A Portentous Question, a Quixotic Proposal
Consider, as an entry into our inquiry, two variations on an earnestly posed question—variations separated by almost two millennia. The first instance of the question was pressed in classical Rome. The second instance arises today in connection with the so-called culture wars. The recurring question is simple but fraught; if we could discern the answer to the question, we would likely be helped thereby to understand something important about the beginnings of our Western civilization, about our own perplexing and conflicted times, and maybe even about the kind of species we are.
Pliny’s Question (and Tertullian’s)
In the early second century, a literate and genial (and sycophantic)1 Roman gentleman named Pliny—historians call him Pliny the Younger to distinguish him from his famous uncle, the encyclopedist who died in the eruption of Mount Vesuvius—wrote to his boss, the emperor Trajan, asking for legal advice.2 At the time, Pliny was serving as governor for the province of Bithynia, in the north of present-day Turkey, and citizens of the province had accused some of their neighbors of being Christians.3 In response, Pliny had adopted what seemed to him a sensible procedure for dealing with such complaints. An accused person was brought before the governor and asked whether he or she was a Christian. Sometimes an accused person would answer yes. In such cases, Pliny would carefully explain that being Christian was a capital offense, and he would then repeat the question, twice. If the accused persisted in his or her affirmative answer, Pliny would sentence the confessing Christian “to be led away for execution.”
Conversely, the accused might deny the charge or claim to have abandoned the Christian faith, and Pliny had devised a method to test such denials. Statues of the emperor Trajan and of pagan gods were provided, and the accused was ordered to worship the statues, to make an offering of wine and incense, and also to “[revile] the name of Christ.” A defendant who satisfactorily complied with these requirements was released.4
This was Pliny’s procedure, but he wasn’t sure whether he was handling the cases correctly. He was especially concerned because the accusations seemed to be proliferating. So he wrote to ask the emperor’s advice.
As part of his inquiry, Pliny also incidentally raised a more fundamental question: Why were Christians being subjected to legal sanctions at all? Was “the mere name of Christian . . . punishable, even if innocent of crime”? Or, instead, were only “the crimes associated with the name” to be punished?5
Pliny’s working assumption, it seems, had been that merely being a Christian was a capital offense, because his investigations (conducted by interviewing some former or lapsed Christians, and also by examining under torture two slaves who were said to be deaconesses in the church) had revealed that the Christians, while practicing a “degenerate sort of cult,” were not guilty of committing any actual crimes. True, they did exhibit an “unshakeable obstinacy” that Pliny found irritating. But “obstinacy” was not a criminal offense, and, in fact, Pliny had discovered nothing more culpable than this. “The sum total of their guilt or error amounted to no more than this: they had met regularly before dawn on a fixed day to chant verses alternately amongst themselves in honour of Christ as if to a god, and also to bind themselves by oath not for any criminal purpose, but to abstain from theft, robbery, and adultery, to commit no breach of trust and not to deny a deposit when called upon to restore it.” Later they would “reassemble . . . to take food of an ordinary, harmless kind.” And even the predawn services and the later gatherings had been discontinued after Pliny, in accordance with a general Roman policy disfavoring private assemblies, had issued an edict forbidding such meetings.6
Despite their seemingly innocuous or even laudable behavior, Pliny had been sentencing people to death, evidently merely for being Christians. But he wondered whether he was doing the right thing.
In his response, Trajan expressed approval of Pliny’s approach. Christians should not be aggressively “hunted out,” Trajan cautioned, and they should be treated with due process in “keeping with the spirit of our age.” But if brought before the governor, they “must be punished.” Meaning, it seems, executed, since that was the punishment Pliny had been dispensing. There was no need to prove any independent offense; being Christian was enough. Accused persons could obtain pardon, though, by recanting and “by offering prayers to our gods.”7
And why exactly should people be put to death merely for being Christian? Pliny had raised the question, but Trajan tendered no answer.
Just under a century later, the why question was raised again—albeit this time indignantly—by a feisty Christian lawyer living in Carthage. Addressed to the “rulers of the Roman Empire,” Tertullian’s Apology demanded some justification for “the extreme severities inflicted on our people.”8 In most respects, Tertullian insisted, Christians were no different from other Romans. “We sojourn with you in the world, abjuring neither forum, nor shambles [slaughterhouse], nor bath, nor booth, nor workshop, nor inn, nor weekly market, nor any other places of commerce. We sail with you, and fight with you, and till the ground with you; and in like manner we unite with you in your traffickings” (69).
