10 
Ontology II: From World–Brain Relation to Consciousness

Introduction

General Background—Ontology of Consciousness

I have characterized the brain’s existence and reality as world–brain relation. This is compatible with structural realism and, more specifically, ontic structural realism (OSR; chapter 9). Rather than presupposing basic elements such as physical or mental properties, OSR presupposes relation and structure as basic units of existence and reality. The brain can thus ontologically be defined by relation as in world–brain relation and structure specified as spatiotemporal structure.

That very same spatiotemporal structure is characterized as space-time relation with relational time and space as distinguished from space-time points as in observational time and space (chapter 9). How such determination of the brain in terms of world–brain relation and space-time relation can account for the ontological characterization of consciousness (and mental features in general) remains unclear, however.

The empirical findings on consciousness suggest a spatiotemporal model (chapters 7 and 8). The spatiotemporal model characterizes consciousness by spatiotemporal mechanisms such as spatiotemporal expansion and nestedness (chapter 7) as well as spatiotemporal alignment to body and world (chapter 8). These spatiotemporal mechanisms concern the constitution of time and space by the brain itself, that is, its “intrinsic” time and space (chapter 7), as well as their relation to the world’s time and space (chapter 8). Ontologically, such construction of time and space amounts to what I described as relational time and space (chapter 9). Presupposing such relational time and space allows me now to go beyond the empirical to the ontological frame and, more specifically, to investigate the question of the basic existence and reality of consciousness, that is, mental features.

Aim and Argument—Spatiotemporal Model of Consciousness

The main aim in this chapter is to suggest a spatiotemporal model of consciousness on the ontological level. Note that I am mainly concerned with the phenomenal features of consciousness as distinguished from neuronal features (while I leave aside cognitive and rational features of consciousness; chapter 7). My main argument is that the world–brain relation as defined in terms of OSR can ontologically account for consciousness (see the Introduction in chapter 9 for my understanding of ontology). Specifically, I will argue that the world–brain relation can be considered a necessary nonsufficient ontological condition of possible consciousness, an ontological predisposition of consciousness (OPC), as I say.

I will first introduce and sketch the spatiotemporal model of consciousness—this is the focus in the first part (part I). The second part (part II) focuses on the core problem, the quest for a necessary (a posteriori) ontological connection between brain and consciousness, the contingency problem, as I describe it. I argue that the assumption of world–brain relation as OPC renders it possible to conceive the relationship between brain and consciousness in a necessary (a posteriori) rather than contingent way: as world–brain relation provides the necessary ontological condition of possible consciousness (i.e., OPC), the brain, as ontologically defined by world–brain relation, is also necessarily (rather than contingently) connected to consciousness (part II).

Importantly, the brain alone, that is, independent of its relation to the world as defined in element-based ontology (chapter 9), does not have a necessary but only contingent connection to consciousness. This makes it possible to disentangle the concepts of consciousness and mind: we no longer need the concept of mind to account for the necessary connection between consciousness (i.e., phenomenal features) and brain (i.e., world–brain relation) as the underlying ontological basis. We can establish a necessary (a posteriori) connection of consciousness and its phenomenal features to the brain (through world–brain relation), which makes the concept of mind superfluous. I therefore conclude that, ontologically, world–brain relation can take on the role of the concept of mind in our search for the existence and reality of consciousness. Therefore, I suggest that what I call the world–brain problem can replace the mind–body problem (part III).

Part I: Ontology of Consciousness—Spatiotemporal Model

Spatiotemporal Model Ia: Spatiotemporal Mechanisms—Spatiotemporal Structure

I characterized consciousness by a spatiotemporal model that is empirically based on different spatiotemporal mechanisms (chapters 7 and 8). These included spatiotemporal expansion, nestedness, and alignment. Despite empirical differences, they all share their essentially spatiotemporal nature, that is, they reflect distinct ways of how the brain itself constructs its own time and space, that is, intrinsic time and space.

Spatiotemporal expansion allows for extending the specific space-time points or events of single stimuli (or contents) beyond themselves to a larger spatiotemporal scale while spatiotemporal nestedness entails the integration of the stimuli/contents’ smaller spatiotemporal scale within the larger range of the brain’s spontaneous activity (chapter 7). Finally, spatiotemporal alignment concerns the linkage or coupling of the brain’s smaller spatiotemporal scale to and within the world’s overall spatiotemporal range (chapter 8).

Taken altogether, the spatiotemporal mechanisms underlying consciousness share the integration of different spatiotemporal scales or ranges. Consciousness, as we have seen, is about such spatiotemporal integration: its phenomenal features are based on integrating different spatiotemporal scales from brain, body, and world by and within the brain’s neural activity (chapters 7–8).

The central relevance of spatiotemporal integration for consciousness is further supported by findings about disorders of consciousness and psychiatric disorders. Disorders of consciousness leading to loss of consciousness such as sleep, anesthesia, or vegetative state show loss of spatiotemporal integration in the brain’s neural activity (chapters 4, 5, and 7). Moreover, abnormal spatiotemporal integration also characterizes psychiatric disorders such as schizophrenia or depression (chapters 2 and 3). That spatiotemporal abnormalities in the brain result in abnormal mental features, that is, loss of consciousness (as in disorders of consciousness) or abnormal consciousness (as in psychiatric disorders), illustrates the central relevance of spatiotemporal integration for consciousness.

What does spatiotemporal integration imply for the ontological characterization of consciousness? Spatiotemporal integration allows for constituting spatiotemporal structure. The spatiotemporal model of consciousness, as developed in chapters 7 and 8, emphasized the central relevance of spatiotemporal structure for consciousness in an empirical sense. Specifically, spatiotemporal structure describes here the relation and organization between the various temporal and spatial features of the brain’s spontaneous activity (as measured in scale-free activity, cross-frequency coupling, etc.; chapters 7 and 8).

Spatiotemporal Model Ib: Spatiotemporal Structure—Ontological Features

How can we now transition from the empirical to the ontological level and raise the question of the ontological determination of consciousness? For that, we need to conceive the concept of spatiotemporal structure in an ontological rather than empirical sense. I already prepared such ontological ground in the last chapter (chapter 9) when conceiving the brain’s existence and reality. Summarizing that account, I determine the concept of spatiotemporal structure by four ontological features:

  1. (i) Relation as distinguished from elements. Spatiotemporal structure can ontologically be determined by relation. Relations are conceived here as the basic units of existence and reality without any prior and more basic underlying primary ontological features—this amounts to OSR. This distinguishes the ontological notion of relation from that of elements such as physical or mental properties or substances. Even if such element-based ontology considers relation, it only considers it in a secondary sense as the relation between primary and independently existent elements or properties including mental or physical properties. In addition, relation-based ontology must also be distinguished from other forms of ontology such as process- and capacity-based ontology (chapter 9).
  2. (ii) Organization as distinguished from collection. Spatiotemporal structure can ontologically be characterized by organization of relation. The organization of relation describes the coupling and linkage between different relations which, most notably, are established in a systematic way. Importantly, organization is spatiotemporal in that it allows for linking and coupling different space-time relations. Such spatiotemporal organization of relation must be distinguished ontologically from mere collections of elements or collections of processes that are usually conceived as only secondary and nonsystematic (chapter 9).
  3. (iii) Difference as distinguished from unity. Spatiotemporal structure is based on difference rather than unity. Specifically, following Floridi (2008), differences de re (chapter 9) can be taken to be the basic unit of existence and reality of spatiotemporal structure. Taken in such an ontological sense, differences de re must be distinguished from their empirical counterpart, that is, differences per se, as they are, for instance, manifest in the brain’s difference-based coding (chapters 1, 2, and 9).
  4. (iv) Space-time relation as distinguished from space-time points or events. Spatiotemporal structure is defined by space-time relations that feature relational time and space (chapter 9)—they must be distinguished from our perception and cognition of time and space in terms of space-time points or events as in observational time and space (chapter 9). Hence, space-time relation as well as relational time and space can be considered truly ontological, whereas space-time points or events, including observational time and space, remain empirical (and/or epistemic at best) (but not ontological).

Spatiotemporal Model IIa: Ontology of Consciousness—Relation and Organization

I suppose that spatiotemporal structure in such ontological sense can also account for the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features in general. The spatiotemporal model of consciousness as developed so far in a purely empirical sense (chapters 7 and 8) is now extended to the ontological level. Consciousness is not only spatiotemporal in an empirical sense, as supported by the empirical data, but also intrinsically spatiotemporal in an ontological sense.

Put briefly, the existence and reality of consciousness, that is, of its phenomenal features, are spatiotemporal and structural and therefore entail OSR. Specifically, the existence and reality of consciousness can be defined by relational time and space with spatiotemporal structure as it spans between world and brain and defines their relation (i.e., world–brain relation). This shall be explicated as follows:

  1. (i) Consciousness is relational. The existence and reality of consciousness can be determined by relations. These relations are neither physical nor mental but spatiotemporal, consisting in space-time relation. Importantly, such a relational view of consciousness must be distinguished from any kind of property-based ontology that assumes mental, physical, or neutral properties to underlie consciousness. The traditional ontological alternative between monism versus dualism that is based on the question of the relationship between mental and physical properties must consequently be discarded (chapter 9). Additionally, any substance-based ontology of consciousness as well as other ontologies such as process ontology (as in Whitehead, 1929/1978; see also Northoff, 2016a,b) or capacity-based ontology (chapters 5 and 9; Cartwright, 1989; McDowell, 1994) of consciousness must be replaced by the assumption of the relational nature of consciousness.
  2. The relational claim considers relation in such ontological sense a necessary condition of possible consciousness (i.e., an OPC; see below for details on the concept of OPC). Hence, the absence of relation in such ontological sense entails the absence of consciousness. For instance, element-based ontology remains incompatible with consciousness. If there were indeed elements or properties defining the basic units of existence and reality as when assuming mental or physical properties, consciousness would nevertheless remain impossible and thus absent—the OPC would simply be no longer given.
  3. (ii) Consciousness consists in organization. The existence and reality of consciousness consist in complex organization of relation, that is, the linkage and coupling between different space-time relations such as those of the existence and realities of world and brain (chapter 9). The notion of organization taken in such ontological sense bears some resemblance to the notion of synthesis as used by Kant (1781/1998) and Cassirer (1944); future investigation may detail such resemblance further.

