, Christians but also nonreligious people. Taylor is concerned to respect this development in the pluralism of our time. And what I am saying is that we should certainly grant him that that is a correct way to modify “the neutral and equidistant ideal of secularism” he favors, but then say, even so, that, when we speak of pluralism and its groupings today,
blasphemers is
not a natural grouping. As a result, his pluralist motivation here in adding to the mix of things toward which the state must be neutral is not sufficient (not sufficiently particular) to make the case that such censorship would be antisecular by the lights of a state-neutralist ideal of secularism.
If he were to go beyond what are broad and natural groupings to something much more indefinitely detailed in its pluralist count in a society, counting as a group any group (however specifically described, blasphemers being just one example) that could claim that there has been a lapse in neutrality by the state, after the fact of some state action, it is very doubtful that there could be anything at all that a neutralist state secularist ideal would yield by way of policy. That is to say, there would hardly be any policy that would be sanctioned as secular policy when there are an indefinite and limitless number of conflicting groups whose points of view have to be equally respected. Indeed, unless there was some
ex ante specification of the pluralist elements that a state was to be neutral between, the ideal amounts to nothing that can be interestingly specified at all. What I think we must assume such an ideal envisages, if it is to envisage something plausible, is not that “blasphemers” are
ex ante counted as a group that must be protected when devising state policies, but rather something like this: Muslims, Christians, Jews, Hindus, etc., as well as “nonreligious” people (
a fragment among whom will be novelists, filmmakers, etc. that satirize, vilify, one or another religion) must equally have a voice in the policies that a polity will adopt. Whatever policy is adopted once this fraternal deliberation takes place must count as the policies of a secular state according to this ideal. After all, it is the outcome of a state allowing evenhanded voice to all groups. Now
it may turn out that nonreligious people will want protection for the fragment among them that have offended religions deeply in the novels they write or the films they make. And if they carry the day in the deliberation, then the outcome of this state-neutralist ideal process of decision making will
coincide with the outcome of a lexical ordering imposed by (S), i.e., they will be co
extensive, (not cointensive) outcomes. But
it may turn out instead that the fraternal deliberation with all voices involved yields a policy that evenhandedly bans novels and films considered blasphemous by various religions, and, if it does, the policy will
also count as secular since the criterion of
fraternal and
equal participation of
freely speaking voices will be satisfied. The point is that (S), however, will
never count such an outcome as secular, so long as free speech is an ideal one begins with. The adoption of the policy will
always fall afoul of the lexical ordering that is essential to (S)’s formulation of secularism. And, just for that reason, I am saying, (S) has things more theoretically right about what secularism is.
In a clarifying response in personal correspondence to a draft of this chapter, Charles Taylor makes a point of real importance and relevance for the present in explaining why he thinks a characterization of secularism should not incorporate the first feature of secularism that I had mentioned at the outset, that it is a stance regarding religion. He expresses the anxiety that the sort of lexical ordering I propose, which mentions explicitly the importance of placing one or other ideal or goal of a polity before some religious practice or custom or law, might sometimes have the effect of having the secular polity equate some unrepresentative element of a religious population with “the religion” in question. The woeful effects of just this sort of thing are familiar from the present cold war being waged against “Islam” on the basis of a few acts of atrocity by a small fraction of Muslims. This is what Taylor says:
Here’s where the hard-line secularist focus on religion alone leads to tragic and destructive moves. They attack “Islam” for instance for female genital mutilation, and for honour killings. And they seem to have a semblance of justification in that the communities who practice these can see them as religiously sanctioned. They tar the whole community with this brush, and drive moderates into the arms of fundamentalists. Whereas, as Anthony Appiah has argued, the most effective way of ending these practices involves making allies with the more orthodox who can effectively convince Islamic societies that they are deviant to the message of the prophet.
As with everything else that prompts him on this matter, this is a humane and politically perceptive concern. But I don’t find myself convinced that these considerations, despite their great importance today, are to be diagnosed as flowing from a characterization of secularism that incorporates the lexical ordering in the terms that I have presented it. As I presented it, there is nothing in (S) that constitutes an “attack” on religion as a generality. In particular, when female genital mutilation or honor killings are identified as practices to be placed second in the lexical ordering, Islam, as a generality, is not “under attack.” Rather, the claim is entirely conditional: If there be a claim by those who practice them that these practices owe to a religion and if that claim is correct, then the placing of the practice lower in the lexical ordering than the moral and political ideals they run afoul of would be properly called a “secularist” policy on the part of the state. That is all a characterization of secularism as (S) amounts to. I don’t see that, so understood, secularism as a stance regarding religion has the effects Taylor thinks it does. If it should turn out that nothing in the religion in question sanctions these practices, then the ideals and goals of the polity may supersede these practices in a lexical ordering, but that lexical ordering would not be the lexical ordering characterized in (S), which specifically mentions religion. In that case, secularism, being a stance regarding religion, is not a notion that descriptively applies to such a case.
Moreover, though the anxiety that a whole community is being tarred by the brush of practices of a fractional group in the community is a genuine and justified anxiety to have, it is not clear how (S) as a characterization of secularism is responsible for its happening. True, as a formulation of secularism, (S) mentions religious practices without distinguishing between the numbers that do and do not practice them. But it is not such a general understanding of secularism that gives rise to the public impression that the religion in question is itself to be identified with the practice. What is really responsible for it is an irresponsible media that doesn’t care to distinguish finely enough between the practitioners and the rest of the community. And it is not as if states are completely innocent of responsibility, since states, for familiar statist reasons, track whatever the media calls or fails to call attention to. But that a state should be implicated in that sort of thing is independent of whether the state has adopted secular policies as characterized by (S). One of the real sources of difficulty is that states, including liberal states, have no (and, by the nature of the case, cannot have any) political mechanisms by which to introduce
intracommunity democratization that would show the practitioners to be an
unrepresentative minority within the community. Liberal politics has institutions that, via mechanisms like elections, calibrate representation with numbers of people. This happens, as we know, at the federal, state, regional, and even municipal level, but, unlike these levels, religious communities are too dispersed and too imprecisely defined to have such mechanisms. Whether there can be intracommunity democratization of a kind that does not depend on such representative institutions is a subject that needs much more study than it has had in political sociology. Until such democratization, a small fraction within a community, which has the shrillest voice and the most activist presence, may often get to be seen as more representative of the community than it deserves by its numbers to be, since the media will typically pay the most attention to the most audible voices, and the state, for typical reasons of state, will do so as well. This, not secularism as formulated in (S), should at bottom be the diagnosed source of Taylor’s quite proper anxiety.
Taylor is rightly anxious too that when there is an equation of a religion with a small fragment of its members and its practices, it can sometimes have the effect of driving ordinary devout people, as he puts it, “into the arms of the fundamentalists.” But again it is not clear why secularism as (S) elaborates it has any role to play in this. It is a complex question why nonpractitioners of the practices in question do not always distinguish themselves vocally and explicitly from (the far smaller number of) the practitioners. Speaking more generally, it is a complex question why ordinary devout people remain a large but silent majority and don’t speak out against the relatively small numbers of extremists and fundamentalists in their community with whom they share so little by way of ideas and ideology. The answer to such questions would have to invoke a whole range of factors, all of which, I think, are at some distance from (S)—factors that make them feel as if they are letting their side down if they were to be openly critical of anyone in their community, even those whose views and practices they have no sympathy for. In the case of Islam, this defensively uncritical psychology has been bred by years of colonial subjugation, by continuing quasi-colonial economic arrangements with American and European corporate exploitation of energy resources of countries with large Muslim populations, by immoral embargos imposed on these countries that cause untold suffering to ordinary people, by recent invasions of some of these countries by Western powers, and, finally, by the racialist attitudes toward migrants from these countries in European nations. It is these factors that are responsible for ordinary Muslims, who might have otherwise been more willing to criticize fundamentalists in their community, focusing instead primarily on an enemy that is perceived to be external rather than internal.