Nor were Christians unfaithful citizens, Tertullian protested. On the contrary: Christians obeyed the law, cared for their poor (64), and supported the government. “Without ceasing, for all our emperors we offer prayer. We pray for life prolonged; for security to the empire; for protection to the imperial house; for brave armies, a faithful senate, a virtuous people, the world at rest, whatever, as man or Caesar, an emperor would wish” (54–55).
Tertullian acknowledged that Christian theological doctrines might seem far-fetched to sophisticated Romans. But these doctrines “are just (in that case) like many other things on which you inflict no penalties—foolish and fabulous things, I mean, which, as quite innocuous, are never charged as crimes or punished” (80–81).
And yet, “with our hands thus stretched out and up to God, [you] rend us with your iron claws, hang us up on crosses, wrap us in flames, take our heads from us with the sword, let loose the wild beasts upon us” (55). And these savage punishments were inflicted merely because someone was Christian. “The mere name is made [a] matter of accusation, the mere name is assailed, and a sound alone brings condemnation” (8).
That punishments were inflicted merely for the status of being Christian was underscored, Tertullian thought, by the fact that, in stark contrast to how they treated other offenses, Roman authorities were quick to forgive anyone who renounced Christianity. “Certainly you give no ready credence to others when they deny [a criminal accusation]. When we deny you believe at once” (5). “Seeing, then, that in everything you deal differently with us than with other criminals, bent upon the one object of taking from us our name [of Christian], . . . it is made clear that there is no crime of any kind in the case, but merely a name” (6).
Roman persecution of the Christians may seem all the more puzzling in light of the Romans’ reputation for broad-minded religious toleration. Under the empire, as we will see in chapter 3, a vast and diverse array of deities, rituals, cults, and temples flourished in relative harmony. As the Romans had conquered the various lands of the Mediterranean world, they had typically left intact as much of the local government, culture, and religion as possible: so long as the subjects accepted Roman rule, eschewed subversion, and paid their taxes, the Romans were generally content to leave well enough alone. Thus, the renowned and immensely erudite historian Edward Gibbon (with whom we will frequently consult) lauded the empire for its “universal spirit of toleration.”9 Jonathan Kirsch, a popular historian, describes the “open-minded and easygoing attitude of paganism.”10 The eminent Yale historian Ramsey MacMullen describes Rome as “completely tolerant, in heaven as on earth.”11
Why, then, did the Romans feel impelled to torture, banish, and execute people for, as Tertullian claimed, “the mere name” of Christ?
It might have been, of course, that Christianity was associated with subversive or antisocial conduct; “the mere name” might have been evidence of, or perhaps a rough proxy for, crime or subversion. Or at least the Roman authorities might have thought so. Could that have been the reason why they were torturing and executing people for being Christian?
But what other criminal or subversive behavior could be associated with the religion? In the first centuries of its existence, to be sure, Christianity was the source of shocking rumors. Christians were said to indulge in incest, cannibalism, and wild orgies. One story had it that Christians covered an infant with flour, then killed him, cut him up, and drank his blood. Another exotic rumor intimated that on their holy days, Christians of both sexes and of all ages mingled together to feast and drink; they then tied a dog to the lamp and provoked the dog to run, putting out the light, and in the darkness each Christian indiscriminately indulged in sexual intercourse with whomever happened to be nearest to him or her.12
Tertullian treated these sorts of slanders with contempt, and historians have generally given them little credence.13 Rumors of cannibalism may have reflected uncomprehending and hostile inferences drawn from the Christian practice of eating the consecrated bread with the belief that it became the body of Christ; suspicions of incest might have arisen as a reaction to the Christian custom of calling each other (including spouses) “brother” and “sister.”14 In any case, it seems unlikely that Roman authorities believed such rumors. Pliny surely didn’t; as noted, his investigations uncovered only innocuous or exemplary behavior.
And yet he executed Christians anyway. Pliny was a proper gentleman and official who wanted to do the right thing, and he had no deep-seated or idiosyncratic animosity toward Christianity. But he thought that as a Roman governor, his duty was to execute convicted Christians. And in this he was evidently correct, as the emperor’s response to his query confirmed. But, once again, why?
