Essential terminology
Act utilitarianism
Consequentialist
Hedonic calculus
Hedonism
Preference
Utilitarianism
Principle of utility
Qualitative quantitative
Rule utilitarianism
Teleological
Universalisability
Key scholars
Epicurus (341–270 BCE) Richard Brandt (1910–1997)
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) R.M. Hare (1919–2002)
John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) John Rawls (1921–2002)
W.D. Ross (1877–1971) Bernard Williams (1929–2003)
Karl Popper (1902–1994) Peter Singer (1946–)
Utilitarianism, including:
Learners should have the opportunity to discuss issues raised by utilitarianism, including:
(From OCR AS Level Religious Studies Specification H173)
You have probably heard someone justify their actions as being for the greater good. Utilitarianism is the ethical theory behind such justifications.
Utilitarianism is a teleological theory of ethics. It is the opposite of deontological ethical theories that are based on moral rules, on whether the action itself is right or wrong. Teleological theories of ethics look at the consequences – the results of an action – to decide whether it is right or wrong. Utilitarianism is a consequentialist theory.
The theory of utilitarianism began with Jeremy Bentham as a way of working out how good or bad the consequence of an action would be.
Utilitarianism gets its name from Bentham’s test question: ‘What is the use of it?’ He thought of the idea when he came across the words ‘the greatest happiness of the greatest number’ in Joseph Priestley’s An Essay on the First Principles of Government, on the nature of political, civil and religious liberty (1768). Bentham was very concerned with social and legal reform and he wanted to develop an ethical theory which established whether something was good or bad according to its benefit for the majority of people.
Bentham called this the principle of utility. Utility here means the usefulness of the results of actions. The principle of utility is often expressed as ‘the greatest good of the greatest number’. ‘Good’ is defined in terms of pleasure or happiness – so an act is right or wrong according to the good or bad that results from the act and the good act is the most pleasurable. Since it focuses on the greatest number, Bentham’s theory is quantitative.
Principle of utility
The theory of usefulness – the greatest happiness for the greatest number.
Consequentialist
Someone who decides whether an action is good or bad by its consequences.
Teleological
Moral actions are right or wrong according to their outcome or telos (end).
Hedonism
The view that pleasure is the chief ‘good’.
The idea that ‘good’ is defined in terms of pleasure and happiness makes utilitarianism a hedonistic theory. The Greek philosophers who thought along similar lines introduced the term eudaimonia, which is probably best translated as ‘well-being’. Both Plato and Aristotle agreed that ‘good’ equated with the greatest happiness, while the Epicureans stressed ‘pleasure’ as the main aim of life. The ultimate end of human desires and actions, according to Aristotle, is happiness, and although pleasure sometimes accompanies this, it is not the chief aim of life. Pleasure is not the same as happiness, as happiness results from the use of reason and cultivating the virtues. It is only if we take pleasure in good activities that pleasure itself is good. This idea of Aristotle’s is taken up by John Stuart Mill, as we will see later.
Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)
Jeremy Bentham was born in London on 15 February 1748. He could read scholarly works at age 3, played the violin at 5 and studied Latin and French at 6. At age 12 he went to Oxford and trained as a lawyer. Bentham was the leader of the Philosophical Radicals, who founded the Westminster Review. He died in London on 6 June 1832. His body was dissected and his clothed skeleton is in a glass case in University College, London. Bentham advanced his theory of utilitarianism as the basis for general political and legal reform.
Jeremy Bentham developed his ethical system around the idea of pleasure, and it is based on ancient hedonism, which pursued physical pleasure and avoided physical pain. There is, therefore, no consideration of the natural rights of humans, which Bentham rejected as ‘nonsense on stilts’. An individual’s right to life or to freedom is granted by society and is the result of legislation, and logically for a utilitarian, such as Bentham, it could be removed if the result was greater social utility and greater pleasure and well-being for the majority.
According to Bentham, the most moral acts are those that maximise pleasure and minimise pain. This has sometimes been called the ‘utilitarian calculus’. An act would be moral if it brings the greatest amount of pleasure and the least amount of pain.
Bentham said,
The principle of utility aims to promote happiness which is the supreme ethical value. Nature has placed us under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. An act is right if it delivers more pleasure than pain and wrong if it brings about more pain than pleasure.
By adding up the amounts of pleasure and pain for each possible act we should be able to choose the good thing to do.
Happiness = pleasure minus pain
Hedonic calculus
Bentham’s method for measuring the good and bad effects of an action.