One might think that the rhetoric of “secularism” (like the rhetoric of “democracy”) plays a role in the anti-Islamist drumbeat of propaganda that accompanies these other factors, and therefore it in turn plays a role in making the vast majority of ordinary Muslims unwilling to be critical of the offending practitioners in their midst. That might sometimes be so. But, if and when it is so, the right thing to do is not to ask that secularism be redefined, but to demand that one should drop talk of secularism and focus instead on trying to improve matters on what is really at stake: the effects of a colonial past, a commercially exploitative present, unjust wars and embargos, racial discrimination against migrants in Europe, and so on. It is a change in these things, not a redefinition of secularism, that will draw ordinary Muslims out of “the arms of fundamentalists,” that will give the vast majority of nonpractitioners the confidence to come out of their silence and their defensive psychologies to distinguish themselves from those whom they find to be a small but extreme and unrepresentative minority in their community’s midst.
In the quoted passage, Taylor implies that secularism, as for instance defined by (S), would spoil the chances of making alliances with the orthodox in a community whose voices would have the most chance of bringing about an end of the offending practices. It is perfectly possible for a state to sometimes judge that it would be better for it to forge alliances with the orthodox element in a community to get it to speak up for an end to a certain offending practice rather than adopt a policy like (S) that opposes the practice that the orthodox element gives support to. That would be to surrender secularism for a more effective pragmatic strategy. It would not be to adopt a different ideal of secularism. I myself think that what is needed is for a secular state, as defined by (S), to help provide
internal reasons to the community, including the orthodoxy that supports the practice, to persuade it to change some of its commitments. Such a strategy is perfectly compatible with a secularism defined in terms of (S) and I discuss how that is so at length in sections 5 and 6 (see particularly note 16 and the text in the main body of this paper to which it attaches.) What is required in order to make this possible is for secularism not to give up on its lexical ordering as formulated in (S) but to seek a
conceptual vernacular within which it can seek to provide internal reasons that speak to even the orthodox element in a community. Too often secularism adopts the universalist rhetoric of rights in its efforts at persuasion rather than seek
local concepts and commitments within the community (including even among the orthodox in the community) that might put pressure on the community’s own practices and thereby eventually provide the source of internal reasons for change. This is the entire theme of sections 5 and 6.
Though (S) insists sturdily on the invariance of the lexical ordering in all contexts where there is secularism, it allows for much contextual differential in the form secularism may take because it allows for much variation in the ideals that are placed first in the lexical ordering.
Thus, for instance, the values and rights may vary from constitution to constitution, but one can assume that, if it is liberal democracies in late modernity one is concerned with, then there will be substantial overlap of the basic and familiar values—freedom of speech, say, or racial and gender equality, and so on. In other sorts of societies, the ideals may be substantially different and there may be less stress on the basic freedoms and social forms of equality. Thus some socialist societies have stressed economic equality and the right to work more than they have stressed basic freedoms. And there will no doubt be yet other forms of ideals and commitments in yet other societies that the lexical ordering mentioned in the stipulated characterization of secularism will place before the religious practices inconsistent with them. The point is not to lay down very specific ideals that form a definite list. The point, rather, is to stress the role of the priority such ideals (whatever they may be) will have in
the lexical ordering that forms the heart of the characterization of secularism.
The last point has wider implications that distinguish between (S) and Taylor’s redefinition in a rather sharp way. One should be able to characterize secularism independently of whether a polity is authoritarian or liberal in its fundamental orientation. Taylor, as I said, mentions with approval Rawls’s starting point in certain rights and other liberal ideals. This is an approval one may share without actually insisting that there cannot be variation in the form that the ideals take or the ideals themselves. The theoretically important requirement is not that there be this or that ideal but that there be ideals that do not get articulated in terms that mention religion or the opposition to religion. All the opposition to religion that the characterization in (S) demands is in the notion of a lexical ordering that follows the initial starting point in these ideals. Thus, by these theoretical lights, so long as there were such ideals motivating a polity, and they played such a role in the minimal demands of a lexical ordering, then (whatever other properties that polity possessed) it meets the necessary and sufficient condition of secularism. So, for instance, on the assumption that there were such ideals that were motivating the political regime that Atatürk imposed on Turkey, and on the assumption that religion and religious practices were always placed second in the lexical ordering as formulated in (S), the authoritarian properties of that regime do nothing to cancel the secularist nature of the regime, whatever else they cancel—for instance, the
liberal nature of the regime. Not all secularism need be liberal secularism. So also, then, many communist regimes should get counted as secular by this criterion. Someone may find the authoritarian methods by which secularism was imposed in both Atatürk’s Turkey and the Soviet Union to be wrong without denying they were committed to secularism. Taylor, who
explicitly takes it to be an advantage of his redefinition that it rules out Atatürk’s Turkey as secular,
9 is on this point at least, quite visibly at odds with (S) as a characterization of secularism. There is a further and symmetrically converse point to be made: just as secularism may bypass liberalism, liberalism may outrun secularism when the liberal goals and ideals one might begin with, such as free speech, say, are concerned to protect those who offend
non-religious sentiments and concerns, over and above protecting blasphemers. It can’t be a reason to redefine secularism that the goals it begins with (when they are liberal goals), which seek to protect one from the illiberality of some religious demands, would also protect one from illiberality coming from
other sources than religious demands. Liberalism is a wider notion than secular liberalism, which qualifies liberalism to a restricted domain, just as liberal secularism qualifies secularism to a restricted set of cases of secularism.
It is true that that Turkey and some other nations did much else besides meet the minimal requirements of the lexical ordering as articulated in (S). They sought to rule out religion not just in the polity, but in a much more general way, intruding into the cultural life and the intellectual and artistic productions of their citizens. In doing so, they went far beyond the requirements of the lexical ordering. And in doing so they were not merely enforcing secularism in authoritarian fashion, they were enforcing secular
ization as a broader social process. All this too may be acknowledged without it falsifying the observation of a more minimal property of these polities, which is that they were secular
ist. As I said in c) earlier, the characterization of secularism on offer in (S) is not by any means committed to rooting out religion in society. The lexical ordering that is the core of the characterization is perfectly compatible with a society that has a great deal of religiosity in its culture and practices. The ideals that are placed first in the lexical ordering could be such as to find acceptable a wide range of religious practices. But, equally, on the other hand, it is not a requirement of secularism, as defined by (S), that secularism should be
incompatible with determined and authoritarian efforts at imposing secularization in addition to secularism. I had said earlier that because secularism, restricted as it is to the polity, is a narrower notion than secularization, which extends as a process to society at large and its cultural and intellectual life, polities may be secular
ist with or without the society at large being proportionately secular
ized. The separateness of these two notions would also have it, of course, that just because there is extreme secularization enforced, as in Atatürk’s Turkey, that is not necessarily a sign that secularism must exist. In Turkey, as it happened, secularism did exist, but there can be a society—Tel Aviv society, unlike Jerusalem, I suspect, is one such—that is highly secularized but is embedded in a national polity that is not secularist. Moreover, the separateness of the two notions guarantees that the existence of secularization via authoritarian methods as in Atartürk’s Turkey is not a sign that secularism does not exist. Authoritarianism, whether it imposes secularism or secularization, is orthogonal to the criterion by which secularism is defined.
Quite apart from Atatürk, even Richard Dawkins and Christopher Hitchens would not get counted as secularists but
antisecularists by Taylor’s redefinition since they repudiate neutrality between religions and unbelief, the very thing that Taylor demands of secularism, when he says: “Indeed, the point of state neutrality is precisely to avoid favoring or disfavoring not just religious positions but any basic position, religious or nonreligious. We can’t favor Christianity over Islam, but also religion over against nonbelief in religion
or vice versa.”
10 But I do think something simple yet deep is under theoretical strain, if these are the implications of a semantic stipulation. I—despite being an atheist—hold no brief for Dawkins and Hitchens, who, in my view, represent one of the least appealing and most irrelevant intellectual stances on religion today. Still, the idea that they as well as the idea that Atatürk should be counted as antisecularists is too counterintuitive, and the redefinition seems to go against our most ordinary understanding and instincts about secularism for reasons that have to do with values that have nothing much to do with secularism at all.
In the last comment, I have urged that we allow that not all secularism is liberal secularism, implying more generally that secularism is only one value among others, and, as a result, it may in some contexts be accompanied by properties that put aside many of the other values that we might cherish. But there is a more radical point to be made: we might, having begun with certain goals and ideals (which make no mention of religion or opposition to religion, just as Rawls, Taylor, and (S) require), find that secularism is a quite unnecessary political doctrine or policy to adopt. We might find that religious practices and customs promote those goals and ideals quite satisfactorily and that it would be a fetish of modernity to think that secularism nevertheless must be adopted by a polity. This is the scenario whose possibility I wanted to leave space for when I was outlining the third defining feature of secularism.