We will return to the question in due course. For now, let us turn to another question, or perhaps to a different version of the same question, raised in a more contemporary setting.
Laycock’s Question
Douglas Laycock is an agnostic, a libertarian, and a law professor who has been called “the preeminent lawyer-scholar of religious freedom over the last quarter-century”;15 and he raises a timely question that has surely occurred to others as well. Commenting on recent cases in which same-sex couples have sued marriage counselors or photographers or florists or other professionals who have objected on religious grounds to assisting with same-sex unions, Laycock observes that in most such cases these professionals’ services are readily available from other counselors or providers who do not have any such objection. Moreover, he suggests, no sensible same-sex couple would actually want the services of, say, a counselor who is religiously opposed to their union.16 Why, then, do these parties insist on suing people whose services they neither need nor want?
Here, though, a small correction is needed, and also an addition. Laycock presents the point I have just described not so much as a question but more as an accusation. He says the plaintiffs in these cases are trying not to gain a needed remedy but rather to drive traditionally religious professionals out of business, and he says the plaintiffs are doing this because they are intolerant.17 In addition, Laycock makes a similar accusation against Christians who oppose same-sex marriage or who favor other sorts of regulations of sexual activity: these Christians are also being intolerant. Laycock the libertarian is visibly frustrated with both sides in these culture-war issues: a perfectly good “live and let live” arrangement is available, he thinks, but each side rejects it. Each side persecutes the other even when there is no good reason to do so and nothing to gain. “Each side wants a total win.”18
Laycock’s “intolerance” interpretation of the contending parties and their motivations is contestable, to be sure.19 But suppose he is right; even so, his accusation of intolerance is more a characterization than an actual explanation of the conflicts he is commenting on. Let us stipulate that it is intolerant to sue people you disagree with, or to restrict their private sexual behavior, when they are not interfering with your ability to live your own life. Fine. But the question still looms: Why would you do that? Except for the handful of perverse or opportunistic souls who revel in litigation or who hope to win some large damage award, becoming embroiled in a lawsuit is a highly unpleasant and unprofitable way to pass one’s days. And it is costly and time-consuming to enact and enforce regulations of, say, sexual behavior you disapprove of. So if (as Laycock supposes) the same-sex couples have no legitimate interest in litigating and the Christians have no legitimate interest in regulating, why do they waste their time and money on these profitless activities?
Although the stakes are not presently as high as they were for Tertullian and his beleaguered coreligionists, this contemporary question seems to have much in common with the Christian apologist’s complaint. In each case, people are using the law to crack down on a religion or a way of life that they disapprove of but that doesn’t seem to be realistically harming them or interfering with their own lives in any obvious way. Why would they do that?
It is a large and important question, not amenable to any quick response. As with Pliny’s and Tertullian’s question, we will return to it in due course. First, though, let us shift our focus for a moment and consider a proposal that, if sound (as it will likely not appear at first to be), might circle back to offer some insight into these puzzles.
A Poet’s Proposal
In the dark days just preceding World War II, the celebrated if often inscrutable poet T. S. Eliot presented a series of lectures at Cambridge University. Published under the title The Idea of a Christian Society,20 Eliot’s lectures advanced a thesis that, though it may seem prima facie implausible and even offensive to contemporary readers, is at least intriguing. For our purposes, the argument might be summarized in terms of three main claims—one predictive, one interpretive, one prescriptive.
The predictive claim was that the future of Western societies would be determined by a contest between Christianity and a rival that Eliot described as “modern paganism” (48). “I believe,” he told his English audience, “that the choice before us is between the formation of a new Christian culture, and the acceptance of a pagan one” (10). Looking outward to America and the Dominions, similarly, Eliot declared that “if these countries are to develop a positive culture of their own, . . . they can only proceed either in the direction of a pagan or of a Christian society” (36).
The interpretive claim was that Western societies as of his time should be characterized as “Christian”—but not because they were deeply or consciously Christian in any substantial sense. On the contrary, Eliot looked out on the world and perceived a religious and cultural muddle. Regarding “the division between Christians and non-Christians,” he observed, “the great majority of people are neither one thing nor the other, but are living in a no man’s land” (39). In this muddled situation, people’s self-labeling could not be taken at face value. “In the present ubiquity of ignorance, one cannot but suspect that many who call themselves Christians do not understand what the word means, and that some who would vigorously repudiate Christianity are more Christian than many who maintain it” (34–35). Still, Western societies had once been Christian, and “a society has not ceased to be Christian until it has positively become something else” (10). And that, he thought, had not happened. Not yet, anyway.