The absence of organization may consequently entail the absence of consciousness. If, for instance, there is no linkage and coupling between the different space-time relations between the existences and realities of world, body, and brain, consciousness remains absent. Hence, mere addition or collection of world, body, and brain is not compatible with the presence of consciousness. Accordingly, without the spatiotemporal ontological organization of world, body, and brain in terms of spatiotemporal structure, consciousness and its phenomenal features cannot come into existence and reality.

Spatiotemporal Model IIb: Ontology of Consciousness—Difference and Relational Time and Space

What are the basic ontological building blocks of consciousness? This leads us back to the question of the most basic units of existence and reality that first and foremost make possible consciousness. Based on prior chapters, I determine difference, that is, difference de re, and relational time and space as the most basic ontological building blocks of consciousness:

  1. (iii) Consciousness is ontologically based on difference, that is, difference de re. (See also Northoff, 2014b, for details.) Difference is understood here in an ontological sense, that is, difference de re, rather than empirically, that is, difference per se. Difference de re constitutes consciousness that therefore is difference based in an ontological sense, which, empirically, is manifest in difference-based coding (chapters 1 and 2; Northoff, 2014a) and thus in what is conceptually described as difference per se (chapter 9).

The claim of the difference-based existence and reality of consciousness contrasts with the traditional claim of unity as being the most basic and fundamental ground of consciousness. The assumption of the unity-based nature of consciousness has a long philosophical history that can be traced at least to Descartes and Kant and is still prevalent today (see Bayne, 2010; Searle, 2004). My claim of the difference-based rather than unity-based nature of consciousness breaks with that tradition which, philosophically, converges with European-continental philosophers such as Heidegger and Deleuze.

However, the notion of difference, that is, difference de re, as used here, is closely related to the concept of relation as understood in OSR. Both relation and difference de re can be used interchangeably on a purely conceptual level, whereas ontologically, one may consider difference de re as an ontological construction feature by means of which relation is established (i.e., constructed).

  1. (iv) Consciousness is ontologically characterized by relational time and space. The existence and reality of consciousness consist in the space-time relation that characterizes relational time and space (chapter 9). Taken in such sense, consciousness cannot be characterized by space-time points or events as a hallmark of observational time and space. This excludes any ontological characterization of consciousness by specific physical or mental properties as well as a merely empirical determination: since physical or mental properties presuppose space-time points or events, consciousness would remain impossible in either of these cases.

The spatiotemporal characterization of consciousness by relational time and space makes it possible to account for its phenomenal features on the basis of spatiotemporal relation and structure. Phenomenal features can then ontologically be characterized by specific forms of spatiotemporal organization and configuration and their relation to the spatiotemporal features of world–brain relation while empirically one can then develop what I described earlier as neurophenomenal hypotheses (Northoff, 2014b, 2015).

Note that such spatiotemporal account of consciousness and its phenomenal features must be sharply distinguished from the reductive and eliminative account of consciousness in current neurophilosophy (Bickle, 2003; Churchland, 2002, 2012; Mandik, 2006). As consciousness (and mental features) are here conceived in merely empirical terms, they are characterized by what I describe as observational time and space (chapter 9). This, in turn, makes it possible to eliminate consciousness and mental features altogether in favor of the brain, which, ontologically, leads to eliminative materialism (Churchland, 1988). Such elimination of consciousness and mental features stands square to the present approach. I do not aim to eliminate mental features but only trace them back to world–brain relation as their ontological predisposition (rather than as an ontological correlate; see chapter 13 for a more detailed discussion of eliminative materialism).

Spatiotemporal Model IIc: Ontology of Consciousness—Mind versus World–Brain Relation and Internalism versus Externalism

  1. (v) The determination of consciousness by relational time and space also stands square to the traditional aspatial and atemporal characterization of consciousness when it is associated with the possible existence and reality of mind (see chapter 13 for a more detailed discussion of the concept of mind). The present account considers consciousness and its phenomenal features as intrinsically spatiotemporal, that is, in terms of relational time and space (Northoff, 2014b for details of spatiotemporal approach to phenomenal features); this excludes its aspatial and atemporal determination: without space and time, that is, relational time and space, consciousness, that is, its phenomenal features, would remain impossible.

Note that the present characterization of consciousness in terms of world–brain relation renders superfluous the concept of mind. We simply no longer need or require the concept of (the possible existence and reality of) mind and its aspatial and atemporal features to account for the existence and reality of consciousness as the latter can now be traced to world–brain relation and its relational time and space.

Therefore, I suggest disentangling consciousness, that is, its phenomenal features and, more generally, mental features, from the concept of mind as such. We can address the question of the existence and reality of mental features independent of and without presupposing the possible existence and reality of mind; that, in turn, renders impossible the subsequent question of the mind’s relationship with the body, that is, the mind–body problem, which then can be replaced by the world–brain problem (see chapter 13 for details).

  1. (vi) The existence and reality of consciousness are based on the existence and reality of the world and its relation to one of its part, that is, the brain, as in our human case. This suggests some form of externalism of consciousness, that is, the necessary reference of consciousness (and mental features in general) to the world. However, externalism in the present context is relational and ontological as it is based on world–brain relation and OSR. Such relational and ontological externalism must be distinguished from the more empirical biological externalism (which, ontologically, is more property- rather than relation-based) as it is, for instance, claimed for by Millikan (1984), Tye (2009), and Dretske (1995). At the same time, the present approach also defies internalism (in the usual sense) of consciousness as the latter necessarily requires relation to the world (i.e., world–brain relation) as OPC.

More generally, the ontological characterization of consciousness (and mental features in general) in terms of world–brain relation complements and traces the distinction between internalism and externalism of consciousness and its contents to a more basic and fundamental level, that is, the level of relation and structure (as in OSR): contents are no longer conceived as either internal or external but are traced to the more fundamental level of relation and its spatiotemporal features (see also chapter 6 for discussion of the role of contents in consciousness).

Part II: Ontology of Consciousness—Contingency Problem, or Necessary Ontological Connection between Brain and Consciousness

Contingency Problem Ia: Internal Relation—Double Necessary Ontological Connection

How can the world–brain relation account for the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features? To address that question, we need to investigate, first, the relationship between world and brain (i.e., world–brain relation) and, second, the relation of world–brain relation to consciousness and mental features.

Let me start with the relationship between world and brain. For that, I turn to Thomas Nagel and the example of H2O and water. Nagel says that we must investigate the behavior of molecules, including the “geometry of their spatiotemporal structure,” to understand how the microlevel with the different molecules of H2O as parts entails water on the macrolevel as whole. H2O is defined by molecules, that is, H and O, that show an “internal relation” (Nagel, 2000, p. 14) and therefore are necessarily (a posteriori) connected with each other. That internal relation, in turn, makes possible the internal relation of H2O to water, that is, their necessary (a posteriori) connection with upward entailment of water by H2O (see below for details on the concept of upward entailment).

I now argue that world and brain are necessarily (a posteriori) connected to each other as well as to consciousness in a way that is more or less analogous to the relationship between H2O and water. In the same way that H and O as molecules are internally related to each other, that is, necessary (a posteriori), world and brain show a necessary and thus internal relation with each other—this is what I describe as world–brain relation. Moreover, as H2O is necessarily connected to water, world–brain relation is necessarily (a posteriori) connected to consciousness and mental features.

We have to be careful though. The analogy between H2O–water and world–brain relation can be understood only in a figurative rather than a literal way. That is because there is spatiotemporal discrepancy. H2O shows a much smaller spatiotemporal scale or range than water—upward spatiotemporal entailment and a necessary connection operate here thus from a smaller (i.e., H2O) to a larger (i.e., water) spatiotemporal scale. The spatiotemporal scale is different in the case of world–brain relation though as, unlike H2O, it does not operate on a molecular level and its small spatiotemporal scale. However, one may argue that consciousness and its phenomenal features “go beyond” the brain in spatiotemporal terms (chapters 7 and 8); this puts consciousness on a somewhat analogous spatiotemporal footing as water that also goes beyond H2O on spatiotemporal grounds.

Let me make the analogy more explicit. What Nagel describes as the geometry of their spatiotemporal structure on the microlevel of H2O may correspond in our case to world–brain relation and its spatiotemporal structure as constituted on the basis of relational time and space—the world–brain relation may thus be characterized by “geometry of spatiotemporal structure between world and brain.” As in the case of the relation between H and O, this makes possible “internal relation” between world and brain. That internal relation is intrinsically spatiotemporal as it is based on space-time relation with relational time and space (chapter 9), which entails a necessary rather than contingent relation between world and brain. In short, the relation in world–brain relation is necessary rather than contingent.

The necessary world–brain relation, in turn, makes possible necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness as will be explicated in the third part in this chapter. Without the necessary connection between world and brain, the brain could not be connected necessarily to consciousness. That is more or less analogous to the fact that the internal relation between H and O makes possible the necessary connection between H2O and water: without the necessary connection between H and O, neither H alone nor O alone could be necessarily connected to water.

In sum, I propose a twofold necessary ontological connection. The first necessary ontological connection is between world and brain, resulting in world–brain relation, while the second necessary ontological connection consists in the necessary ontological connection of the world–brain relation, including brain and consciousness. Taken both together, the necessary world–brain relation is an ontological predisposition for the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness.