It is how Gandhi thought of the ideal of secularism for India in the early part of the twentieth century, and there was wisdom in that view then. India, because of its distance from Europe, not merely physical but cultural and political, was a good test case for contemplating both secularism’s content and its relation to its own history.
If we step back and look at secularism’s history from a distance in order to try and view its larger trajectories and patterns, we notice that much of the consolidations of secularism, that is, much of it coming to be viewed as a necessity in modern societies, occurred in the context of slow- and long-forming features of European societies. One particular trajectory was central.
In the post-Westphalian European context there emerged a need for states to seek their legitimacy in ways that could no longer appeal to outdated ideas of the divine rights of states as personified in their monarchs. This new form of legitimacy began to be sought by the creation of a new form of political psychology in a new kind of subject, the “citizen,” of a new kind of entity that had emerged, the “nation.” It was to be done, that is, by creating in citizens a
feeling for the nation, which generated a legitimacy for the state, because the nation was defined in tandem, in hyphenated conjunction, with a certain kind of increasingly centralized state. This nation-state was to be legitimized by this feeling among its subjects, a political-psychological phenomenon that would somewhat later come to be called national
ism. In European nations such a feeling was uniformly created in their citizens by a very standard ploy—by finding an
external enemy
within, the outsider in one’s midst, “the other” (the Irish, the Jews … to name just two) to be despised and subjugated. In a later time, with the coming of a more numerical and statistical form of discourse, these would come to be called minorities, and the ploy that I am outlining would be described as majoritarianism. Often
religion was either central to or was implicated in the way that minorities and majorities were defined, and it was to
repair the deep and severe damages and scars caused by
this process that secularism was consolidated as an indispensable necessity in the political life of nations. It came to be seen as a politically constructed guarantee of tolerance in this context, that is to say, in a context of modernity in which a very specific trajectory of nation-state formation was central. It is not that intolerance did not exist in prior times, but the structural necessities set up by new national boundaries and political institutions made the intolerance generated by the self-consciously adopted ploy I have sketched, as something seemingly quite impossible to alleviate in any other way but by the formulation of secularism and the devising of state policies in order to promote it.
Now, it should be possible to say, as Gandhi did, that where such a trajectory had never occurred as it had in Europe, no such repair was needed. It was his view that religions had long pervaded the political life of India, but it was within an ethos of quite unself-conscious pluralism, a syncretic religious culture, within which politics was conducted in scattered loci of power, with no highly centralized state seeking to legitimate itself by creating the wrong basis for unity by a self-consciously constructed feeling among its citizens. A unity that was instead an outgrowth of a rooted and syncretic culture within which diverse religions were, without too much strain, in any case relatively tolerant of each other, required no artificial measure and policies, no doctrinal formulations of modernity, under the name of secularism. Whatever the other shortcomings of such a culture, there was nothing measurably damaging of this specific sort to repair, and to impose secularism on one’s people under these circumstances would be a mimicry of its colonial masters, a form of cognitive slavery. So it seemed to Gandhi. And, in fact, his greatest anxiety was that the eager modernizers around him in the Indian freedom movement that he led would fall into a form of thinking in which the post-Westphalian European path to modernity, conceived via this new form of state, was seen as compulsory for India as well. When he wrote first about it in the early part of the twentieth century he declared explicitly that it was quite uncompulsory.
Savarkar, who very deliberately and articulately formulated such a European path of politics for India, with majoritarian methods to achieve feelings of unity in his vision of a modern Indian nation of the future, was Gandhi’s chief ideological opponent, and it is not surprising that it was one of his followers who would later assassinate him. Everything Gandhi stood for also stood in the way of such a conception of Indian modernity. As it turned out, Savarkar’s thinking had a great deal of influence in India, even within the Congress Party that Gandhi led, and the openly vocal and activist form of majoritarian Hindu nationalism that has emerged in the country since the passing of Gandhi, Nehru, and some of the other leaders of the older generation has made something like secularism seem much more obviously relevant for India than it seemed to Gandhi when he was writing about these matters during the early period of the freedom movement. The point I am laboring in all this is that there may be many ideals—of pluralism, of tolerance—that we start with, just as Taylor asks, but in many societies, there may be no work for the lexical ordering and for secularist doctrine, in general, to do in order to promote those ideals. Secularism is a normative position that is shaped by these ideals in specific contexts where the ideals and goals require it. It is not a goal in itself. Were the ideals present in other political forms and arrangements, the need for secularism would not so much as arise. In my view, it is theoretically sounder to say this than to redefine secularism so that it becomes the appropriate doctrine for all contexts and occasions and always serves the ideals we wish to pursue.
Still, I think one can explore these matters a little more by voicing a protest on behalf of Taylor’s redefined ideal of secularism. One might do this by saying that what I am suggesting is the wrong lesson to learn from Gandhi’s reaction to the situation in early twentieth-century India. After all, what Gandhi was pointing out was that there was tolerance by each religion of the other and there was equal and free participation of all religions in the syncretic religious culture of the time, and that just is secularism in the fraternal as well as the liberty and equality sense that Taylor has outlined. So, if Taylor is right, Gandhi was in favor of, not against, secularism, and his view was that India was always secularist. It may be that, once there is a more centralized state than existed in India in that earlier time, this earlier secularism would have to be recast a bit to be seen as a centralized state being neutral and evenhanded among different religions, trying to steer modern society to replicate the syncretism of past times by keeping all religions to be mutually respectful of each others’ freely chosen religious practices. But it would essentially be a secularism that was continuous with the past.
A response on behalf of (S) to such a protest will help to bring out in a little more depth the history by which (S) has come to seem necessary.
The view voiced in the protest, I think, would be a quite mistaken reading of Gandhi, who was more clear-eyed about how secularism emerged from a certain history in the West and had certain distinct functions of meeting specific goals that needed to be met as a result of certain developments in Europe in the modern period.
The fact is that the goals and ideals Gandhi articulated were merely those of tolerance and pluralism. But tolerance and pluralism, though they obviously have some relation with secularism (as they do with any number of other political notions and doctrines) are by no means identical with it. And secularism is not a guarantee for those ideals in all contexts. It is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for tolerance and pluralism. Secularism is a doctrine that is also introduced to further goals of a quite different sort that were not in the forefront of Gandhi’s mind, and even when tolerance and pluralism were at the core of what secularism sought to promote it was within a context that I have just sketched, in which this core came to be surrounded by other goals as well. Thus, for instance, it would never occur to Gandhi to be anxious to allow blasphemy to go uncensored. Nor did it particularly worry him that one or other religion, Hinduism or Islam, was running afoul of the ideals of gender equality in its family laws. These were not ideals or goals that were central to what he thought politics should be responding to and pursuing.
11 On the matter of religion, his focus was instead on keeping India removed from a politics in which Hindu majoritarianism entered as a way of creating nationalist feeling in India, thus giving rise to a trajectory in which secularism would be the natural outcome introduced to repair the damage in this.
Now, one might think that a state conceived as neutral among different religions, as Taylor envisages it, is the best method by which to deal with the damage done by this trajectory. So why am I resisting calling it secularism?
This is a good question and the answer is that once this trajectory takes its course, the damage is so deep and pervasive and so easily and constantly revived and revisited, that minorities are simply not in a position to ensure that the state, even in a democracy (obviously even less so in more authoritarian regimes), will be able to be evenhanded. Political parties will constantly appeal, for electoral gain to majoritarian tendencies and will not be able to eschew these tendencies after electoral success when they are tenants of the state. This, in turn, gives rise to a
reaction among minorities to fall into identity politics as a defense, since the state is often unable to withstand majoritarianism and remain neutral. When majorities and minorities are defined in terms of religion in this familiar scenario, there inevitably arises a sense that religion (in the political sphere)
itself is the problem, even though the historical source of the problem lies in majoritarianism. Recent Indian history has increasingly shown this to be true, a victory, as I said, for the forces of Savarkar over Gandhi, even within the Congress Party, leave alone the Hindu nationalist party. For this general reason (and not merely in India), something more radical was said to be needed, something that—in crucial ways that are necessary to avoid this entire tendency to domination by a majority and religious identitarian reactive responses by minorities—keeps religion out of the polity, so that the temptation of the appeal to religious majoritarianism is preempted at the outset as a legal or constitutional transgression, something the courts of an independently constituted judiciary are there to ensure (though, as it turns out in some recent decisions, it is not obvious that the courts are willing always to do so). Thus this entire trajectory that I’ve been describing at some length gives rise to an ethos in which something like a lexical ordering of the sort I have mentioned tends to come to the forefront in how a modern polity is conceived. Once conceived this way, the term
secularism is and has been the natural name for it. And once the conception comes into place, it begins to seem, in this increasingly and
very specifically modern political ethos that had its origins in post-Westphalian Europe, that it is not sufficient to be neutral and evenhanded among religions.