To help us choose the good thing to do and work out the possible consequences of an action, Bentham provided a way of measuring. This is the hedonic calculus.
It has seven elements:
The quantity of happiness
Jordi Clave Garsot/Alamy
This calculus gave Bentham a method of testing whether an action is morally right, in that if it was good it would result in the most pleasurable outcome, all the elements having been weighed up. Whatever is good or bad can be measured in a quantitative way. Bentham’s utilitarianism stresses that each person’s pleasures count equally – so public interest is more important than the individual’s own happiness or pleasure. Sentience – the ability to feel pleasure and pain – is also important for Bentham: ‘The question is not, Can they reason? Nor Can they talk? But Can they suffer?’ (Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation). Overleaf there is an example of how the hedonic calculus might be applied to a young totally paralysed man who is deciding whether to have euthanasia.
It is actually quite difficult to decide which decision would bring the most pleasure and the least pain, and this is one of the problems when using the hedonic calculus as it is not possible for us to see into the future; we can only make educated guesses, and these are often clouded by our emotional state at the time.
Quantitative
Looking at the quantity of the happiness.
Act utilitarianism
A teleological theory that uses the outcome of an action to determine whether it is good or bad.
Bentham’s utilitarianism is a universal hedonism – the highest good is the greatest happiness for the greatest number. Actions are judged as a means to an end. What is right is that which is calculated to bring about the greatest balance of good over evil, where good is defined as pleasure or happiness.
Bentham’s view is described as act utilitarianism.
Hedonic calculus |
Have euthanasia |
Do not have euthanasia |
---|---|---|
Intensity |
He could be at peace and his family would not have to devote their lives to caring for him. However, his death could bring intense feelings of pain to his family and friends. |
His continuing existence gives intense feelings of joy to his family and friends, but may also lead to resentment in those who care for him. |
Duration |
Death is permanent but the grieving of family and friends might last a long time. |
The young man will need looking after for a lifetime. |
Certainty |
The freedom from the pain of his situation is certain. |
It is uncertain what pleasures continuing to live totally paralysed will bring. |
Remoteness |
The relief from his situation is immediate. |
Any possibility of a cure or of learning to live successfully with his situation is a long way off. |
Succession |
There will be no more choices. The relief that he is no longer suffering may help his family and friends to accept his death. |
Pleasure that he is still living but pain that he is still suffering will cancel each other out. |
Purity |
If he regrets his decision it will be too late. |
May live a miserable life stuck on a bed or in a wheelchair, totally dependent on others. |
Extent |
The young man and his family and friends are the most directly affected. |
His continuing existence will bring both pain and pleasure for a lifetime. |
Bentham argued that we should be guided by the principle of utility and not by rules. However, it may be necessary to use rules of thumb based on past experience, especially if there is no time to work out the consequences. However, it is the consequences that are the most important for Bentham as they can be easily predicted.
Mill was also a hedonist and accepted that happiness is of the greatest importance. He stressed happiness rather than pleasure.
Mill said,
The Greatest Happiness Principle holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain and the privation of pleasure.
Happiness for Mill is more than just pleasure and also includes having goals and virtues.
John Stuart Mill (1806–1873)
John Stuart Mill was born on 20 May 1806, the son of James Mill, who had a significant influence on nineteenth-century British thought in philosophy, economics, politics and ethics. From 1822 he worked for his father in India House and stayed there until 1858, when the company closed and he retired. Mill then lived in St Véran, France, until 1865, when he became a member of Parliament. He went back to France in 1868, and lived there until his death on 8 May 1873. He is most famous for his essay On Liberty (1859).
Having affirmed his agreement with the principle of utility, Mill then modifies Bentham’s approach, especially the quantitative emphasis. He says, ‘Some kinds of pleasures are more desirable and more valuable than others, it would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is not also considered as well as quantity.’
According to Mill, quality of pleasure employs the use of the higher faculties. Here he is answering the objection to Bentham’s approach that utilitarians are just pleasure-seekers. For example consider the case of the Christians and the Romans: many Romans got a lot of pleasure from seeing a few Christians eaten by lions – here the greatest happiness (that of the Romans) was produced by an act (Christians being eaten by lions) that is surely quite wrong. Mill says that the quality of pleasure that satisfies a human is different from that which satisfies an animal. People are capable of more than animals, so it takes more to make a human happy. Therefore, a person will always choose higher-quality human pleasures and reject all the merely animal pleasures. As Mill puts it,
Few human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals for a promise of the fullest allowance of the beast’s pleasures … It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool or the pig are of a different opinion, it is because they only know their side of the question.
