8  What is ethics?

Essential terminology

Deduction

Definition

Factual statement

Fallacy

Logic

Ethics is the philosophical study of good and bad, right and wrong. It is commonly used interchangeably with the word ‘morality’ and is also known as moral philosophy. The study of ethics requires you to look at moral issues, such as abortion, euthanasia and cloning, and to examine views that are quite different from your own. You need to be open-minded, use your critical powers and above all learn from the way different ethical ethics need to be applied with logic so that we can end up with a set of theories to approach the issues you will study for AS and A level. Ethics needs to be applied with logic so that we can end up with a set of moral beliefs that are supported with reasons, are consistent and reflect the way we see and act in the world. Ethical theories are constructed logically, but give different weights to different concepts.

However, it is not enough to prove that the theory you agree with is true and reasonable; you must also show where and how other philosophers went wrong.

Fallacies

With the possible exception of you and me, people usually do not have logical reasons for what they believe. This is especially true for ethical issues. Here are some examples of how not to arrive at a belief. We call them fallacies.

Here are some common beliefs; you may recognise your own reasons for holding a particular view:

Is–ought fallacy

David Hume (1711–1776) observed that often when people are debating a moral issue they begin with facts and slide into conclusions that are normative – that is conclusions about how things ought to be. He argued that no amount of facts taken alone can ever be sufficient to imply a normative conclusion: the is-ought fallacy. For example it is a fact that slavery still exists in some form or other in many countries – that is an ‘is’. However, this fact is morally neutral, and it is only when we say we ‘ought’ to abolish slavery that we are making a moral judgement. The fallacy is saying that the ‘ought’ statement follows logically from the ‘is’, but this does not need to be the case. Another example is to say that humans possess reason and this distinguishes us from other animals – it does not logically follow that we ought to exercise our reason to live a fulfilled life.

Areas of ethics

Ethics looks at what you ought to do as distinct from what you may in fact do. Ethics is usually divided into three areas: meta-ethics, normative ethics and applied ethics.

  1. 1 Meta-ethics looks at the meaning of the language used in ethics, and includes questions such as: are ethical claims capable of being true or false, or are they expressions of emotion? If true, is that truth relative only to some individual, society or culture? What does it mean to say something is good or bad, and what do the words ‘good’ and ‘bad’ mean? (This is studied in Year 2.)
  2. 2 Normative ethics asks the question ‘what ought I to do?’ and attempts to arrive at practical moral standards (or norms) that tell us right from wrong and how to live moral lives. These are what we call ethical theories. This may involve explaining the good habits we should acquire and looking at whether there are duties we should follow or whether our actions should be guided by their consequences for ourselves and/or others. There are various ethical theories that are described as normative:
  3. 3 Applied ethics is the application of theories of right and wrong and theories of value to specific issues, such as abortion, euthanasia, cloning, foetal research, and lying and honesty.

Ethics is not just giving your own opinion, and the way it is studied at AS and A level is very like philosophy: it is limited to facts, logic and definition. Ideally, a philosopher is able to prove that a theory is true and reasonable based on accurate definitions and verifiable facts. Once these definitions and facts have been established, a philosopher can develop the theory through a process of deduction, by showing what logically follows from the definitions and facts. The theory may then be applied to controversial moral issues. It is a bit like baking a cake.

The definitions of the main theories in normative ethics

Deontological ethics is concerned with the acts that are right or wrong in themselves (intrinsically right or wrong). This may be because these acts go against some duty or obligation or they break some absolute law – for example a deontologist may say that killing is wrong as the actual act of killing another human being is always wrong. Deontologists are always certain in their moral decisions and can take strong moral positions, such as being totally against war. On the other hand they do not take into account the circumstances, or different cultures or different religious views.

Teleological ethics is concerned with the ends, results or consequences of an action. Followers of teleological ethics consider the consequence of an ethical decision before they act. The action is not intrinsically good (good in itself) but good only if the results are good – the action produces happiness and love. However, the main problem with teleological ethics is that it can never be sure what the result or consequence of an action might be – it is possible to make an educated guess but not to be absolutely sure, and sometimes we can tell if the consequences of an action are right only with hindsight. Another problem with teleological ethics is that some actions are always wrong – rape for example – and can never be justified by the consequence.

Moral objectivism claims that there are certain universal and absolute values. Modern moral objectivists do not believe that these universal values hold forever, but they hold until they are proven to be false.

Moral subjectivism claims that moral statements are simply a matter of personal opinion. We simply make our own morality according to our own experiences and see our moral views as true for ourselves or our society and not necessarily applying to others.

Intrinsic good means something is good in itself: it has value simply because it exists without any references to the consequences. This applies to deontological ethics.

Instrumental good means something is good because of the effects or consequences it has, or as a means to some other end or purpose. To explain this Peter Singer (Practical Ethics, 2011, p. 246) uses the example of money – it has value because of the things we can buy with it, but if we were marooned on a desert island we would not want it.

Ethical theories

If we are to have valid ethical arguments then we must have some normative premises to begin with. These normative premises are either statements of ethical theories themselves or statements implied by ethical theories. The ethical theories that will be examined in this book are as follows:

Utilitarianism:An action is right if it maximises the overall happiness of all people.
Kantian ethics:Treat other people the way you wish they would treat you, and never treat other people as if they were merely objects.
Cultural relativism:What is right or wrong varies according to the beliefs of each culture.
Divine command:Do as the creator tells you.
Natural law:Everything is created for a purpose, and when this is examined by human reason a person should be able to judge how to act in order to find ultimate happiness.
Situation ethics:Based on agape, which wills the good of others.

Review questions

Look back over the chapter and check that you can answer the following questions:

  1. 1 What is the ‘Is-ought fallacy’?
  2. 2 Name the three areas of ethics.
  3. 3 Explain what is meant by ‘Cultural relativism’?