Moreover, in such an ethos, where religion itself comes to be seen as the source of the problem, whether in its majoritarian exploitation or in its minoritarian reaction to that, new goals (that is, goals beyond merely tolerance and pluralism) emerge, and, though they are defined independently of religion (goals such as free speech, say, and gender equality), one begins to detect that, in light of these new goals, there are shortcomings
in religion. Thus free speech is now seen as free speech (even) in the face of a religious requirement to suppress deliberate and brazen blasphemy, and gender equality is steered toward gender equalit
y in the face of gender-unjust religious family laws; and so on. Again, as a result, something like (S) alone, therefore, comes to seem like the only policy that could provide the repair and reform of religion, because neutrality and evenhandedness among religions cannot possibly promote these new goals and ideals. It is not enough to neutrally and evenhandedly allow each religion in society its free speech-denying blasphemy laws or its gender-discriminating family laws. These laws are trumped only by the first-placed lexical ordering of free speech and gender equality. Of course, one can still insist that the state neutrally and evenhandedly apply the lexical ordering to each religion, but that still means that the ideal of neutrality and evenhandedness is embedded in (S). It does not constitute a secularism that is independent of (S).
None of this, however, was relevant when Gandhi wrote, as neither issues of blasphemy laws nor of gender inequality were in the forefront of the public agenda surrounding the local, syncretist religious cultures and the politics that surfaced in them. (And this may well be the case in many parts of the world to this day—in many regions of Africa, say, even possibly in parts of the Middle East, though the intense material and therefore cultural gaze on, not to mention interventions in, the latter by Western interests may be comprehensively and decisively changing that.)
12 But they are much more relevant now, and, along with the need for the reversal of social and political damages of religious majoritarian sources for nationalism, they form part of a trajectory that emerged in India
since the time Gandhi expressed his qualms against a very specific path in European modernity. To describe Gandhi’s position of an earlier time in India as secularist, therefore, is to quite fail to see the relevance of a range of developments in India since the time in which he first wrote (the developments of what I had called a specific post-Westphalian trajectory), regarding which he had prescient anxieties about what might be visited upon India if the trajectory was adopted there. If we pay close attention to his anxieties in that period, we can recognize that he was not a proto-secularist but rather that he did not want the conditions in which secularism would seem a necessity at all to occur in India.
To sum up, it has, in general, been the burden of these several comments, a) to f), that I have been making on the nature of (S) to say that its stipulated form of secularism in terms of a certain lexical ordering gives a certain theoretical bite and specificity to secularism, such that it is not all good in all contexts but only a good in some contexts and therefore not always to be embraced even in temporal modernity, if the conditions don’t require it for the pursuit of other worthy goals. This specificity also allows one to say that secularism can often be accompanied by bad political and institutional arrangements, such as in Atatürk’s Turkey or in Baathist Iraq or in the aggressively authoritarian secularist policies of some communist regimes. It does not see those bad political arrangements and institutions as a reason and occasion to try and redefine secularism so that they don’t count as secularist polities at all. Such redefinitions take the bite out of the concept, in much the same way that the redefinition attempted in the idea of “people’s democracy” to counter “free democracy” took the bite out of the notion of democracy.
13 The specific formulation of the lexical ordering, moreover, has the strict advantage over the “neutrality and equidistant state” ideal of secularism in disallowing things that would, in our own time if not earlier, intuitively count as antisecular—for example, censorship of works of art and literature on grounds of “blasphemy” against a religion, something that the latter ideal would permit in a given case, on the grounds that it was ready and willing to neutrally permit it in all other cases of blasphemy against all other religions in the society.
I’ve spent considerable time on these semantic matters with a view to bringing out the content of secularism, using Taylor’s interesting and challenging ideas of a redefinition of secularism as a foil. I had said that though I think Taylor’s redefinition has worthy moral and political motivations, it is not as well motivated theoretically. (S), by contrast, does not make any attempt at redefinition, it merely tries to elaborate, along modest and minimalist lines, the rationale underlying the instincts behind dogmatic-sounding metaphors such as “the separation of church and state.” As such, (S) seems to contain crucial elements that Taylor is trying to redefine secularism away from.
I want to turn now from semantic matters, from questions of what is the more plausible and nonarbitrary stipulation by which we define or characterize the content of secularism, to questions of which position is more plausible, no matter how it is defined and what it is called, i.e., whether it is called secularism or not. Thus we might ask: no matter which we think is better described as secularism, is it better to adopt the ideal of a state that is neutral and evenhanded with all religions and nonreligious points of view, and that takes no adversarial stance against religion (thus repudiating the very first feature of secularism that I had presented in section 1), or is to better to adopt (S)?
5
Let me begin by trying to diagnose sympathetically why it might theoretically and philosophically seem to many that Taylor’s ideal of a state, neutral and equidistant between religious and nonreligious points of view, is a better position to adopt than (S).
In section 2 I took up the question of what
justified secularism over and above what defined or characterized it, saying that it was important to distinguish between the two. And, while discussing the justification of secularism, I had invoked Bernard Williams’s distinction between two types of justification, one that appealed to internal reasons and the other to external reasons, and had claimed that there are only internal reasons for embracing secularism. I have not argued for nor will I argue for that claim in this chapter, partly for reasons of space, but partly also because I have done so extensively in previous essays.
14 The point of interest in the present essay, as I say in section 2, is that this view is entirely compatible with, and indeed lies behind, the claim that secularism should only be adopted on the basis of an overlapping consensus. On these issues of justification and adoption (rather than those of definition just discussed in section 4) there is complete accord between Taylor’s views and the ones expressed in this chapter.
To political philosophers and theorists, it might seem natural to conclude from these commitments on which there is complete accord between us that secularism is fated to be mired in a form of
relativism regarding moral and political values, and such a relativism may well suggest, in turn, that something like a “neutral state” version of secularism is what we should retreat to, whereas any secularism such as (S) that seeks a somewhat more adversarial stance against religion should be counted not as secularism but as one nonreligious standpoint among other standpoints, including religious standpoints, between which the state is neutral.
15 This approximates Taylor’s own favored understanding of secularism.
So, we must ask, whichever we think is best to call secularism, is the neutralist ideal shown to be better than (S) as a consequence of the relativist implications that seem to follow from the stress on internal reasons in the justification of secularism?
The idea is this. If there are no external reasons that support a moral or political standpoint or value (such as secularism, say, or, to keep things even more specific and focused, secular liberalism), if internal reasons are the only reasons one can bring to bear when there is a deep disagreement over values (between, say, such a secular liberalism and one or other religious point of view), then it might seem that something like relativism about these values and points of view is necessarily in the offing. Recall that external reasons are reasons that all will agree on, no matter what their values and substantial commitments may be, and internal reasons appeal only to substantial moral and political commitments of individual citizens. If internal reasons are the only reasons there are for justifications of such values as secularism, the thought that (S) in its secular liberal form will even have the resources to effectively offer such internal reasons to a strongly held religious standpoint (say, for example, a position with strong Muslim identitarian political values) to change its mind might seem too optimistic; and that, in turn, will make it seem as if some antisecular Muslim commitments, such as to the value of censorship of blasphemy, may have their own sort of truth (
relativistically characterized truth) on their side.