Eliot’s interpretive claim about a society’s character was analogous to the law’s treatment of domicile: you remain a domiciliary of a state until you establish domicile in a different state. So if you were born and raised in Kansas, say, then although you may have wandered the globe for the last half-century without in all that time setting foot in Kansas, until you establish a permanent residence somewhere else you will still be a domiciliary of Kansas.21 In a similar way, Eliot thought that England and other Western societies had once been Christian, and until they became “positively something else,” they would remain “Christian” societies—even if there was precious little Christianity left in them.
Eliot’s prescriptive claim was that a Christian society is preferable to a pagan one. Not that a Christian society, or at least one that could possibly be achieved, would be any sort of Shangri-La. On the contrary. “We must remember that whatever reform or revolution we carry out, the result will always be a sordid travesty of what human society should be.”22 Eliot understood as well that his preference for a Christian society would not find ready acceptance with the kind of people who attend learned lectures at eminent universities like Cambridge—or, for that matter, anywhere else.23 But he suggested that the other option was even less inviting. “A Christian society only becomes acceptable after you have fairly examined the alternatives.”24 And once those alternatives—the “pagan” alternatives—are considered, it becomes apparent, he thought, that “the only hopeful course for a society which would thrive and continue its creative activity in the arts of civilisation, is to become Christian. That prospect involves, at least, discipline, inconvenience and discomfort: but here as hereafter the alternative to hell is purgatory.”25
There is little in this position that seems calculated to elicit assent or even sympathy in educated readers today. Such an audience will not merely disagree with Eliot’s preference for a Christian society; it will likely find his description of the alternatives puzzling, or perverse. Perhaps with some less than welcome help from so-called Christian Reconstructionists,26 we might form some dim idea of what a modern Christian society might look like. And we can concoct imaginary scenarios—albeit fantastic and probably dystopian ones—by which such a society might come about.27 But paganism? Seriously?
Indeed, what would it even mean to embrace, today, a “pagan” society? To revive the practice of sacrificing bulls to Apollo? To make important political and military decisions by poring over the entrails of animals, or by studying the flight patterns of birds? Nobody, surely nobody worth bothering about, wants anything like that. As Thomas Bulfinch wrote (with perhaps a tinge of regret?) in the introduction to his famous book of mythology: “The religions of ancient Greece and Rome are extinct. The so-called divinities of Olympus have not a single worshipper among living men.”28
Nor need we turn to secularists to press this objection. Consider this observation from another lecture, also given at Cambridge by a literary Anglican, a decade and a half after Eliot’s presentation. In a talk inaugurating a chair in Renaissance and medieval literature, C. S. Lewis commented:
It is hard to have patience with those Jeremiahs, in press or pulpit, who warn us that we are “relapsing into Paganism.” It might be rather fun if we were. It would be pleasant to see some future Prime Minister trying to kill a large and lively milk-white bull in Westminster Hall. But we shan’t. What lurks behind such idle prophecies, if they are anything but careless language, is the false idea that the historical process allows mere reversal; that Europe can come out of Christianity “by the same door as in she went” and find herself back where she was. It is not what happens. A post-Christian man is not a Pagan; you might as well think that a married woman recovers her virginity by divorce. The post-Christian is cut off from the Christian past and therefore doubly from the Pagan past.29
Given such peremptorily dismissive criticism from a fellow in the faith, Eliot’s thesis may seem hopeless. And if “paganism” is equated with sacrificing bulls to Zeus, or perhaps with fantastic stories about whimsical or lascivious deities, the thesis would indeed be irredeemable. (Although given Lewis’s ample use of fauns and dryads and satyrs and such in his own stories, one might wonder why he in particular should be so dismissive of paganism, even in this fairly literal sense.)