(On Virtue and Happiness, 1863)
The quality of happiness
Darren Robb/Getty
So since the Romans are enjoying only ‘animal’ pleasure, it does not matter that they are getting a lot more of it than the Christians – it is the quality and not the quantity of the pleasure that really counts. For Mill, it is intellectual pleasures (e.g. reading poetry or listening to music) that really count and are more important than such pleasures as eating, drinking or having sex.
Happiness, he argues, is something that people desire for its own sake, but we need to look at human life as a whole – happiness is not just adding up the units of pleasure but rather the fulfilment of higher ideals. In order to distinguish between these higher and lower pleasures Mill proposed the idea of competent judges who had experienced both higher and lower pleasures and so were able to say with authority that the higher pleasures were to be preferred.
Mill next develops the argument that in order to derive the principle of the greatest good (happiness) for the greatest number we need the principle of universalisability. He says, ‘Each person’s happiness is a good to that person, and the general happiness, therefore, is a good to the aggregate of all persons.’
As you can see, the last proposition does not follow logically from the previous one. To move from each person to everyone is a fallacy. Mill makes this move because he wants to justify ‘the greatest number’. This can mean that utilitarianism demands that people put the interests of the group before their own interests, and Mill compares this to ‘the Golden Rule of Jesus of Nazareth’. Mill has a positive view of human nature and thinks that people have powerful feelings of empathy for others, which can be cultivated by education and so on.
Mill also separates the question of the motive and the morality of the action. There is nothing wrong with self-interest if it produces the right action.
Happiness
Mint Images Limited/Alamy
Universalisability
If an act is right or wrong for one person in a situation, then it is right or wrong for anyone in that situation.
Rule utilitarianism
Establishing a general rule that follows utilitarian principles.
Another aspect of Mill’s approach is the idea that there need to be some moral rules in order to establish social order and justice – but the rules should be those which, if followed universally, would most likely produce the greatest happiness. Mill has been seen as a rule utilitarian in contrast to Bentham’s act utilitarianism – although Mill never discussed act or rule utilitarianism in these terms. Also, like many philosophers, Mill’s approach was not consistent throughout his writings – at first Mill appears to be an act utilitarian, saying that pleasures can be described as either higher or lower, and later he writes that rights and rules are principles of utility. He argues that some rights need to be guaranteed in order to ensure general happiness and the greater good. Mill considers that people have interests that ought to be defended, such as protection from harm, so rule utilitarianism can protect human rights if they make everyone’s lives happier. He seems to assert that when one is uncertain as to which action to take, the rules of justice and rights (life, liberty and property) must be considered as most important.
As Mill’s position is unclear it is perhaps better to describe him as a weak rule utilitarian, as when a strong utilitarian reason exists to break the rule, the rule should be disregarded. This is also the case when two utilitarian rules conflict – for example should Robin Hood break the rule ‘do not steal’ or the rule ‘help the poor’? In this dilemma the only possible solution is to consider which action will maximise utility. However, this still leaves the possibility of injustice, lack of consideration for minorities and so forth, which rule utilitarianism was designed to avoid.
Bentham |
Mill |
---|---|
‘The greatest good [pleasure] for the greatest number’ |
‘The greatest happiness for the greatest number’ |
Focused on the individual alone |
We should protect the common good, universalistic |
Quantitative – hedonic calculus |
Qualitative – higher/lower pleasure |
Act utilitarianism |
Rule utilitarianism |
In search of maximisation of happiness |
|
Consequentialist |
Consequentialist |
Jeremy Bentham
World History Archive/Alamy
John Stuart Mill
Everett Collection Historical/Alamy
The distinction between act and rule utilitarianism is to do with what the principle of utility is applied to.
You must decide what action will lead to the greatest good in the particular situation you are facing and apply the principle of utility directly. You need to look at the consequences of a particular act and what will bring about the greatest happiness.
Since the same act might in some situations produce the greatest good for the greatest number, but in other situations not, utilitarianism allows moral rules to change from age to age, from situation to situation.
There are no necessary moral rules except one: that we should always seek the greatest happiness for the greatest number in all situations.
Act utilitarianism is linked to Bentham’s form of utilitarianism.