16 And, if that is so, then it would seem only right that a state having to now navigate these different
true standpoints—(S) in its secular liberal form as well as various religious standpoints such as Islamists and other strongly held religious views—should be neutral and evenhanded with each of them, since each has the prestige of
truth on its side. This would reduce (S), even in the eyes of those who subscribe to it, to one among other true points of view, including religious ones. Thus the relativism that seems to emerge as a consequence from the points of philosophical
agreement between Taylor and me, on the primacy of internal reasons and the inefficacy of external reasons, may seem to suggest that the state neutrality ideal is
theoretically quite well motivated (by this relativism) and (S) less well so, despite all the theoretical points I made in the previous section.
Can this be right? Does this specific argument, via a relativism that flows from the primacy of internal reasons, that I make on sympathetic behalf of Taylor’s view, give us a reason to adopt the state-neutralist ideal he favors over (S)? Or, to put it differently, does this specific argument give a state committed to adopting (S) any reason to yield to a more state-neutralist ideal?
I think it is arguable that it does not.
Notice, first, what exactly is meant by relativism, as it seems to follow from the denial of external reasons and the claim that only internal reasons will justify secular liberalism. It means something quite strong. What is meant is that when there are no external reasons, and two parties are in disagreement over some value commitment,
there may in principle be no scope for either party to give even internal reasons to one another. Internal reasons are dependent on support coming from our substantive values, not something given to us by the very fact of our rationality. Therefore, unlike external reasons, there is no guarantee that internal reasons to subscribe to (S) will be available, since they are dependent on further values that may not be present—in the case under consideration, present in the values held by Islamists. And, in general, it is prima facie possible that in some sorts of value disagreement there will,
in principle, be no such further values for the parties in the disagreement to appeal to. In that case we will have the kind of impasse mentioned in the formulation, just given, of relativism. The expression
in principle is doing some serious work in this formulation of relativism. Relativism is a theoretical or philosophical position; it is not just a practical difficulty about how it is sometimes very hard to persuade someone you disagree with on some evaluative matter. The theoretical position is that each party in the dispute may be utterly unreach
able by the other. This may indeed be cause for alarm to subscribers to (S), and, to the extent that we are alarmed, a concession and retreat to Taylor’s redefinition of secularism shows the appropriate respect for each position that has truth on its side because (S) cannot claim greater truth for the ideals it begins with and therefore must drop its claim to a lexical ordering that places those ideals first and religious laws and customs and practices second when they clash. Thus relativism requires that not only are there no external reasons for justifying secular ideals, reasons that all can share and find to be reasons, but there are
no reasons (not internal ones either) that it can, in principle, find to justify secular ideals to other more religious points of view. Secular liberalism is one truth among many, and not merely one standpoint among many. The latter claim (one standpoint among many) is uncontroversial. But for a secular liberal to allow the former claim (that religious points of view that it often wants to place second in a lexical ordering have the
truth on their side) would undermine the very priorities asserted in the lexical ordering. A relevantly neutral state of the kind that Taylor recommends is a better form of polity for such a scenario than (S), which has to concede that secular liberalism is just one truth among many. So these considerations of relativism might well motivate the adoption of Taylor’s neutralist state rather than a state that adopts the lexical ordering ideal.
But before we concede that this relativism is the fate of (S), given the primacy of internal reasons, some more detailed understanding of what exactly internal reasons are is required.
What is it to find internal reasons to persuade another? Internal reasons are reasons we give to another that appeal to some of his own values in order to try and persuade him to change his mind on some given evaluative issue, such as, say, a commitment to censorship of blasphemy. So if a Muslim does have such a commitment, a secular liberal subscribing to (S) can only appeal to some other value of his which is in tension or in conflict with his commitment to the censorship of blasphemy. To put it very explicitly, one will have to find that such Muslims are committed a) to censorship of blasphemy, and yet that they are also committed b) to various other values that may lend support to the value of free speech. And for (S) to use internal reasons against such Muslims is to stress b) them in an effort to bring them around to discarding a). Of course, if (S) was justifiable on grounds of external reasons, one couldn’t appeal to considerations such as b), which is a substantive value. But, in that case, one would not need to appeal to such a consideration. It is only because one takes the view that both Taylor and I, following Williams, take, that there are no external reasons, that one is forced to appeal to considerations such as b).
In general, then, the strategy of internal reasons is a strategy that can only work when those against whom it is brought to work are
internally conflicted. (It is important to add that conflicts within values need not always take the form of there being blatant inconsistencies among them. In fact it may seldom be that. Much more likely and much more pervasive are conflicts of a more subtle kind, tensions or dissonances between values.)
We can now pull the strands together. Relativism, as I’ve defined it for the purposes of this chapter’s concerns, is a doctrine that holds if there is a certain kind of impasse. It holds if there are, in principle, no internal reasons that two parties in a disagreement over values can give to one another. And if the prospect for giving internal reasons turns on the possibility of there being an internal conflict in at least one of the parties involved in a disagreement over values, then that implies that relativism would hold only if both parties in such a disagreement are completely unconflicted, that is, if they have perfectly and maximally coherent value economies. In other words, in order for relativism of the sort we are worrying about to be true, it would have to be the case that someone with whom one disagrees over values is not merely never inconsistent (as I admitted, blatant inconsistency might be hard to attribute to political and moral subjects), but they would also have to be wholly without any tension or dissonance in their values and desires. That alone makes for a principled impasse.
But it is hard to think that ordinary human subjects are so completely without internal conflict in this broad sense. The idea of such a total lack of inner conflict is an extraordinary condition to find in any value economy. Relativism, conceived on this condition, would find instance, it seems, only when two parties in a dispute over a value were monsters of coherence. Perhaps some imagined rational automata are maximally coherent in their value commitments, but the idea that ordinary human moral-psychological economies are so is barely conceivable. Thus, so long as Islamists with commitments to blasphemy laws are susceptible to conflicting relations among their commitments, so long as they are not possessed of maximally coherent value economies, the scope of internal reasons to establish secular liberalism even in the face of identity politics is maintained. Maximal coherence being a barely conceivable condition, there is no need to despair about the scope for secular liberal politics to succeed without externalist reasons and arguments.
The point cannot be quite left where it is.
Let it even be conceivable that, at a given time, a particular illiberal moral-psychological economy is highly coherent and unconflicted—at any rate, let it be conceivable, as it surely is, that any conflict or tension that it
does contain among its value commitments is not as a matter of fact helpful in bringing it around to shedding its antiliberal commitments. It is perfectly possible that, even if Islamists are internally conflicted, these may be on matters that are not relevant to (S)’s efforts to give internal reasons to them to get them to change their mind on censorship of blasphemy. This
still does not hobble the scope of secular liberalism. Why not? The answer to this question, I think, is central to the epistemology of political and moral values. The answer is
because political philosophy cannot consider moral subjects and political citizens as standing outside of history, in some timeless, unconflicted psychological economy.
Since citizens are historical subjects, history and the incoming states of information that it provides to those subjects in its course may well introduce conflict for them by introducing tensions and dissonance in the relations between their value commitments. Let me give just one example at some distance from the dispute on issues of blasphemy to illustrate what I have in mind. It is now fairly well documented that the large increase in pro-choice attitudes among hitherto even relatively conservative women in America in the third quarter of the last century was a result of their having deliberated their way out of a conflict in their own commitments, a conflict that emerged fully only in that period of history, when, as a result of the rise of service industries and the relative decline of heavy manufacturing goods industries, the possibility of a more gender-distributed work force was created. A historical change, which provided greater prospects for employment for women, introduced conflict into the values of even hitherto conservative women, and this in turn gave rise to internal deliberation on their part that resulted in many of them revising their views on the issue of abortion. The point, then, is that even if, at a given time, a value economy seems relatively unreachable by internal reasons because it is relatively coherent and unconflicted, so long as we think of moral-psychological economies as necessarily being in history, internal conflicts may be injected by historical developments into moral-psychological economies.
The point is essentially Hegelian, though in Hegel himself it is unfortunately marred because it is nested in terms that were unnecessarily deterministic. But it is a point of the utmost importance for those who think both that (S) can only be justified on the basis of internal reasons and that thinking so entails
no relativism of the sort we are considering.