We might, but probably should not, deflect Lewis’s criticism by speaking not of “paganism” but rather of something like a “classical” orientation or worldview. “Classical” is a more respectable quality, and it is possible to revere the “classical” culture of the ancient Greeks and Romans without endorsing the religious subcomponent described as “paganism.” Indeed, this stance (manifest in, among many other sites, the celebrated epic history of Rome’s decline by Edward Gibbon) is by now utterly familiar. Nor is there anything especially unsettling about the claim that the modern world has in many ways returned to a “classical” perspective and culture: as it happens, this is the central claim of a recent book by Ferdinand Mount explaining, as its subtitle suggests, “how the classical world came back to us.”30
And yet, it would be a mistake to try to salvage Eliot’s thesis through this kind of amendment. Though it may incite resistance, the term “paganism” is preferable to “classical,” I think. Not merely because it is more provocative, nor because Eliot used it, but because it retains a recognition of something I think Eliot meant (and in any case, should have meant) to recognize: namely, that religion—or what we would call “religion”—was central to and not detachable from the much-admired classical approach to culture and sexuality and politics.
To be sure, Eliot referred not to “paganism” simpliciter, but rather to “modern paganism.” That term might of course be nothing more than an unilluminating pejorative. Conversely, it might be that beneath the surface features or manifestations, there is some more substantive continuity perspicuously connecting the classical perspectives and practices we call “paganism” with modern movements and views. In that case, Eliot’s thesis might provide insights that more conventional accounts of our situation do not. And it might turn out that just as Laycock’s question seems to be a variation on the question urgently pressed almost two millennia ago by Tertullian, so the answer to the contemporary question will turn out to be a modern version of the classical explanation.
That, at least, is the hypothesis on which this book proceeds. The book grows out of a project that I have thought of as an extended reflection on Eliot’s quixotic proposal. This project thus involves the consideration and defense of various claims that will seem counterintuitive, or worse, at least initially.
Why undertake such a project—one that is faced from the outset with daunting obstacles and entrenched incredulities? And why invite anyone else—namely, readers—to join in the project?
The answer, quite simply, is that Eliot’s diagnosis may provide much needed illumination. At the beginning of his first lecture, Eliot explained that he was advancing his admittedly unconventional interpretation in response to “immediate perplexities that fill our minds.”31 He declared as well his “suspicion that the current terms in which we discuss international affairs and political theory may only tend to conceal from us the real issues of contemporary civilisation.”32 Indeed, “the current terms in which we describe our society . . . only operate to deceive and stupefy us.”33 I have a similar suspicion.
But how have “current terms . . . tend[ed] to conceal from us the real issues of contemporary civilisation”? Well, here is one possibility. Modern understandings of history and culture commonly work against the backdrop of a story in which history unfolds in stages, one replacing the other: once retired, past stages are gone for good. Been there, done that. More specifically, an ancient and classical world culturally dominated by what is often called “paganism” eventually gave way to a medieval world presided over by Christianity, which in turn was gradually superseded by a modern world characterized by “secularism.” So we live today in “a secular age,” as the title of a hefty book by the philosopher Charles Taylor has it.34 History does not stop, and so we may move on—indeed, we may already be in a “postsecular” period, as some observers claim—but there is no going back to earlier stages of Christendom or paganism.
Something like this historical story and this “no going back” progressive conception of how history unfolds is taken as virtually axiomatic by educated people today. Thus, in culture-war controversies over matters like same-sex marriage, traditionalists and holdouts are frequently warned against being on “the wrong side of history.” The progressive conception informs the confident dismissal of the possibility of modern paganism even by traditionalist religious thinkers like C. S. Lewis. The “historical process,” Lewis declares, does not “[allow] mere reversal. . . . It is not what happens.”
The conception of history as progressing—as moving from pagan to Christian to secular—widely informs our interpretations of current cultural struggles, which are often depicted as conflicts between progressive “secular” constituencies and holdover “religious” actors. And yet, this “secular versus religious” framework increasingly seems inadequate. That is because the parties and factions on all sides of the culture wars exhibit qualities standardly associated with “religion”: an uncompromising zeal or passion, a tendency to view issues in “good versus evil” or “light versus darkness” terms, an eagerness to demonize opponents. These are the features that Laycock finds so dismaying in the current culture wars. Perhaps surprisingly, and distressingly, similar tendencies—and in particular, an eagerness to resort to the rhetoric of demonization—are starkly evident even in some decisions of the United States Supreme Court.35
At least a few observers have recognized that our current cultural struggles are most perspicuously described as a contest between competing religiosities.36 But between which religiosities? One party, though complex, has a familiar feel to it—it is composed mostly of traditional Catholics and evangelicals and devout Jews, uneasily allied with Mormons and perhaps a few Muslims. But what sort of religiosity animates the other side?