Contingency Problem Ib: External versus Internal Relation—Causal versus Constitutive Relation

How can we describe the necessary connection between world and brain, that is, their internal relation, in more detail? The traditional philosopher may now want to argue that these are causal relationships: the world causes the brain, which, in turn, causes consciousness. Without being able to go into full detail about, especially, the concept of causality, I here briefly indicate that this does not hold; I reject the characterization of the internal relations as causal relations—internal relations are noncausal and constitutive.

Causal relation presupposes an external relation where world and brain can be distinguished and separated from each other, which, in turn, allows them to link in a causal way. That is not the case in the internal relation of world–brain relation though. Here, world and brain are related to each other by default, implying that they cannot be clearly distinguished and separated from each other on ontological and ultimately also on empirical (chapter 8) grounds. Analogously, H and O cannot be distinguished and separated from each other within H2O—to consider them in terms of an external or causal relation within H2O would simply be nonsensical as it would make H2O impossible.

Accordingly, to characterize the internal relation between world and brain (i.e., world–brain relation), as well as the internal relation between brain (i.e., world–brain relation) and consciousness as causal relation is to confuse internal relation and external relation and consequently necessary and contingent connection. Instead, we may want to characterize the internal relation of world–brain relation as constitutive rather than causal: the relation between world and brain constitutes the existence and reality of the brain in a relational and, more specifically, in difference, that is, difference de re (chapter 9), to the world. However, future investigation is needed to characterize such constitutive rather than causal relation in more detail.

Contingency Problem IIa: Brain and Consciousness—Necessary versus Contingent Connection

I am now ready to address the second step, the relationship between world–brain relation and consciousness. I will argue that the world–brain relation is a necessary ontological condition of possible consciousness (i.e., an OPC). How can the ontological connection between world–brain relation and consciousness be necessary rather than contingent? For that, I turn to a paper by Thomas Nagel (2000). Note that I will mainly focus on discussing the necessary versus contingent connection between brain and consciousness. In contrast, I will leave out the discussion of the a priori versus a posteriori nature of the necessary connection—I will simply follow Nagel (who, in turn, bases his account on Kripke, 1972) when assuming a necessary a posteriori connection between brain and consciousness.

Nagel argues that a solution to the mind–body problem must address and challenge the problem of the contingent connection between brain and consciousness: “It appears at first blush that we have a clear and distinct enough grasp on both phenomenological consciousness and physical brain processes to see that there can be no necessary connection between them” (Nagel, 2000, pp. 3–4). Following Kripke, Nagel states that we need to draw a necessary connection between brain and consciousness, that is, a necessary connection between mental and physical processes, to address and ultimately solve the mind–body problem. This necessary connection between mental and physical processes will be the focus in the remainder of this chapter.

How can we conceive or take into view the potentially necessary connection between brain and consciousness? We observe the brain and its neural activities in the brain scanner. We observe various changes in the brain’s neural activity, but none of that tells us anything about consciousness—the brain’s neural activity, as we observe it, does not entail consciousness. Hence, we cannot observe consciousness in the brain and do therefore remain unable to draw any necessary connection between them—the relation between brain and consciousness remains opaque and thus contingent.

Despite all their empirical progress, the various neuroscientific theories of consciousness such as global neuronal workspace theory and integrated information theory (chapters 5 and 7) cannot overcome the problem of contingency between brain and consciousness. We are thus confronted with the problem of contingency between brain and consciousness—the contingency problem. The contingency problem is a conceptual–logical problem that concerns the nature of connection between brain and consciousness that can be either contingent or necessary. As such, the contingency problem is prevalent in both the empirical domain of neuroscience and the ontological domain of philosophy (see figure 10.1).

11046_010_fig_001.jpg

Figure 10.1 Contingency problem of connection between brain and consciousness.

Contingency Problem IIb: Introduction of Mind—Mind–Body Problem

How can we resolve the contingency problem? One way to address the contingency problem is to claim that there just is a necessary connection between brain and consciousness, as posited by identity theory (see Searle, 2004, for an overview). However, the necessity of such a connection between brain and consciousness remains rather intuitive and hence problematic. To escape these problems, one may want to simply eliminate mental features on an ontological level, which renders superfluous and eliminates the contingency problem—this is the strategy suggested in eliminative materialism (Churchland, 1998). However, as with identity theory, such eliminative materialism remains at best intuitive and raises several problems by itself (see chapter 13 for extensive discussion). Therefore, without going into detail, both identity theory and eliminative materialism have to be discarded as feasible candidate answers to the contingency problem.

We may thus revert to the traditional way to address the contingency problem. We may want to go beyond brain/body themselves and introduce the concept of mind. Instead of the brain, the concept of mind can address the contingency problem: by its very definition as mind, the concept of mind shows a necessary rather than contingent connection to mental features such as consciousness, that is, the mind, unlike the brain, entails by default mental features in a necessary (a priori) way (see chapter 13 for more details on the concept of mind). The contingency problem between brain and consciousness is thus resolved by introducing the mind and its necessary a priori connection with consciousness (see figure 10.2).

11046_010_fig_002.jpg

Figure 10.2 Contingency problem—necessary connection between mind and consciousness.

Nothing is free, though. The introduction of the possible existence and reality of mind raises yet another question, namely, that of the mind’s ontological relationship to the actual existence and reality of the body, including the brain, that is, the mind–body problem. Accordingly, the introduction of the concept of mind as an ontological (or metaphysical) basis of consciousness turns out to be a Pyrrhic victory. One solves one problem by introducing another one: it solves the contingency problem of a necessary connection between brain and consciousness by linking the latter to the mind, which introduces the mind–body problem.

How can we deal with this situation? One way is that one can now pursue the mind–body problem and discuss different solutions as is done in philosophy of mind. That, as I claim, cannot resolve its original birth defect though, namely, the shift from brain to mind for taking into view a necessary connection to consciousness. Alternatively, one may go back to brain and consciousness themselves and investigate how we can conceive their necessary connection in a way that is different from both identity theory and eliminative materialism (and related solutions)—that shall be the focus in the following.

Note that the concept of mind, as understood here, is not considered identical to or synonymous with the concept of consciousness or mental features. While both mind and mental features are necessarily and a priori connected with each other, that does nevertheless not entail that we cannot consider them separately and thus dissociate mental features from the concept of mind. That is, for instance, possible by showing a necessary connection of mental features to a concept that is different from that of mind—this is exactly the strategy I will pursue here.

Contingency Problem IIIa: Brain and Consciousness—Upward Spatiotemporal Entailment

Why is it so difficult to draw a necessary connection between brain and consciousness? Nagel, relying on Kripke, compares the relationship between brain and consciousness to that between H2O and water. We can draw a necessary connection between H2O and water while, because of their spatiotemporal differences, we remain unable to do so in the case of brain and consciousness. There is no upward entailment of consciousness by the brain as there is of water by H2O.

Let us cite a quote by Nagel (2000):

But to reach this conclusion, we must see that the behavior of H2O provides a true and complete account, with nothing left—an approximate entailment—of the features that are conceptually essential to water, and that this account is in fact true of the water around us. It is this “upward entailment” that is so difficult to imagine in the case of the corresponding psychophysical hypothesis, and that is the nub of the mind-body problem. We understand the entailment of the liquidity of water by the behavior of molecules through geometry, or more simply micro-macro or part-whole relation. Something analogous is true of every physical reduction even though the spatiotemporal framework can be very complicated and hard to grasp intuitively. But nothing like this will help us with the mind–body case, because we are not dealing here merely with larger and smaller grids. We are dealing with a gap of a totally different kind, between the objective spatiotemporal order of the physical world and the subjective phenomenological order of experience. And here it seems clear in advance that no amount of physical information about the spatiotemporal order will entail anything of a subjective phenomenological character. (p. 13; emphasis added)

Why is there a lack of upward entailment? Nagel argues that the objective spatiotemporal order of the physical world and the subjective phenomenological order of experience are different in principle when it comes to spatiotemporal features: the former is objective and spatiotemporal while the latter is subjective and phenomenological and thus nonspatiotemporal (if not aspatiotemporal; see above). This principal difference precludes their necessary connection, that is, the brain by default, cannot entail anything about consciousness, which renders their connection contingent rather than necessary.

Nagel formulates it very clearly. We can conceive upward entailment between H2O and water while that remains impossible in the case of brain and consciousness. He argues that the objective spatiotemporal order of the physical world is in principle different from and does not entail the subjective phenomenal order of experience. I will argue that he is right and wrong at the same time.

Nagel is right in that our current definition of time and space in general, which conceives the brain’s time and space in terms of the objective spatiotemporal order of the physical world, does indeed not allow us to consider upward entailment of consciousness by the brain. In contrast, Nagel is wrong in his assumption that both orders, that is, spatiotemporal and phenomenological, are mutually exclusive: once one presupposes a different concept of time and space, that is, relational rather than observational time and space, one can draw a necessary connection with upward entailment between brain and consciousness. I will argue that the lack of upward entailment between brain and consciousness is due to the way the brain is traditionally defined in ontological and, more specifically, spatiotemporal terms.

Contingency Problem IIIb: Ontological Redefinition of Brain—Structural Realism and Relational Time and Space

Traditionally, the brain is defined by physical properties as presupposed in element-based ontology (chapter 9). Such definition of the brain by physical properties goes hand in hand with its definition by space-time points or events as we can observe them—this amounts to the objective spatiotemporal order of the physical world Nagel refers to. Those very same space-time points or events define the brain (as well as the world) and its objective spatiotemporal order. Most important, they cannot be related to the space-time relation with relational time and space that characterize consciousness.