This Hegelian idea goes deeper than it might seem. It might seem that all the idea amounts to is that at some later time we might be able to persuade someone with whom we are in disagreement by giving her internal reasons, but, for now at least, there is an impasse and so relativism about reasons is true. But this deflationary description misses the real theoretical status of the appeal to the subject-in-history. That appeal is precisely intended to repudiate the idea that we should think of subjects as being in slabs of time, with relativism about their values holding in one slab, and possibly passing away in the next. Despite the talk of different times, that would still be to conceive the subject essentially synchronically at each slab of time. A genuinely diachronically conceived subject (hardly ever the subject that is considered by analytical philosophers and political theorists writing about morals and politics or anything else), a subject conceived neither synchronically nor in discreetly periodized times, but rather a subject conceived of as essentially historically open-ended, is exactly intended to replace the subject relativized to a time when her values may have a “relative” truth or her reasons a relative closure. Hence the inclination to say, “Relativism for now, but not perhaps later!” is to not yet quite be on board with the depth of the point that Hegel’s stress on the importance of history for our conception of human subjectivity is making. To be fully on board is to see that no sort of relativism is sanctioned for subjects conceived essentially diachronically and therefore open to the internal conflicts that history may provide.
I will admit again, however, that my appeal to Hegel here is highly selective, since the fact that history should play this kind of role in our understanding of moral subjectivity (paradoxically) opens things up against the very sort of historical determinism that historicism, in particular Hegel’s own historicism, usually suggests. The select element in Hegel that I am applauding is the idea that reason (what I, following Williams, call “internal” reason) does its work in a human subject by bringing about changes of value via deliberation on her part to overcome internal conflicts between values (something that popularizing Hegelians—never Hegel himself—describe overly schematically in dialectical terms of the trio of “thesis, antithesis, and synthesis”), and that one does so very often as a result of conflicts (what in the popular Hegelian representation is called antitheses) that emerge because of incoming states of information provided by specifically historical encounters. Once viewed this way, there is no reason to think that relativism follows upon the loss of external reasons, and so no reason to be pessimistic about the scope of
internal reasons to be a resource for secular liberal political outcomes. Within this selective Hegelian view of the importance of history and of diachronic subjectivity, the right way to describe what has wrongly been described as this “pessimism” is simply to say that there is no Whiggish
guarantee of a consummation of the historical process in a secular liberal outcome. That is not pessimism, it is just a recoil from a
deterministic historicism. One can be as optimistic as one wishes and hold out for history to introduce conflict in the points of view that one wishes to offer internal reasons to in order to change their commitments. Thus secular liberalism can remain committed to its ideals with confidence, and a secular state need not retreat to neutrality between secularism and other religious points of view, even in the face of the most vexed disagreement with these other points of view.
That we should see the significance of history for subjectivity along these lines is, however, not a merely metaphysical position; it is in a rarefied sense itself an
evaluative position. This point is crucial. After all, someone else may see history as having a rather depressing record in resolving conflict between groups and resist my repudiation of relativism, a repudiation that has
the default lie in the view that it is always at least possible that new conflicts
internal to an individual or group will—via internal reasoning—help resolve conflicts
between individuals or groups. Such a person will simply not find the record in history sanctioning this default position. The default says that when there is an intractable value disagreement between two parties, history may always inject in one of the parties the sort of internal conflict necessary for the other to provide internal reasons to it. The interlocutor here will deny this, saying that the record of history does not justify this to be the default position. I have no purely philosophical or metaphysical argument against such an interlocutor, one that does not agree with me about how to view the significance of history for moral subjects in conflict with one another. To find this interlocutor wrong is, in the end, to assert a value. In fact, we cannot find him wrong without asserting a value, we cannot find him wrong by a nonevaluative argument. And to say that is to assert the priority of the evaluative over the metaphysical.
This needs more patient exposition.
The default position says we must see the significance of history for subjectivity to be as follows: that one always see it as at least possible that a dispute in values may be resolved by internal reasoning as a result of the requisite internal conflict being introduced into one or other of the disputing parties by the incoming states of information that historical changes provide to their psychological and value economies. It is when the significance of history is viewed along these lines (as allowing such a default position) that we are in turn allowed to turn our backs on the claim of relativism that the deepest disputes in value might constitute an impasse. Such a default allows one to make no concession to a possible right or truth or correctness on the side of one’s opponent in cases of interesting and deep moral and political dispute. So the hard question remains: what gives us the right to view the significance of history for moral subjectivity along these lines? Why may we not see its significance along quite different lines, see history as providing too much evidence for disallowing what I claim as at least a necessary and permanent possibility? The nested modalities are complicated here, but my interlocutor’s idea will be that what I am insisting is a possibility might only be contingently so: there may be no necessity that such a possibility always exists. History is simply not to be viewed in the optimistic way I am viewing it. It is possible that such dispute resolving internal conflicts are introduced into moral subjects by history, but it is possible also that they are not. Why, then, am I insisting that history must be viewed in a way that it necessarily leaves it as an open possibility that such a conflict is introduced?
As I admitted, there is no answer to this question (and so there is no justification for taking the default position I do on the significance of history) along lines that are
non-normative or purely metaphysical. There is nothing in history, nothing in the concept of history and our place in it, when that is conceived in purely descriptive and non-normative terms, that could instruct us to view history as offering us the default position I insist on. To take the default position I do, therefore, is
itself to take a higher-order
evaluative stance. And it is only by taking such an evaluative stance that a secular liberal can express the confidence that disputes in identitarian contexts with illiberal tendencies need not ever produce the despondency of saying that perhaps both sets of principles (liberal and illiberal) may have their own sort of right on their side.
What do I mean by saying that it is in the end an evaluative stance that gives a secular liberal the confidence to insist on the exclusive rightness of secular liberalism against illiberal opponents, despite the loss of externalist reasons and the loss of externalist justifications of liberalism? I mean simply that it reflects a value, a value central to what I think is best conceived as a special and unusual version of humanism.
Here is how I have allowed myself to think of it.
When one is in a moral dispute with another, even if it is a bitter and vexed dispute, it is far better to have an attitude of inclusiveness toward one’s foe that makes one strive to share the truth as one sees it with him, rather than to adopt an excluding attitude and say that he may have his own sort of truth or right on his side. The latter is what the relativist pluralist says, and it will be said by anyone who does not see the philosophical and methodological force and insight of the Hegelian notion of a subject and its significance for morals and politics as I am seeing it. For someone who does see that force and that significance, the attitude will be quite the opposite, the value of inclusiveness. This is the value that claims it is far more attractive to say, even to one’s bitterest foe in a moral or political conflict, “You must be my brother” than it is to say “You can never be my brother.” To insist that he must be your brother, to refuse to allow him his own truth, and to strive to convince him of the truth as you see it and judge it is to show the requisite attitude of inclusiveness toward him. This may seem paradoxical since one is refusing him his own sort of truth for his views in the name of seeing him as one’s brother. But that is just how it is. Perhaps only a subject as perverse and abstract as philosophy can see in this no paradox at all.
I will admit that the rhetoric of “must” versus “never” in my last paragraph to express the contrasting values does not present the best options. I did use the flamboyant rhetoric even so, and presented the options in their most extreme form, in order to bring out the contrast vividly. To care about the truth, as one sees it and judges it, and to care enough for others who do not see it, to strive to share it with them, need not take on the vocabulary which has it that one thinks they “must” be one’s brothers and embrace the truth we see. But that vocabulary captures something of the caring that I want to stress here against the relativist form of pluralism that precisely does not care in this way. Opposing such a relativistic form of pluralism, I am saying, involves not merely appealing to the Hegelian notion of subjectivity in the way I do, but also seeing that appeal as an assertion of a value of caring about the truth (as one sees it and judges it), rather than showing an indifference to others who disagree with one, as the relativistic pluralist does when he says that they may have their own sort of moral truth on their side. Such a way of caring for truth therefore itself reflects a caring for
others, caring enough to want to convince them of the truth. That is the point of the talk of “brotherhood” as a value, a humanist value, that, in this specific sense, is missing in the relativist cast of pluralism.