Rule utilitarians believe that rules should be formed using utilitarian principles for the benefit of society. Your action is judged right or wrong by the goodness or badness of the consequences of a rule that everyone should follow in similar circumstances. Rule utilitarianism enables us to establish universal rules that will promote the happiness of humanity and will generally be right in most circumstances (e.g. telling the truth, keeping your promises). This avoids the difficulty of the negative consequences which could result if act utilitarianism were to be universalised – if everyone acted according to their own personal knowledge of the situation without considering general rules or excepted behaviour, the result could lead to injustice, disorder and unpredictable actions. So for a rule utilitarian it is better to follow general rules based on the principle of utility than try to work out the best action to take in every situation. This can also protect human rights as in general having rights makes everyone’s lives happier.
Strong rule utilitarians believe that these derived rules should never be disobeyed.
Weak rule utilitarians say that although there should be generally accepted rules or guidelines, they should not always be adhered to indefinitely. There may be situations where the better consequence might be achieved by disregarding the rule (e.g. where it might be better to tell a lie).
Weak rule utilitarianism is commonly linked with Mill; however, it is not clear whether Mill was an act or a rule utilitarian. For Mill it seems that experience teaches us the best consequences of our actions, so in utilitarianism he advocates that it could be a duty to steal medicine or food in order to save a life.
Preference utilitarianism
Moral actions are right or wrong according to how they fit the preferences of those involved.
Preference utilitarianism is a more recent form of utilitarianism and is associated with R.M. Hare, Peter Singer and Richard Brandt.
An act utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the maximising of pleasure and minimising of pain, a rule utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the keeping of rules derived from utility, but a preference utilitarian judges moral actions according to whether they fit in with the preferences of the individuals involved. This approach to utilitarianism asks, ‘What is in my own interest? What would I prefer in this situation? Which outcome would I prefer?’ However, because utilitarianism aims to create the greatest good for the greatest number, it is necessary to consider the preferences of others in order to achieve this. This requires an equal consideration of the interests of everyone else affected by an ethical decision.
Hare argues that in moral decision making we need to consider our own preferences and those of others. He says that ‘equal preferences count equally, whatever their content’. People are happy when they get what they prefer, but what we prefer may clash with the preferences of others. Hare says we need to ‘stand in someone else’s shoes’ and try to imagine what someone else might prefer. We should treat everyone, including ourselves, with impartiality – he also argues for universalisability.
Peter Singer (1946–)
Peter Singer was born on 6 July 1946 in Melbourne. He studied at Melbourne and Oxford. In 1999 he was appointed DeCamp Professor of Bioethics at the University Center for Human Values at Princeton University. Singer’s system is based on reason and not on self-interest or social conditioning. His work deals with issues such as embryo experimentation, genetic engineering, surrogacy, abortion and euthanasia. Singer’s best-known work is Animal Liberation (1975). He is a vegetarian and donates the royalties from his books to international aid and animal liberation. He gives between 10% and 20% of his income to the poor.
Singer also defends preference utilitarianism and suggests that we should take the viewpoint of an impartial spectator combined with a broadly utilitarian approach. He says that ‘our own preferences cannot count any more than the preferences of others’ and so, in acting morally, we should take account of all the people affected by our actions. Ethical judgements must be made from a universal point of view. This view accepts that our own wants, needs and desires cannot count for more than those of anyone else. Singer uses the example of sharing the abundance of nature’s fruits – everyone is entitled to an equal share. These have to be weighed and balanced, and then we must choose the action that gives the best possible consequences for those affected. Singer says society is made up of a collection of individuals, each with their own preferences; trade-offs, however, have to be made for the general welfare – in other words some preferences have to be accepted and others rejected so that the good of all may be achieved.
For Singer, the ‘best possible consequences’ means what is in the best interests of the individuals concerned – this is different from Bentham and Mill, as he is not considering what increases pleasure but what diminishes pain. In Practical Ethics (1993) Singer wrote that ‘an action contrary to the preference of any being is wrong, unless this preference is outweighed by contrary preferences’ The more preferences satisfied in the world, the better – so killing someone like Hitler, which would save the lives of many others and lead to many preferences being fulfilled, would be the right thing to do.
This principle of equal consideration of preferences or interests acts like a pair of scales – everyone’s preferences or interests are weighed equally. So, in Singer’s view, killing a person who prefers to go on living would be wrong and not killing a person who prefers to die would also be wrong. Racism is wrong, as it goes against the principle of acknowledging other people’s interests or preferences and gives greater value to the preferences of one’s own race.
If Singer’s principles were put into practice, they would prove radical – for example he argued that since $1,000 can keep several children alive for years, each of us is obligated not to spend it but to donate it to Oxfam or the Red Cross. Singer’s principle is ‘If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it’ (‘Famine, Affluence, and Morality’).