Unlike space-time points or events characterizing the supposed existence and reality of the brain (as part of the physical world), space-time relations as they signify consciousness cannot be observed. Because of their different spatiotemporal orders, that is, space-time points or events versus space-time relation, brain and consciousness cannot be connected to each other in a necessary way. Instead, brain and consciousness can spatiotemporally only be connected in a contingent way—the brain’s time and space (i.e., space-time points or events) do not entail consciousness (i.e., space-time relation) in an upward way in the way H2O entails water. Accordingly, lack of upward spatiotemporal entailment (as I say) of consciousness by the brain renders impossible their necessary connection.

However, that changes once one ontologically defines time and space of the brain in a different way. Now the brain’s existence and reality are no longer defined by physical properties with space-time points or events but rather by a relation with space-time that intrinsically relates the brain to the world (i.e., world–brain relation; chapter 12). Instead of presupposing element-based ontology with space-time points or events and observational time and space, one may rather define the brain by relation-based ontology, that is, OSR with world–brain relation and space-time relation with relational time and space.

Contingency Problem IIIc: Ontological Redefinition of Brain—Necessary Connection to Consciousness in Terms of Upward Spatiotemporal Entailment

How does such determination of the brain by world–brain relation change our view on the connection between brain and consciousness? The world–brain relation is featured by space-time relation rather than space-time points or events. That puts the world–brain relation on the same spatiotemporal and ultimately ontological ground as consciousness that, as in the spatiotemporal model outlined above, can also be defined by space-time relation. If so, the world–brain relation entails consciousness in an upward way in the same way H2O entails water—one can thus speak of upward spatiotemporal entailment. Upward spatiotemporal entailment implies that world–brain relation is necessarily (a posteriori) connected to consciousness.

So far, I have only demonstrated a necessary (a posteriori) connection between world–brain relation and consciousness. In contrast, I left open a necessary connection between brain and consciousness. That is easy though. As the brain is ontologically defined by world–brain relation (chapter 9), the latter’s necessary connection to consciousness implies a necessary connection of the brain to consciousness. We must thus presuppose relational, and, more specifically, ontic structural realist, determination of the brain to conceive its necessary connection to consciousness. If, in contrast, one presupposes element-based ontology with ontological determination of the brain by either physical or mental properties, the necessary relation of the brain to the world (i.e., world–brain relation) will no longer be conceivable; that, in turn, renders it impossible to take into view a necessary connection between brain and consciousness, which then remains contingent by default (see figure 10.3).

11046_010_fig_003.jpg

Figure 10.3 Contingency problem—necessary connection between brain and consciousness.

In sum, the contingency problem of a necessary connection between brain and consciousness can be resolved without reverting to the concept of mind. This is possible by presupposing a different ontological determination of brain, that is, relation-based rather than element-based ontology, and a different concept of time and space, that is, relational rather than observational time and space (which distinguishes my approach from both identity theory and eliminative materialism and related theories). The ontological determination of brain in terms of both relation-based ontology and relational time and space makes it possible to conceive its necessary rather than contingent connection to consciousness: consciousness and its relational time and space are entailed by the brain’s relational time and space, including their relation to the world’s time and space—this amounts to upward spatiotemporal entailment between brain and consciousness.

Such an ontological redefinition of the brain fits well with Nagel, who argues in exactly this way, namely that we need to shift our conceptual (or ontological) definitions in order to account for the necessary (a posteriori) connection between two concepts (such as brain and consciousness) that otherwise seem to be merely contingently (a posteriori) connected:

The greatest scientific progress occurs through conceptual change which permits empirically observed order that initially appears contingent (a posteriori) to be understood at a deeper level as necessary (a posteriori), in the sense of being entailed by the true nature of the phenomena. (Nagel, 2000, p. 22)

Contingency Problem IVa: Criteria of Necessity—Spatiotemporal Fit into the World

What are the criteria that must be met and fulfilled for that connection to be necessary? For that, I turn again to Nagel, who touches on the question of such criteria for the necessary (rather than contingent) character of the ontological (rather than merely empirical) connection between mental features and their potential ontological origin, that is, ontic origin. I will focus on three such criteria: spatiotemporal fit into the world, transparency through world–brain relation, and spatiotemporal subjectivity.

The first criterion consists in what I call spatiotemporal fit into the world. I discuss how the existence and reality of world can be characterized by space and time (chapters 9 and 11). At the same time, we are part of that very same world and its spatiotemporal features—I demonstrated that that becomes possible by means of our brain: our brain relates us to the world (i.e., world–brain relation) by means of which we become part of that very same world.

How is it possible for the world–brain relation to integrate us into the world such that we become part of the wider world? Since the world is by itself spatiotemporal, the world–brain relation must allow for linking and integrating the brain within the world’s time and space, that is, its relational time and space (chapter 9). The brain must thus relate to the world’s relational time and space in a spatiotemporal way by establishing spatiotemporal relation with the world—the world–brain relation is intrinsically spatiotemporal, that is, it is defined by its spatiotemporal features without which it would not exist.

The world–brain relation integrates us into the world by spatializing and temporalizing us and our existence as part of the wider spatiotemporal scale of the world. Taken in this sense, the brain and its relation to the world (i.e., world–brain relation) can be taken as marker of our fit into the world, a spatiotemporal fit into the world, as I say. Such spatiotemporal fit into the world comes close to what Nagel (2012) describes as “systematic understanding of how we and other living things fit into the world” (p. 128); this is also well expressed in the following quote:

The hope is not to discover a foundation that makes our knowledge unassailably secure but to find a way of understanding ourselves that is not radically self-undermining, and that does not require us to deny the obvious. The aim would be to offer a plausible picture of how we fit into the world. (Nagel, 2012, p. 25; emphasis added)

How does this spatiotemporal fit into the world establish a necessary ontological connection between world–brain relation and consciousness? The world itself can ontologically be characterized by relational time and space (chapter 9), which also characterizes the brain and its relation to the world (i.e., world–brain relation). As the world–brain relation is a necessary OPC, consciousness itself must be characterized by relational time and space and thus “fit” spatiotemporally into the world. Spatiotemporal fit of consciousness into the world consequently entails a necessary connection between world–brain relation and consciousness—the former can thus be regarded as a criterion of the latter.

Contingency Problem IVb: Criteria of Necessity—Third Shared and Commonly Underlying Feature

The critic, however, may not want to relent yet. The spatiotemporal fit of consciousness into the world characterizes consciousness as spatiotemporal. However, the assumption of the spatiotemporal nature of consciousness conflicts with our preconception that mental features are aspatial and atemporal, which distinguishes them from physical features that are spatial and temporal (see chapter 13 for a more detailed discussion of this point).

The critic may thus want to argue that we lose the distinction of mental features from physical features by characterizing them in a spatiotemporal way. To escape the critic’s argument, we need to show how consciousness and mental features in general can be spatiotemporal rather than aspatial and atemporal without collapsing them into physical features. Importantly, that argument needs to concern specifically mental features themselves and must thus be separate from the argument for the spatiotemporal nature of world–brain relation as OPC.

How can we provide such argument for the spatiotemporal nature of mental features? When conceiving mental and physical features themselves, we cannot but state their essential difference in spatiotemporal terms. Physical features can be observed in time and space, entailing observational time and space (chapter 9). In contrast, mental features cannot be observed at all in time and space—consciousness can neither be observed in the brain nor elsewhere. Mental features show neither any spatial extension nor temporal duration—they are aspatial and atemporal. As spatiotemporal and aspatial/atemporal features are mutually exclusive, physical and mental features are not compatible with each other. This, in turn, makes it impossible to draw a necessary ontological connection between physical and mental features.

How can we establish a necessary ontological connection between physical and mental features? Because of spatiotemporal discrepancy between physical and mental features, claims of a necessary and direct connection between brain and consciousness as in identity theory and eliminative materialism (and related suggestions) remain at best intuitive. As a direct way seems to be impossible for spatiotemporal reasons (and others; see chapter 13), we may want to search for indirect ways. Nagel suggests exactly that. He proposes that we may want to seek some third feature that is shared between and thus commonly underlies both mental and physical features:

What will be the point of view, so to speak, of such theory? If we could arrive at it, it would render transparent the relation between mental and physical, not directly, but through the transparency of their common relation to something that is not merely either of them. (Nagel, 2000, p. 45; emphasis added)

I now postulate that the third shared and commonly underlying feature, as I describe it, consists in world–brain relation and its spatiotemporal features. Following Nagel, I now need to show that world–brain relation provides a common relation, that is, a necessary ontological connection, to both brain (as placeholder for what Nagel describes as “physical”) and consciousness (as placeholder for what Nagel describes as “mental”). That, in turn, renders transparent the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness, that is, the relation between mental and physical.

Contingency Problem IVc: Criteria of Necessity—Spatiotemporal Transparency through World–Brain Relation

I argue that world–brain relation is an ideal candidate to account for such third shared and commonly underlying feature in the sense of Nagel. Let me explicate that in the following.

I demonstrated that the brain is necessarily connected to world–brain relation (chapter 9). The existence and reality of brain are necessarily dependent upon its relation to the world—without world–brain relation, the brain simply does not exist and is not real. There is thus a necessary (a posteriori) ontological connection between brain and world–brain relation. Thereby, the emphasis is put on relation (as in world–brain relation), which precludes equivocation of the concept of brain as included in both “brain” and “world–brain relation.” The same holds with regard to consciousness and mental features. I showed in this chapter that mental features such as consciousness are necessarily dependent upon world–brain relation—the world–brain relation is an OPC.

The world–brain relation shows a necessary ontological connection with both brain and consciousness. This makes the world–brain relation an ideal ontological candidate for the third shared and commonly underlying feature (in the sense of Nagel) as it is shared between and commonly underlies both brain and consciousness. Following Nagel, this renders transparent the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness on spatiotemporal grounds: as both are based on world–brain relation, brain and consciousness share the former’s relational time and space, which renders transparent their necessary ontological connection within that very same relational time and space. I consequently claim that the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness, that is, between physical and mental features, becomes transparent by conceiving world–brain relation—I thus speak of the transparency of brain–consciousness connection through world–brain relation.