To many humanists such talk of brotherhood—flowing as it does from an ideal of caring for something so abstract as truth and wanting to share that abstract thing with others—will seem too intellectualized a way of talking compared either to the down-to-earth ways in which we talk of the humanist values of brotherhood or to the sentimental, literary cast it has taken on ever since the rhetoric of “sweetness and light.” It is brotherhood based on an epistemological value rather than on the usual sort of moral values of solidarity and support that are articulated in standard versions of humanism. To such traditional humanists, the paradox of denying one’s moral foe his own sort of rightful moral view in the name of brotherhood will seem to undermine the doctrine from within. But, as I said, there is no paradox here. It is a sign of greatly respecting someone, of including him in humanity, that you deeply want him to believe what you believe to be the truth rather than grant him, as a truth (his truth), what you take to be deeply false. I admit that this is an abstract way of configuring the ideal of human inclusiveness. But why should humanism not have highly abstract sources? These sources are precisely what might give the doctrine some further muscle and rigor and therefore make it less dismissible as a musty and pious doctrine.
If I am right, it is, in the end, this abstractly humanistic and evaluative understanding of the role of history in the constitution of human subjectivity in morals and politics that underlies the repudiation of relativism in the realm of moral and political values.
17 (In the more purely cognitive realm of science, the issues are quite different, and responses to relativism need to be constructed along different lines.) What are its implications for our subject of secularism?
6
The goal has been to show that this repudiation of relativism allows a state that has adopted (S) to remain committed to its idea of a lexical ordering. It was intended to preempt the need for a state to abandon (S) and retreat to a neutrality between nonreligious and religious points of view.
If the argument of the last section is convincing, then, though anyone, committed to the idea of an overlapping consensus on some policy such as (S), is committed to a pluralism about
reasons for subscribing to (S), they are
not committed to a pluralism about the conclusions and outcomes based on those reasons. This is because the argument allows them to say that they are not committed to merely a relativistic truth for (S), but committed to its truth,
simpliciter. With right (a right given by the entire Hegelian dialectic I am presenting), (S) takes its own commitments to be true and holds out for them against opponents, given the possibility that history will inject conflicts in their thinking so as to make them come around to its commitments by the internal reasons that those conflicts might introduce into their moral-psychological economies. It holds out for fully secular outcomes and in no way wavers in confidence about the truth of (S), even if it grants that (S) might not be implementable until internal reasons, as a result of historical developments, are available to religious points of view that, in the present, contain illiberal commitments. So, in the examples we considered earlier, it would insist that something like laws requiring censorship of blasphemy or gender-unjust family laws of a religion must be placed lower in the lexical ordering than free speech and gender equality. It would not grant that these laws possess truth, relativistic truth, from within their own larger religious points of view. The whole point of the stress on a Hegelian framework for understanding the role of internal reasons is to ensure that (S) need not make any such concession or compromise on the
exclusive truth or rightness of its commitments to free speech and gender equality, giving it the right to assert the lexical ordering it favors. Thus (S) will not allow secular liberalism to be demoted to just one truthful standpoint amongst others, as was suggested would happen if relativism were true. This makes all the difference to the question whether we should hold fast to (S) or concede the superiority of a state-neutralist ideal that Taylor has proposed as being better.
The issue can be usefully explored by looking at a very well-known example from India as a test case. In the aftermath of Indian independence, Muslims in India, after much fascinating discussion during the Constituent Assembly debates, were allowed by constitutional provision to live by their own personal and family laws. (I am going to consider this case, ignoring the fact that there has been a reform of the Hindu code as it applies to family laws. What this asymmetry between Muslims and Hindus shows is that granting Muslims their own personal laws runs afoul of both (S) and the state neutrality ideal that Taylor has advocated, but, I am concerned for now only with the fact that Muslims were granted their own personal laws and how that falls short of (S).)
How exactly that awarded outcome of an exception to Muslims in India is to be interpreted is actually a rather delicate matter, and one may see in it two possible ways of conceiving of what the state intended and therefore two possible ways in which the state conceived of itself.
One way to look at this case is to see it as triumph of the kind of pluralism that is suggested by the relativist position. What pluralism, in the relativist form, allows for is the idea that a liberal democratic state will, in the name of minority cultural rights, grant to minorities (in the Indian case, to Muslims) their own special personal laws on divorce, marriage, alimony, etc., even if some of these laws are illiberal in various respects. On this reading, the state may grant to all religions their own
alternative nomic or customary system, which is a rival system to liberal law, with its own sort of right or truth on its side, and the pluralism that the constitution was committed to must acknowledge that fact.
18 So interpreted, the state can be viewed as approximating a neutralist position, not favoring secular ideals over Muslim personal laws as a lexical ordering would, but instead granting the Muslim demand in the constituent assembly debates that they be allowed to live by their own personal laws.
But the Hegelian considerations I have presented allow another possible reading of the concession to Muslims, which I also think is the more historically accurate one, the one that the framers of the constitution actually had in mind. On this reading, it is not that the Muslim community is being granted its demand for living by its own personal and family laws on the grounds that their standpoint, like the secular standpoint, has truth on its side. Rather the thinking was this: in the aftermath of independence, the Muslims who remained in India and did not migrate to Pakistan lost a great deal—they lost their count in numbers not only due to migration to Pakistan but also due to the killing of Muslims in the pogroms on the Indian side of the newly partitioned borders, they lost jobs, they lost land, in the vital sense of its wide availability in instruction in schools and colleges, they even lost their language, Urdu. In the face of these losses and the demoralization it generated, depriving them of the cultural aspects of their lives that are centered in their family and personal laws would be an inhumane blow for a state to deliver to a minority community. What a secular state, subscribing to something like (S) must, therefore, do is to wait for history to bring into Muslim thinking the sorts of internal conflict that might give them reasons to come around to secular ideals of gender equality and put aside their family and personal laws. But, until then, the lexical ordering that places those laws second to gender equality may be put in
abeyance—which is not the same as putting the lexical ordering
aside. One would put it aside only if one thought that the state thinks that there is
truth on the side of those laws, equal to the truth of ideals of gender equality. But one would put it in abeyance only because it would be
coercive to implement (S) until the necessary internal reasoning takes place among Muslims.
(I should add as an aside that this issue has been excruciatingly complicated at present by the fact that the demand for reform of Muslim personal law usually comes these days—and for some years now—not from anything recognizable as allowing Muslims to reform them as a result of their own internal reasoning, but rather from a kind of harassment of a minority by the Hindu right wing in the country. That Muslims could be reasonably expected to reform their personal laws by internal reasoning in the face of such harassment would be to utterly fail to understand the psychological preconditions for how internal reasons usually work in a historical context. A group’s capacity to change via internal reasoning requires a great deal of psychological security and self-confidence, precisely what is undermined by the demoralization caused by such harassment.)
Returning from the details of this example to the general point: this second reading reveals that a Hegelian framework for thinking of justification by internal reasoning and the adoption of political outcomes by an overlapping consensus preempts any need to think that a state must be neutral between secular ideals and religious standpoints. It allows for a full and confident adherence to (S), confident not only about it having the exclusive right on its side on the liberal outcomes at stake, but in the hope that it will provide internal reasons eventually to other opposing illiberal points of view to embrace those outcomes.
How does this square with my project of having secularism applaud Taylor’s motives for redefining secularism, while refraining from embracing the position that is articulated in the redefinition?
It does so by distinguishing between what is the
right outcome and the right definition, on the one hand and, on the other, what are the right ways of
justifying and implementing the right outcomes, correctly defined. If my argument is effective, the right outcome for a polity, according to a secularist, remains (S), and (S) remains the right stipulation by which secularism should be defined or characterized. It needs no redefinition. But this still leaves open the possibility for us to say that in justifying and implementing (S) we should do exactly as Taylor suggests. We should involve, in the fraternalist manner he rightly proposes, all the voices in the polity, including the antisecularist religious voices, should there be any, just as happened in the Constituent Assembly debates in India where the Muslims were able to make their demands and argue for them. Until those voices find the
internal reasons to adopt (S), (S) must be held in abeyance. If so, it should be quite possible to allow—without conceding anything theoretically amiss with (S)—that (S) remain temporarily unimplemented, just as happened with Muslim family laws in postindependent India on the
second reading I gave.