A moment’s reflection on the implications of this principle should convince you of its radicalness. If we were to follow it, we would be left just slightly better off than the worst off people in the world (who would be much better off). People would have to turn in their second cars and second homes and share the ones they already have.
(Pojman, Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong, 2002)
There are always going to be issues with this as one could argue that it is not always possible to know people’s true preferences, as these change over time as our knowledge and understanding change, and according to Singer’s principle of equal consideration this shows that the ties of love and kinship do not count.
Some of Singer’s approaches seem difficult to accept for many people – he argues that some animals have a higher moral status than some humans. He begins this argument by observing that many animals prefer to avoid pain and enjoy pleasure. Singer argues that causing animals pain by killing them for food, caging them, separating them from their mates and families and so forth is against their preferences and is therefore wrong. He does not consider humans to be above animals and states that an intelligent adult ape has more conscious preferences than a newborn infant. To think otherwise is to be guilty of speciesism. He approves of Bentham’s dictum ‘the question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?’, and follows Mill’s idea when he talks of extending ‘the standard of morality so far as the nature of things permits, to the whole of sentient creation’ (utilitarianism). Singer accords animals rights as sentient (feeling) beings; they have valid interests. So according to Singer’s preference utilitarianism, it is preferences rather than human life that we should value.
This view obviously brings out the problem of those people who are unable to express preferences – the newborn, the severely mentally disabled and those who have no rational self-consciousness, such as people suffering from Alzheimer’s. Also, according to Singer, an early foetus would have no preferences as it cannot feel pain, and even a late foetus would have its limited preferences outweighed by those of the parents: for Singer the worth of human life varies. The same philosophy applies to the dying or those with Alzheimer’s – they may have no preferences left, but the family and friends who love them do.
Richard Brandt was one of the leading utilitarian philosophers of the twentieth century. He defended a version of rule utilitarianism, but later, in his book A Theory of the Right and the Good (1979), he talks about the preferences you would have if you had gone through a process of cognitive psychotherapy, explored all the reasons for your preferences and rejected any you felt were not true to your real values. He argued that the morality you would then accept would be a form of utilitarianism – with your preferences free from any psychological blocks and you in full possession of all the facts. Such a person would not, therefore, be influenced by advertising.
Bernard Williams (1929–2003)
Bernard Williams was born in Southend-on-Sea and studied at Balliol College, Oxford. In 1967 he was made Knightsbridge Professor of Philosophy at the University of Cambridge. In 1988 he moved to the USA. He was a professor at Berkeley, California, and White’s Professor of Moral Philosophy at Oxford until his retirement in 1996. He was very interested in politics and sat on several government committees, including those on gambling, drugs and pornography.
John Rawls (1921–2002)
John Rawls was known for his theory of ‘justice as fairness’. He taught at Cornell University and Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and then moved to Harvard. He is known for A Theory of Justice (1971) and Political Liberalism (1993).
Utilitarianism has some major weaknesses as far as duty, justice, motives, intentions and consequences are concerned, and the principles of ‘the greatest good for the greatest number’ and ‘treating people as a means to an end’ are rather dubious moral principles. The principles of seeking to act in a benevolent way and trying to apply universality and a consideration of consequences (even if only estimated) are principles that may be used with other, more deontological principles, such as duty and integrity. Perhaps we need to combine the best principles from both the teleological and deontological approaches to ethics.
Look back over the chapter and check that you can answer the following questions:
Try to explain the following key ideas without looking at your books and notes:
Examination questions practice |
When writing answers to questions on utilitarianism, make sure you can explain clearly the different types, as utilitarianism is more a family of theories than one simple theory.
‘Utilitarianism will always lead to wrong ethical decisions.’ Discuss.
AO1 (15 marks)
AO2 (15 marks)
Bentham, J. 1948. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (ed. Harrison, W.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gensler, H., Earl, W. and Swindal, J. 2004. Ethics: Contemporary Readings. New York: Routledge (contains original writings of many classic and contemporary philosophers).
Mill, J.S. [1861, 1863], 2002. Utilitarianism. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Norman, R. 1998. The Moral Philosophers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pojman, L.P. 1989. Ethical Theory. Toronto: Wadsworth.
Pojman, L.P. 2002. Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong. Toronto: Wadsworth.
Pojman, L.P. 2006. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (5th ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomson/Wadsworth.
Singer, P. 1993. Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smart, J.J.C. and Williams, B. 1973. Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.