If, in contrast, one neglects world–brain relation (as in both identity theory and eliminative materialism), one can only apply observational time and space, which renders opaque the necessary ontological connection between brain and mental features on spatiotemporal grounds: the brain can now be determined only by observational time and space while mental features are then characterized as aspatial and atemporal in order to distinguish them from physical features and the brain. In that case, transparency is replaced by opacity of the relation between brain and consciousness—the transparency of brain–consciousness connection through world–brain relation is here replaced by opacity of brain–consciousness connection.

The critic may now want to argue that the claim of transparency of brain–consciousness connection through world–brain relation does indeed provide an answer to Nagel’s question. However, it does not provide an answer to the critic’s argument, that is, the spatiotemporal nature of mental features as distinct from physical features. That can be addressed easily though.

World–brain relation can be characterized by space and time and, more specifically, relational time and space as distinguished from observational time and space (see above and chapter 9). By being necessarily connected to world–brain relation, mental features are ontologically connected to relational time and space and must therefore be characterized in this way—mental features are spatiotemporal in terms of relational time and space. That distinguishes them from physical features that are characterized by observational time and space. For instance, the phenomenal features of consciousness such as qualia, intentionality, and so forth may then be determined by relational time and space (see Northoff, 2014b, for details).

We can now address the critic’s argument. We are well able to characterize mental features in spatiotemporal terms in such way that distinguishes them from both physical features and aspatial/atemporal features. Hence, the world–brain relation “renders transparent” not only the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness but also the spatiotemporal nature of mental features in terms of relational time and space—I therefore speak of spatiotemporal transparency through world–brain relation.

The critic neglects the possibility of such spatiotemporal transparency through world–brain relation. Therefore, both the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness as well as the spatiotemporal nature of mental features remain opaque to her or him and cannot be rendered transparent. According to Nagel (as implied by the first sentence of his quote), the critic simply applies the “wrong” point of view. What does the “right” point of view look like? That, as I suggest in later chapters, requires nothing less than a Copernican revolution in neuroscience and philosophy (chapters 12–14).

Part III: Ontology of Consciousness—World–Brain Problem

World–Brain Problem Ia: Subjectivity and Spatiotemporal Structure

The critic may not be satisfied yet though. The hardest nut to crack with regard to the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features is their subjectivity (Nagel, 1974; Searle, 2004). Mental features are intrinsically subjective, which distinguishes them from physical features that are nonsubjective and thus objective. How is it possible that something as subjective as consciousness or other mental features can occur in a world characterized by brains and bodies that are objective rather than subjective?

What does the quest for subjectivity imply for world–brain relation and its spatiotemporal features? If the world–brain relation serves as OPC, it must also provide the necessary condition of the subjective nature of consciousness and mental features in general. The spatiotemporal features of world–brain relation must thus predispose the subjective nature of consciousness. There must thus be an intrinsic linkage, that is, a necessary ontological connection between spatiotemporal and subjective features in world–brain relation.

The necessity of such intrinsic linkage between spatiotemporal and subjective features is well reflected in the following quote by Nagel (2000):

The right point of view would be one which, contrary to present conceptual possibilities, included both subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure from the outset, all its descriptions implying both these things at once, so that it could describe inner states and their functional relations to behavior and to one another from the phenomenological inside and the physiological outside simultaneously—not in parallel. (pp. 45–46; emphasis added)

Extending Nagel, I now argue that such intrinsic linkage, that is, a necessary ontological connection between subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure is included “from the outset” in the ontological concept of world–brain relation. My argument includes two steps. I first determine the concept of subjectivity in a novel way, that is, in spatiotemporal terms (in a brief way though without going into the myriads of literature on this topic). That, in turn, serves as a basis for the second step, that is, showing the necessary ontological connection between subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure within world–brain relation, including the necessary connection to mental features. Let me start with the first step, the determination of subjectivity.

World–Brain Problem Ib: Spatiotemporal Subjectivity versus Mental Subjectivity

We traditionally determine subjectivity in reference to mental features such as consciousness—everything that is mental is subjective as distinguished from that which is nonmental and thus objective rather than subjective. When determining the concept of subjectivity, we usually presuppose (most often in an implicit and tacit way) consciousness and mental features and, more generally, the mind as such as our reference, that is, as epistemic reference (see chapters 12–14 for more detailed determination of this concept). This renders subjectivity by default mental—I therefore speak of mental subjectivity. This, for instance, renders it rather paradoxical if not incoherent to determine something that is nonmental and observable like the brain as subjective. Hence, mental subjectivity is the wrong frame or epistemic reference to characterize the brain in a subjective way.

How about taking the world itself and its spatiotemporal features rather than mental features as the epistemic reference for determining the concept of subjectivity? In that case, we no longer reference subjectivity against mental features and the mind but, alternatively, compare and set it against the spatiotemporal framework of the world. For instance, when comparing the smaller spatiotemporal scale or range of both world–brain relation and brain against the much larger one of the world itself (i.e., independent of world–brain relation and brain), the former can be characterized as subjective when compared to the objective nature of the latter.

Subjectivity is here determined on spatiotemporal grounds, that is, in reference to the spatiotemporal scale or range of the world itself. Such spatiotemporal determination of subjectivity can be described as spatiotemporal subjectivity. The concept of spatiotemporal subjectivity determines subjectivity on purely spatiotemporal rather than mental grounds for which reason it must be distinguished from mental subjectivity. Specifically, spatiotemporal subjectivity is determined on the grounds of spatiotemporal discrepancy to the world that is objective (on spatiotemporal grounds) and therefore serves as an epistemic reference for determining spatiotemporal subjectivity.

The concept of spatiotemporal subjectivity fulfills Nagel’s requirement of a concept that “included both subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure from the outset, all its descriptions implying both these things at once.” Let me specify that in both directions, from space and time to subjectivity as well as from the latter to the former.

The concept of “spatiotemporal” in spatiotemporal subjectivity refers to relational time and space (chapter 9). As it is relational, relational time and space imply relation between world and its parts such as the brain (i.e., world–brain relation), which show different, that is, smaller, spatiotemporal scales or ranges than the world itself. Relational time and space thus imply what I described as spatiotemporal discrepancy. As spatiotemporal discrepancy defines spatiotemporal subjectivity, relational time and space and, more specifically, their “spatiotemporal structure” (to use Nagel’s term) cannot but include spatiotemporal subjectivity right from the outset.

What about the reverse, namely, that spatiotemporal subjectivity includes time and space, that is, spatiotemporal structure, from the outset? When setting and comparing subjectivity against mental features and mind as the epistemic reference, we cannot draw any necessary connection to spatiotemporal features. Since the mind is traditionally determined in an aspatial and atemporal way (see above and chapter 13), mental subjectivity is not conceived in spatiotemporal terms at all and therefore shows no necessary connection to spatiotemporal features.

That changes once one shifts the epistemic reference from mind to world though. As the world itself can be characterized by time and space, we can now set and compare subjectivity against the spatiotemporal features of the world, that is, relational time and space, including its respective spatiotemporal scale or range. That renders transparent the necessary connection between subjectivity, that is, spatiotemporal subjectivity, and time and space, that is, relational time and space. This, in turn, makes it possible that, unlike the concept of mental subjectivity, spatiotemporal subjectivity (as in its name) includes reference to time and space right “from the outset.”

World–Brain Problem Ic: Spatiotemporal Subjectivity as Necessary Condition of Mental Subjectivity

The critic may now want to argue that I showed very well the necessary connection between subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure as it is suggested by Nagel. In contrast, I have not shown that the necessary connection between subjectivity and spatiotemporal structure is related to both world–brain relation and mental features. This is the easy part, which leads me to the second part of my argument, the hard part.

World–brain relation is essentially spatiotemporal—it consists in the spatiotemporal relation between the world’s larger spatiotemporal range and the smaller one of the brain. That includes spatiotemporal discrepancy and therefore entails spatiotemporal subjectivity (see above). Hence, when compared to the world itself, that is, independent of its relation to the brain, world–brain relation cannot be but subjective (rather than objective) in a spatiotemporal sense. In short, world–brain relation entails and can therefore be characterized by spatiotemporal subjectivity.

How is the spatiotemporal subjectivity of world–brain relation related to mental features and their mental subjectivity? I showed that world–brain relation provides the necessary OPC which is possible on spatiotemporal grounds (see above). I now argue that world–brain relation can provide the OPC by means of the subjective nature of its spatiotemporal features (i.e., spatiotemporal subjectivity). Because its spatiotemporal features are subjective (in a spatiotemporal sense), the world–brain relation can predispose the mental subjectivity of consciousness and mental features.

World–Brain Problem Id: Self-Mediation between Spatiotemporal Subjectivity and Mental Subjectivity

Without providing a separate argument, I postulate that the relationship between spatiotemporal and mental subjectivity is mediated by the self: the self is intrinsically relational (as based on world–brain relation), spatiotemporal (as based on relational time and space), and subjective (as based on spatiotemporal subjectivity; see Northoff, 2016, 2017, for the concept of self in the realm of neuroscience). At the same time, the self is not necessarily mental, that is, conscious or experienced as such, while it enables consciousness—the self is thus preconscious or prephenomenal (or proto-conscious, as philosophers might want to say) rather than nonconscious or nonphenomenal (see Northoff, 2014b, for the concept of prephenomenal). This makes the self an ideal candidate to mediate between spatiotemporal and mental subjectivity by providing the bridge between the nonphenomenal world and the phenomenal consciousness of a specific subject with its mental subjectivity.