19
Why exactly should it be possible to allow this? Because the deepest concern behind Taylor’s demand of fraternal involvement of all groups, I believe, is that a state must, as far as it is possible, be
noncoercive in the adoption and implementation of the policies it views as justifiable. (Jeffrey Stout wisely advises me that since states have sanctions backing the laws they make and implement, they are, by their very nature, going to be coercive no matter what, and so a better term to use to describe Taylor’s motivation is that he would like the state to be, as far as is possible,
nondominating. I am happy to follow his advice.) Taylor’s concern here is a moral one, and it speaks for a certain conception of politics. What it properly motivates, indeed, what it forces us to do, is to look for the right forms of adoption and implementation of (S). It would be wrong to think that, in doing so, what it motivates and forces are merely things in the practical rather than in the theoretical domain. The entire construction of the role and relevance of the Hegelian notion of subjectivity in the dialectic of this chapter was intended to provide a
theoretical solution to the problem posed by Taylor’s search for a noncoercive and overlapping consensus for the secular outcome or, to put it in my own favored terms, to the problem of implementing a secularism whose justification is based only on internal rather than external reasons. But what this chapter has nevertheless insisted is that this theoretical solution requires neither a redefinition of secularism nor any concession to the superiority of state neutrality ideals over (S). It is an avoidable inference that the nondomination in the adoption of secularism that motivates Taylor’s arguments makes a difference to what it is we are adopting or should adopt. It does not lead to another
conception of secularism.
20 Such secularism as is worth believing in is well characterized by (S).
Yet I have also said that it is not required to believe (S) in all contexts. The relevance of a doctrine of the sort that (S) exemplifies emerged in particular historical contexts when certain political goals could not be pursued without something like the lexical ordering (S) formulates. (S), therefore, is a valuable doctrine to embrace and implement in contexts that approximate those historical conditions and contain those political goals. It is not a doctrine that holds without regard to context, purely on the basis of abstract philosophical arguments or on the basis of glib assertions of the universal reach of a certain familiar form of modernity.
Taylor’s own desire to redefine secularism is based—as we saw in section 3—on the argument that a context of modernity has now emerged in which his redefinition is needed. This, as he sometimes puts it, is the context of multiculturalism, in which talk of
toleration is no longer appropriate. A state neutral between different religious cultures and also nonreligious cultures should constitute the new meaning of secularism in such a multicultural context. I will end with some closing remarks on the relation between (S) and the idiom of “toleration.”
What is it about the idiom that seems inappropriate in the present multicultural West? The answer is obvious. It is a familiar and repeatedly made observation that the very idea of toleration presupposes disapproval of what is tolerated and a condescending acceptance of what is disapproved of. If, in the context of an aspiring multiculturalism, one wants to improve on or replace the attitude of disapproval with some other moral psychological attitude that cultures (including secular cultures) must exhibit toward one another, it might seem that we have two choices. One is to emphasize a different, less hostile, kind of negative attitude: indifference rather than disapproval. And his redefined secular ideal of state neutrality toward different religions might be seen as precisely maintaining such an indifference toward them, neither favoring nor disfavoring any of them, allowing each culture, in turn, to thrive in relative autonomy and with indifference rather than hostility toward one another. The other is to stress a more positive attitude: respect rather than disapproval.
Now, it must be admitted that it is exactly indifference that is opposed by the humanism underlying the Hegelian ideal of historical subjectivity in the understanding of secularism as defined by (S). When one finds something appealing in the attitude expressed by “You must be my brother” toward someone with whom one is in moral conflict, it is the appeal of
not being indifferent to his views. Respect is another matter. As I said earlier, it
is showing (a rarefied form of) respect of this abstract humanist kind to someone with whom one is in moral disagreement when one seeks to change his mind and make him one’s brother. But
for just that reason one is not showing indifference toward him and his views. So, if indifference is a crucial ingredient in the way in which one must (in multicultural societies) supersede the disapproval implicit in “toleration,” does this repudiation of indifference by (S) mean that (S) is retaining the element of disapproval that is presupposed by the idiom of “toleration”? And, if so, should we conclude that the state-neutralist secularist ideal is more apt than (S) for a context in which multiculturalism has taken us beyond the ideal of toleration? I think it would be a mistake to infer that. The moral psychology involved in (S) is more subtle than that conclusion suggests.
First of all, because (S) replaces indifference with a concern to register disagreements and attempt to change the minds of those points of view with which one is in moral and political disagreement, its assumption of disapproval of one point of view for another is never accompanied by any condescension whatever. Even if disapproval of another point of view is present, (S) demands the sort of positive engagement between points of view that leaves no place for condescension. But, for the same reason, it is not at all obvious that there really is even an assumption of disapproval that it really makes, and here is why not. The sorts of efforts that are needed to reach others (with whom one is deeply conflicted) by providing them with internal reasons and arguments requires one not merely to get past indifference toward their views but also, in a sense, to get past the disapproval of their views. Now this idea of “getting past” disapproval could, of course, still be interpreted as meaning that the disapproval of others is a necessary condition, even if not a sufficient condition, when one seeks to change their minds in situations of moral and political conflict with them. That is, it could be interpreted as saying that the disapproval must be in place throughout, but it must be supplemented by some rational engagement with (rather than merely toleration of) those whom one disapproves of. However, such an interpretation of “getting past” disapproval would not be up for the tasks at hand as I have sketched them in the last many pages. “Getting past” the disapproval would have to really amount to overcoming the disapproval and replacing it (rather than merely supplementing it) not just with respect but with further more detailed attitudes toward the other, if one is to engage the other with something as empathy-demanding as the search for internal arguments, arguments in their conceptual vernacular, in order to change their minds—since as these last two sections of the chapter make clear, nothing less than that are the tasks at hand.
What these further attitudes that are needed exactly are is a searching question in the moral psychology of politics, and part of the exercise in these last two sections has been to bring us to the point of raising it. There is not enough space to explore this question in any detail in a chapter that is already far too long. But one can convey in a general way the sorts of considerations that will matter in any answer we might give.
Take one sort of example, particularly relevant to a point Taylor raised in his response to me cited earlier. To tap the conceptual vernacular of those one opposes in providing them with internal reasons to change their mind on some particular matter (censorship of blasphemy, say), may often (though not necessarily always) involve tapping elements in their tradition that are themselves religious, even sometimes elements in the orthodox aspects of their religion. There is no reason to think that a secularism such as (S), even though it does in some sense take a stance against “religion,” cannot display its own wisdom and appeal by showing how the ideals it seeks have their echoes (or premonitions) in religious traditions. As I have said, (S) tends to be most pressingly required when religion emerges in the political arena in a specific way—in the context of majoritarianisms that are peculiarly the product of modern nationalism (to take a contemporary example, Hindu nationalism—and the Muslim identitarian backlash against it—in India of the last twenty years or more). And so, in particular, there is no reason to think that various ideals that (S) seeks to promote in the face of such religious majoritariansim cannot sometimes be argued for by appealing to the commitments of ordinary people that flow from some of the remnants of their older religious traditions that are still relatively uncontaminated by the modern contexts that have been marked by majoritarianism. It is not as if these traditions are totally erased in the lives and mentalities of people in modern society. However ruthless modernity’s trajectory might be in some parts of the world, so long as it is human mentality and culture that it acts upon, its surface will be more like a palimpsest than some sort of brand new and blank slate. If that were not the case, we would have no use or application for the concept of tradition. And so the thought is that it is quite possible that sometimes religious tradition may provide someone the grounds for internal reasons to change his mind away from the new majoritarian forms that religion takes in its appearance in political modernity.
I particularly want to stress this for two reasons. First, and less important, because it may seem that just because the entire Hegelian argument of these last two sections is based on a subject’s capacity to be redirected in her values by incoming considerations in one’s historical future, those considerations can’t turn on elements of one’s past thinking and traditions. But that would be an elementary fallacy. It is a childish non sequitur to think that considerations that cause one to change one’s mind in the
future cannot contain elements in one’s
past traditions. But the more important reason to stress it is that such a reliance (as I have been stressing in the last page or two) on the conceptual vernacular in the providing of internal reasons necessarily generates elaborately empathetic attitudes of engagement with the traditions and mentalities of those one opposes. If the implementation of a doctrine such as (S) is theoretically elaborated along these lines, it cannot possibly be faulted for failing to have relevance in a context in which we have gone “beyond toleration” to multiculturalism. Being based on a specific form of humanism, (S) admittedly does eschew indifference toward those it opposes, but what it replaces it with—in the sort of detailed engagement that I have been trying to convey—equally takes it decisively beyond the chronic assumption of disapproval that has made the idiom of toleration come to seem so off-beam in the pluralist contexts of multiculturalist modernity.
NOTES