In sum, I postulate that the spatiotemporal subjectivity of world–brain relation is a necessary condition of its role as OPC, which, through mediation by the self, makes possible mental subjectivity. Put simply, spatiotemporal subjectivity of world–brain relation is an ontological predisposition of mental subjectivity. This makes it possible for world–brain relation to simultaneously (rather than in parallel) predispose “the phenomenological inside and the physiological outside” (as described by Nagel, 2000, quoted above) of mental features: both “phenomenological inside” and “physiological outside” can be traced to one and the same underlying spatiotemporal structure, that is, relational time and space, that features world–brain relation by spatiotemporal subjectivity.

Finally, note that the concept of spatiotemporal subjectivity is tied neither to a first-person perspective (FPP) nor to a second- or third-person perspective (SPP, TPP). True, mental subjectivity can be featured by FPP and physical objectivity by TPP. However, as it provides the basis for both, including their distinction, spatiotemporal subjectivity itself cannot be characterized by either FPP or TPP as it would be to confuse the necessary condition with what it conditions. Instead, spatiotemporal subjectivity as based on world–brain relation is by itself nonperspectival or preperspectival as it provides the necessary ontological condition of possible epistemic distinction between FPP and TPP.

This carries major reverberations for consciousness. As I characterize consciousness by spatiotemporal subjectivity, consciousness itself cannot be characterized by either FPP or TPP—FPP only provides the epistemic access to consciousness that ontologically remains nonperspectival (or preperspectival). Hence, to characterize consciousness by FPP (or TPP) is to confuse ontological (i.e., non- or preperspectival) and epistemic determination of consciousness (which I would, for instance, charge against the distinction between first- and third-person ontology as suggested by Searle, 2004).

World–Brain Problem IIa: Brain—Subjective or Objective?

The critic may now be inclined to argue that the ontological redefinition of the brain in terms of world–brain relation renders the brain subjective and conscious rather than objective and nonconscious. The only way for the brain to account for its necessary connection to consciousness is that the brain is by itself subjective and conscious. Otherwise, following Nagel, the brain could not bridge the gap between objective spatiotemporal order and subjective phenomenological order. However, the ontological characterization of the brain as subjective entails some sort of panpsychism, which ultimately would undermine my own approach in terms of OSR.

Such an ontological determination of the brain as subjective and conscious has indeed been assumed by some authors. These include the nineteenth-century philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer, who spoke of the brain as subjective (Schopenhauer, 1818–1819/1966), and more recently Colin McGinn (1991), who assumes specific mental properties in the brain. Finally, Nagel himself seems to tend in this direction when speaking of a “conscious brain” (Nagel, 1993, p. 6). The concept of a conscious brain is also somewhat entailed by John Searle (2004) in his concept of first-person ontology (as distinguished from third-person ontology), even though he does not explicitly characterize the brain itself as conscious or subjective (Searle, 2004): first-person ontology accounts for the FPP of consciousness (see chapter 8 for discussion of FPP vs. TPP with regard to consciousness) and its underlying neuronal mechanisms in the brain that thereby must be subjective and conscious (or at least pre- or proto-conscious).

I reject any such ontological definition of the brain as subjective and/or conscious (or as given by first-person perspective as related to first-person ontology). The ontological redefinition of the brain in terms of world–brain relation can be considered neither subjective nor objective. It pertains to neither the objective spatiotemporal order nor the subjective phenomenological order. That, as I argue, would be to confuse the world–brain relation as a necessary condition, that is, as an OPC, with what it conditions, that is, the brain as we observe it within the objective spatiotemporal order and its necessary connection to and upward spatiotemporal entailment of consciousness as featured by its subjective phenomenological order. Let me explain in more detail.

To regard the brain as either subjective and conscious or as objective and nonconscious is to simply confuse world–brain relation and brain on ontological grounds. The brain’s existence and reality can only be defined by its relation to the world, the world–brain relation (chapter 9). If one now conceives the brain by itself, that is, as separate and detached from the world (as when characterizing it as subjective and conscious), one replaces world–brain relation by what can ontologically be described as world–brain isolation. Such world–brain isolation is possible only by presupposing a particular conception of time and space though: the brain could then longer be defined by space-time relation with relational time and space but only by space-time points or events as in observational time and space.

World–Brain Problem IIb: Brain Paradox—Dissolution

The characterization of the brain in terms of world–brain isolation provides the necessary condition of the possible distinction between world and brain and their subsequent characterization as objective and subjective: the world is objective while the brain is subjective and as both are isolated from each other, there is no necessary connectivity between objective physical and subjective mental features. The isolation between world and brain thus entails the dissociation and segregation between objectivity and subjectivity including their determination as physical and mental.

Moreover, world–brain isolation provides the presupposition for the “brain paradox” (Northoff, 2004; Schopenhauer, 1818–1819/1966). In a nutshell, the brain paradox consists in the fact that one and the same brain cannot be objective (i.e., physical) and subjective (i.e., mental) at the same time. Because both determinations of the brain, that is, subjective/conscious and objective/nonconscious, are opposite and mutually exclusive, the connection between subjective/conscious and objective/nonconscious brain remains contingent by default. The mind–body problem thus resurfaces in what can be called the brain–brain problem, the problem of the relationship between subjective and objective brain.

We can avoid both the brain paradox and the brain–brain problem by shifting our ontological presuppositions. Instead of presupposing world–brain isolation as based on element- or property-based ontology (chapter 9), one can account for world–brain relation as based on OSR. The latter renders impossible any segregation between world and brain, including the brain paradox, while it makes possible the introduction of spatiotemporal subjectivity. The brain can then ontologically be characterized by spatiotemporal subjectivity as based on its spatiotemporal relation to the (spatiotemporally) objective world, the world–brain relation.

This undermines the paradoxical dichotomy between subjective/conscious and objective/physical brain by putting it into the larger spatiotemporal framework of world and world–brain relation. That, in turn, makes it possible to dissolve the brain paradox: the characterization of the brain as both subjective and objective is at best epistemic or even better empirical but not ontological anymore—the paradoxical nature of double determination of the brain is thus dissolved.

World–Brain Problem IIIa: World–Brain Relation—Ontological Predisposition of Consciousness

I demonstrated two necessary connections, the one between world and brain (i.e., world–brain relation), as well as the one between brain and consciousness through world–brain relation and its spatiotemporal subjectivity. Moreover, I argued that the second necessary connection, that is, the one between world–brain relation and consciousness, is based on the first one, that is, the necessary connection between world and brain in terms of world–brain relation. This was specifically reflected in the assumption that mental subjectivity is based on and presupposes spatiotemporal subjectivity.

This carries major implications for consciousness. Taken both necessary connections together, this amounts to the claim that the necessary (a posteriori) connection between world and brain (i.e., world–brain relation) is a necessary ontological condition of possible consciousness. Formulated in a converse way, without the necessary (a posteriori) connection between world and brain (i.e., the world–brain relation), consciousness remains altogether impossible. Therefore, world–brain relation is a necessary condition of possible consciousness, an OPC, as I say.

How can we describe the notion of ontological predisposition in more detail? The notion of predisposition in OPC refers to the necessary (rather than sufficient) ontological conditions of possible (rather than actual) consciousness (i.e., OPC). Conceived in this way, the concept of predisposition mirrors to a certain extent Kant’s concept of the transcendental as distinguished from the empirical. Following Kant (in in a loose sense), transcendental conditions (i) cannot be directly accessed, (ii) operate in the background and are, at the same time, (iii) indispensable. That holds well for the world–brain relation: (i) it cannot be accessed as such in a direct way but only indirectly, (ii) it remains in the background, and (iii) it is nevertheless indispensable for the existence and reality of consciousness. I consequently postulate that the world–brain relation is a necessary condition of possible consciousness (i.e., OPC) by means of which it takes on a transcendental role (in the sense of Kant) or, as I would say, a neurotranscendental role.

World–Brain Problem IIIb: World–Brain Relation as OPC—Panpsychism or Neutral Monism?

The critic may now want to argue that the introduction of world–brain relation as OPC implies panpsychism (Strawson, 2016) or, at least, proto-panpsychism (Chalmers, 1996). Briefly, the world–brain relation can only serve as OPC if the world can be characterized by the existence and reality of some kind of psychic elements or properties or, at least, psychic proto-properties. Otherwise, in the absence of such psychic properties in the world, the world–brain relation could not serve as OPC. I reject the assumption of panpsychism, however.

The advocate of panpsychism is certainly right that the world itself must show certain ontological features that make possible and ultimately necessary its relation to the brain, the world–brain relation. However, those ontological features do not need to be psychic or proto-psychic elements by themselves. That would mean to take something as a sufficient ontological condition of actual consciousness (i.e., ontological correlate of consciousness; OCC) that is only a necessary condition of possible consciousness (i.e., OPC). Instead, the world and its relation to the brain only need to provide those spatiotemporal features that predispose or make possible consciousness—neither the world nor world–brain relation are conscious by themselves. As we will see in the next chapter (chapter 11), in more detail, we can indeed ontologically define the world by spatiotemporal features that predispose consciousness.

Most importantly, these spatiotemporal features entail relational time and space, which goes hand in hand with relation-based ontology (chapter 9). Relation-based ontology stands square to the panpsychist or proto-psychic assumption of psychic or proto-psychic properties or elements. Therefore, the assumption of world–brain relation as OPC is not compatible with any form of panpsychism or proto-psychism. Instead, one may rather want to ontologically presuppose what I describe as spatiotemporalism of world and world–brain relation. Such spatiotemporalism can, ontologically, be considered as a necessary condition of possible consciousness (i.e., an OPC).

The assumption of world–brain relation as OPC bears some superficial similarity to yet another approach in the realm of possible mind–body relation, that is, neutral monism (NM). NM assumes that mind and body can ontologically be traced to some more basic and fundamental ontological existence and reality that are neutral, that is, they are neither mental nor physical by themselves. The proponent of NM may now be inclined to argue that my concept of world–brain relation can be considered a candidate for such neutral ontological basis: the world–brain relation provides the OPC while, at the same time, it is closely related to physical features.

The analogy to NM is only superficial though as there are some basic differences. First, the assumption of such neutral ontological basis in NM provides the answer to the question of how we can link mind and body. That is different in my case. The world–brain relation and its role as OPC provides the answer to the question of the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features. Hence, NM still presupposes the concept of mind whereas that is no longer the case in world–brain relation.

The difference in starting point, that is, presupposition versus nonpresupposition of mind, carries major implications. Because it still presupposes the (possible existence and reality of) mind, NM must provide a necessary relation of the neutral ontological basis to both mind and body. That is no longer necessary in my case. There is no need to provide a necessary connection of world–brain relation to the mind as the latter is simply no longer presupposed. Moreover, unlike in NM, the relationship to the body is already entailed in world–brain relation as the body is part of the world for the brain (chapter 8 for details). Taken together, this relieves the world–brain relation of establishing a necessary connection to both mind and body, which is one of the major puzzles in NM. Therefore, the similarity of my assumption of world–brain relation as OPC with NM is at best superficial with major differences becoming apparent once one compares both in more depth.

World–Brain Problem IVa: Mind–Body Problem versus World–Brain Problem

The ontological redefinition of the brain in terms of world–brain relation carries far-reaching implications for the concept of mind and subsequently the mind–body problem. We recall the concept of mind was introduced to address the question of the lacking necessary connection between brain/body and consciousness (or mental features in general). (See chapter 13.)

To establish a necessary connection of consciousness (and mental features in general) to its underlying ontological substrate, philosophers introduced the concept of mind: they assumed the possible existence and reality of mind that is connected necessarily and a priori to consciousness (and to mental features in general). However, that turned out to be a Pyrrhic victory. While solving one problem, that is, that of the necessary connection between body/brain and consciousness, another one was created, that is, that of the ontological relationship between mind and body, the mind–body problem.

I now argue that the concept of mind becomes superfluous for establishing a necessary connection to consciousness and mental features as this role can be taken over by world–brain relation. The world–brain relation is an OPC. As an OPC, the world–brain relation makes possible consciousness, implying that neither world alone nor the brain itself could account for a necessary connection to consciousness. Therefore, to understand the necessary (a posteriori) ontological connection between brain and consciousness, we need to go back to the relationship between world and brain (the world–brain relation).

This shifts the ontological focus away from the mind–body problem to a novel problem that I call the world–brain problem. We need to understand the relation between world and brain (the world–brain relation) to account for the necessary (a posteriori) ontological connection between brain and consciousness. Specifically, we first need to investigate the necessary ontological connection between world and brain to understand the necessary connection between world–brain relation and consciousness. Therefore, I speak of a world–brain problem that must be raised to address the question of the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features. As such, the world–brain problem renders the mind–body problem simply superfluous as the question raised by the latter can well be addressed by the former.

World–Brain Problem IVb: World–Brain Problem—Brain–World Problem?

What is the world–brain problem? The world–brain problem is an ontological problem that concerns the ontological relationship between world and brain. Specifically, the world–brain problem concerns the question of how the existence and reality of the world are related to those of the brain. The concepts of world and brain are understood in a strictly ontological sense rather than either an epistemic or an empirical sense: the world–brain problem is about existence and reality of world and brain rather than our knowledge or observation as related to either world or brain. The world–brain problem is thus about the ontological rather than epistemic or empirical relationship between world and brain.

The world–brain problem as ontological problem intentionally puts the terms world and brain in this sequence, as distinguished from brain–world problem. The brain is part of the world as a whole. Conceived in purely logical–conceptual terms, the assumption that the brain is part of the world as a whole comes close to trivial as there is no brain outside or beyond the world (see below for more details on the argument of triviality). This changes once one conceives their relationship in empirical and ontological terms, however. Instead of mere passive entailment on a logical–conceptual basis, there are active construction processes, both empirically and ontologically, that first and foremost make it possible for the brain to become part of the world as a whole. Using a term from Sellars (1963), the brain as part of the world as a whole is not a “given” (Sellars 1963, p. 128).

Empirically, such active construction processes were, for instance, manifest in specific coding mechanisms, that is, difference-based coding (chapter 2), and spatiotemporal mechanisms such as spatiotemporal alignment of the brain’s rhythmic structure to the one of the world (chapter 8). While ontologically, such active construction is provided by differences de re that constitute relation and structure with relational time and space (chapter 9) which make possible integration of the brain as a part within the world as a whole. If one were now locating these active construction processes within the brain itself, one would indeed better change the sequence of terms and speak of the brain–world problem rather than the world–brain problem. That is not the case, though. Relation and structure as postulated in OSR operate across the observational divide between world and brain by aligning and integrating the latter as part (i.e., brain) within the former as a whole (i.e., world). Therefore, ontologically conceived, we would better speak of the world–brain problem rather than the brain–world problem.

While the concept of world–brain problem is ontological, the reverse sequence as in brain–world problem may be understood in epistemic and empirical terms. The brain–world problem may epistemically concern how we can obtain knowledge of the world on the basis of our brain on the basis of first-, second-, and/or third-person perspective. Empirically, the brain–world problem describes the various ways in which our brain can process and interact with events in the world (chapter 2). As my main focus in this book is on the ontological question of the relationship between brain and consciousness, I concentrate on the world–brain problem while, in contrast, I leave open the epistemic issues related to the brain–world problem.

The critic may now want to argue that the world–brain problem may be just a mereological problem about the relationship between whole and part rather than being a genuine ontological problem. I reject that argument though. True, the brain is indeed part of the world as a whole. However, OSR defines the world by relation and structure that, by definition, include its parts such as the brain in a necessary (a posteriori) way.

As that very same connection remains contingent when one presupposes element-based ontology, the world–brain problem is not just merely mereological but concerns a much deeper ontological problem (see chapters 13 and 14 for discussion of mereological issues). Specifically, the world–brain problem raises the question of how relation and structure must be defined such that they can link world and brain necessarily, in such a way that their relation entails consciousness and mental features. Therefore, the question of world–brain relation is not just a mereological question but rather a basic ontological issue about relation and structure and, more generally, relationship.

World–Brain Problem IVc: World–Brain Problem—Two Halves

That is only half of the world–brain problem, however. The other half consists in the question of the existence and reality of mental features such as consciousness—that shall be explicated in the following.

What must the ontological relationship between world and brain be like to serve as an OPC? I argued that the characterization of the ontological relationship between world and brain in terms of elements (i.e., element-based ontology) is not plausible. Specifically, the definition of world and brain in terms of element-based ontology leaves the connection between brain and consciousness contingent (see above) and therefore fails to account for the existence and reality of consciousness. Therefore, defined by element-based ontology, neither the world nor the brain alone (nor their mere combination or addition) can serve as OPC. Instead, we need to presuppose an alternative ontology, that is, relation-based ontology (i.e., OSR), where structure and relation (rather than elements) constitute world and brain including their relation (i.e., world–brain relation). That allows for the necessary connection between world–brain relation and consciousness with the former serving as OPC.

Taken together, I suppose that the ontological redefinition of the brain in terms of OSR leads to an ontological shift from the mind–body problem to the world–brain problem. Instead of raising the question of the ontological relationship between mind and body, we better question how the world is related to the brain (the world–brain problem) when addressing the question of the existence and reality of consciousness and mental features.

Unlike the mind–body problem, the world–brain problem can well address the original problem of the lack of a necessary connection and upward entailment between brain and consciousness without reverting to either the concept of mind or intuitive relation (as in identity theory or eliminative materialism; see above). This puts the world–brain problem in a superior position when compared to the mind–body problem, which therefore can be replaced by the former.

World–Brain Problem IVd: World–Brain Problem—World–Body Problem?

Finally, one may argue that the world–brain problem can be identified with or even be replaced by what may be called the world–body problem as it may, for instance, be postulated in embodiment approaches (Park et al., 2014; Thompson, 2007; see chapter 8 for more details). I reject that, though. As discussed in chapter 8, the body is transformed from a merely objective body into a lived body by the brain’s alignment to body and world. Ontologically, the lived body presupposes the constitution of consciousness on the basis of world–brain relation as OPC since otherwise there would be no experience of the body as lived body.

Specifically, this means that the body is related to the world on the basis of the brain’s active construction of time and space in terms of the world’s relational time and space. Therefore, the brain and its relation to the world (i.e., world–brain relation) must be considered a necessary condition of transforming the merely physical or objective body into a lived body, the body as we experience it (chapter 8). I therefore speak of the world–brain problem rather than the world–body problem.

However, the proponent of embodiment may not yet be satisfied. We do not experience world–brain relation at all while we do experience our body as lived body and its relation to the world (i.e., world–body relation). Therefore, the world–body problem must be more basic and foundational than the world–brain problem. This is to confuse phenomenal and ontological realms though. True indeed, we do not experience world–brain relation by itself as it is only a predisposition but not a correlate of consciousness (i.e., OPC rather than OCC).

However, to infer from experience of the body and the concomitant lack of experience of world–brain relation to the ontological primacy of the world–body problem over the world–brain problem is to confuse phenomenal and ontological realms. The fact that we do not experience world–brain relation as such in our consciousness does not entail that it cannot serve as OPC of consciousness. More generally put, we cannot infer from the phenomenal realm of consciousness, that is, the experience of the body as lived body, to its ontological basis, world–body relation. This amounts to what I describe as the phenomenal–ontological fallacy. The proponent suggesting the ontological primacy of the world–body problem over the world–brain problem can make that claim only by committing such phenomenal–ontological fallacy. Therefore, her or his argument can be rejected.

The inference from the phenomenal realm of the lived body to the ontological primacy of world–body relation is more or less analogous to the following scenario. Imagine we were inferring from our lacking consciousness of H2O to the claim that H2O cannot constitute the molecular basis of water. This would be considered absurd given our current knowledge. In contrast, this is not considered absurd in the case of world–brain relation by at least the proponent of embodiment. Let us put things straight. In the same way that H2O provides the molecular basis of water, world–brain relation constitutes the ontological basis of consciousness including our experience of the body as lived body. Therefore, as with H2O with respect to water, world–brain relation must be ontologically more basic and foundational for consciousness than the lived body including world–body relation.

The critic may want to argue that the concept of world–brain relation is way too abstract as we can neither observe it nor experience it as such. Even if ontologically valid, the concept of world–brain relation is too abstract to serve as OPC for something as concrete as our consciousness. This is to neglect the history of science though. As pointed out in chapter 2, several discoveries in science including quantum theory and the genetic code are rather abstract and not directly accessible as such in both observation and experience. However, that neither hinders quantum theory in serving as an ontological predisposition of physical reality nor the genetic code in providing the ontological basis of inheritance. Hence, the argument of abstraction as an argument that world–brain relation is too abstract to serve as OPC must be rejected on scientific and ontological grounds (see also chapter 14 for a similar argument).

World–Brain Problem Va: World–Brain Problem—Argument of Triviality

One may now want to argue that the world–brain problem is trivial. The argument of triviality posed here with regard to the world–brain problem can be considered an ontological extension of the argument of triviality I raised in the empirical context of the spatiotemporal model of consciousness (chapter 7). Specifically, the world–brain problem may be regarded as trivial on empirical, conceptual, and ontological grounds.

First, the world–brain problem is empirically trivial in that it refers back to the brain and its neuronal mechanisms. Therefore, conceived empirically, the world–brain problem really turns out to be a “brain problem” rather than world–brain problem. Second, the world–brain problem is trivial on conceptual grounds. The addition of the brain does not add anything new to the concept of world, which includes the brain by default since the latter is part of the former. Therefore, considered conceptually, we could replace the world–brain problem by what can be called the world problem.

Third, the world–brain problem is ontologically trivial. The existence and reality of the world must also characterize the existence and reality of the brain as the latter is part of the former. For instance, the physical or mental properties that characterize the world, as in materialism or panpsychism, also apply to the brain and must thus characterize its existence and reality. Therefore, the inclusion of the brain in the world–brain problem is rather trivial on ontological grounds.

However, I reject all three claims of triviality. First, I demonstrated that a specific neuronal mechanism, that is, spatiotemporal alignment, accounted for the brain’s empirical relation to the world (chapter 8). The absence of such spatiotemporal alignment renders impossible, on empirical grounds, world–brain relation, which is then replaced by world–brain isolation. Hence, considered empirically, the world–brain problem includes different kinds of empirical options, that is, mechanisms by means of which the brain’s neural activity could position itself in regard to the world, that is, world–brain relation versus world–brain isolation. Therefore, the assumption of the world–brain problem is far from trivial on empirical grounds.

Second, the world–brain problem is not conceptually trivial. The world–brain problem contains different options with respect to the relationship between world and brain. For instance, there can be a necessary or a contingent connection between world and brain. If the connection between world and brain is necessary, the world–brain problem can account for the necessary connection between brain and consciousness. If, in contrast, the connection between world and brain remains contingent, the world–brain problem cannot account for the necessary connection between brain and consciousness and remains therefore unable to address the question of the existence and reality of mental features. Since the world–brain problem includes different conceptual options, that is, necessary versus contingent, for the relationship between world and brain, it cannot be considered trivial on conceptual grounds.

Third and finally, the world–brain problem is not ontologically trivial. One can presuppose different ontological frameworks such as element-, relation-, process-, and capacity-based ontology. We have already seen that the relationship between world and brain will be different when presupposing either element- or relation-based ontology. Other ontological options for their possible relationship emerge when presupposing either process-based ontology (Northoff, 2016a,b) or capacity-based ontology (chapters 5 and 9). Since the ontological characterization of world and brain, including their relationship, depends on the presupposed ontological framework that entails different ontological options, the world–brain problem cannot be conceived as ontologically trivial.

World–Brain Problem Vb: World–Brain Problem versus World–Brain Relation—Question versus Answer

The critic may now want to argue that we did not really define the various terms included in the notion of world–brain problem. We defined neither the concept of world nor that of relation; only the concept of brain was defined somewhat as it relied on the previous chapter (chapter 9). I will define the concept of world in an ontological sense in more detail in the next chapter, chapter 11. Here I shall focus on the concept of relation. We can distinguish between at least two (possible) distinct concepts of relation in world–brain relation, for example, narrow and wide.

“Relation” in “world–brain relation” can be understood in a narrow sense. In that case, “relation” refers to the ontological definition of relation in terms of OSR. Empirically, the narrow meaning of relation is determined by spatiotemporal alignment (chapter 8) while, conceptually, it implies a necessary (rather than contingent) and therefore intrinsic (rather than extrinsic) connection between world and brain. Hence, the narrow meaning of relation is determined in a specific way on empirical, conceptual, and ontological grounds. Such determination, and consequently the narrow meaning of “relation,” is presupposed when I consider world–brain relation as the answer to the world–brain problem (as the underlying question).

What about the wide concept of relation in world–brain relation? The wide meaning of “relation” refers to relationship in general, that is, the commonsense notion of relationship, which includes all possible ontological, conceptual, and empirical options. Thus, the wide meaning of “relation” in “world–brain relation” remains empirically, conceptually, and ontologically undetermined. This is the notion of relation I presuppose when I speak of the world–brain problem. Since it includes several empirical, conceptual, and ontological options with regard to the relation between world and brain, the world–brain problem cannot be considered trivial at all on any of these grounds (i.e., empirical, conceptual, and ontological).

In conclusion, my rejection of the trivial nature of the world–brain problem on all three levels, that is, empirical, ontological, and conceptual, presupposes the wide meaning of the concept of relation in my concept of world–brain relation. The world–brain problem must therefore be distinguished from world–brain relation: the former raises the question of the possible relationship between world and brain by adopting a wide meaning of relation while the latter provides an answer by determining relation in a specific and thus narrow meaning. If, in contrast, one presupposes the narrow meaning of relation in the concept of the world–brain problem, the latter will indeed be rendered trivial—that is to confuse answer (i.e., the world–brain relation with its presupposed narrow meaning of relation) and question (i.e., the world–brain problem presupposing the wide meaning of relation).

Conclusion

How can we determine the existence and reality of consciousness? As based on the ontological determination of the brain in terms of world–brain relation and OSR, I suggest the world–brain relation as a necessary, nonsufficient ontological condition of possible consciousness (i.e., as OPC). Most important, because of its constitution of spatiotemporal structure with space-time relation, the world–brain relation allows us to take into view and thus conceive a necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness. That must be distinguished from the contingent relationship between brain and consciousness that plagues most past and present philosophical and neuroscientific approaches to consciousness and mental features in general.

To allow for a necessary rather than contingent ontological connection between brain and consciousness, we have to revise our standard ontological presuppositions though. Instead of element-based ontology with mental and physical properties, we rather need to presuppose OSR with structure and relation as basic units of existence and reality. This makes possible the ontological redefinition of the brain in terms of relation, that is, world–brain relation, rather than by some intrinsic features within the brain itself such as physical or mental properties.

How and why can world–brain relation allow for a necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness? I propose that it is connected with its spatiotemporal characterization by relational time and space. Relational time and space make necessary the ontological relation between world and brain (i.e., world–brain relation). That, in turn, puts the brain, through its world–brain relation, in a necessary ontological connection to consciousness as defined by its phenomenal features, which I propose are characterized by space-time relation (reflecting relational time and space).

Hence, time and space and, more specifically, relational time and space provide the missing glue or missing link between brain and consciousness and, even more generally, between world and consciousness. The proposed empirical spatiotemporal theory of consciousness (chapter 7) can thus be complemented on the ontological side by an analogous spatiotemporal model of consciousness.

Such spatiotemporal model of consciousness provides a new view on some of the problems discussed in philosophy of mind such as the explanatory gap problem (Levine, 1998), which shall be briefly indicated here (awaiting further detailed discussion in the future). The explanatory gap problem argues that there is an explanatory gap between physical and mental features which, applied to the case of the brain, can be reframed as the gap between neuronal and phenomenal features (Northoff, 2014b). Within the current ontological framework of structural realism, the concept of such an explanatory gap is not plausible and therefore can no longer be sustained. The role of world–brain relation as OPC implies the necessary ontological connection between brain and consciousness. Such a necessary connection stands counter to the assumption of a gap between neuronal and phenomenal features, which in turn renders the assumption of an explanatory gap implausible and even nonsensical in the present framework.

Most important, characterization of world–brain relation in terms of spatiotemporal ontology renders superfluous the need to introduce the concept of mind for drawing the necessary connection to consciousness and mental features. The role of the mind can now be taken over by world–brain relation, which serves as OPC. This renders the concept of mind and subsequently the mind–body problem superfluous in our account of consciousness and mental features. All that we aim to answer by the concept of mind and the mind–body problem can now be addressed in a much more empirically and ontologically plausible way by the world–brain problem. In short, we can replace the mind–body problem with the world–brain problem.

Several issues remain open, however. First, I identified the necessary ontological conditions, that is, predisposition of consciousness (OPC); this left open the sufficient ontological conditions of actual consciousness though, the OCCs. Second, I left open the nature of phenomenal features of consciousness and how they are related to world–brain relation as OPC. Third, one may wonder about the sequence of the terms “world” and “brain” in “world–brain relation.” One may, alternatively, suggest brain–world relation, which I reject though as the latter is at best epistemic or empirical rather than ontological. Finally, I left open the exact determination of the concept of world in my account of world–brain relation. These issues shall be addressed in the next chapter.