This is where Eliot’s proposal might provide some help. Both the implausibility and the potential illumination in his proposal derive from the fact that it implicitly departs from the standard, taken-for-granted view of Western history as a one-directional advance from one stage to another (pagan, to Christian, to secular, to . . . postsecular?) and instead discerns an ongoing contest between two contrasting and enduring religiosities or orientations. In the classical world, one of these orientations was most conspicuously (though not solely) manifest in Christianity; the competing orientation was manifest in what came to be called “paganism.” And those contesting orientations remain active today—or so Eliot’s diagnosis suggests—in shaping our culture, our politics, and our world. They were and are foundational to the practices that provoked Pliny’s question almost two millennia ago, and that provoke Douglas Laycock’s question today. The investigation and defense of Eliot’s proposal thus offer an oblique but potentially revealing way of addressing the questions noted earlier in this chapter.
That investigation and defense will require considerable work, as well as a willingness to examine and perhaps reconsider our ingrained attachment to some current assumptions that are often taken for granted. We have already noticed one of those entrenched assumptions—the assumption that history moves forward from one phase to another, leaving past phases irretrievably behind. Another common assumption that we will discuss is the widespread conception, pervasive and influential in the academy, of human beings as bearers of “interests” who live and act primarily to further those interests (and who, accordingly, need to be understood and explained as “rational interest-seekers”). In contrast to this conception (though not necessarily in contradiction to it) is the possibility that humans—or many humans—have an essential religious dimension, and that without appreciating this religious dimension we will not understand what people are or why they behave in the ways they do.
Such assumptions about the nature of human beings are presupposed in all discussions of human affairs, and so we will need to consider them at the outset. Then we will turn to the Rome of late antiquity and observe the struggles, sometimes inconspicuous and sometimes quite open, between “paganism” (as it came to be called) and Christianity. We will see how these contrasting religiosities reflected basic existential orientations that could not easily coexist in peace. The tension led to the back-and-forth political struggle of the fourth century between Christianity and paganism.
But although Christianity ultimately prevailed in that struggle as an official and political matter, we will see that the contrasting orientations endured: though officially defeated, paganism as a distinctive existential orientation persisted through the centuries in uneasy collaboration and contention with an official Christianity. And in recent decades, that position has become more open and confident. It is readily discernible, for example, in the work of respected and thoroughly “secular” thinkers like Ronald Dworkin, Sam Harris, and Barbara Ehrenreich.
Finally, we will return to the present and consider how the conflict between the kind of religiosity represented by Christianity and that reflected in paganism can help to make sense of our present situation.
Why go to the trouble? But I have already said: the motivation for the undertaking is the hope of illumination. My goal is the same as Eliot’s—to see through and past “the current terms [that] only tend to conceal from us the real issues of contemporary civilisation.”37
In addition, I should at the outset make, a fortiori, the same disclaimer Eliot did: “This is a subject which I could, no doubt, handle much better were I a profound scholar in any of several fields. But I am not writing for scholars, but for people like myself.”38 For people, scholars or not, who find our times perplexing, and troubling, and who find the standard “religious versus secular” interpretations and explanations unsatisfying. Perhaps Eliot will provide some help. We will see.
1. Pliny’s numerous letters to the emperor Trajan are filled with flattery. “I am well aware, Sir, that no higher tribute can be paid to my reputation than some mark of favour from so excellent a ruler as yourself.” The Letters of the Younger Pliny, trans. Betty Radice (London: Penguin, 1963), 265. Such praise pervades the letters; see 260, 264, 277, 291, 296.
2. The letter is reprinted in Letters of the Younger Pliny, 293–95.
3. For a careful analysis of the episode, see Robert Louis Wilken, The Christians as the Romans Saw Them, 2nd ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003), 15–30.
4. Letters of the Younger Pliny, 293.
5. Letters of the Younger Pliny, 293.
6. Letters of the Younger Pliny, 294.
7. Letters of the Younger Pliny, 295.
8. Tertullian, “Apology,” in Selected Works (Pickering, OH: Beloved, 2014), 1. Hereafter, page references from this work will be given in parentheses in the text.
9. Edward Gibbon, The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, 2 vols. (London: Penguin, [1776] 1995), 1:56.
10. Jonathan Kirsch, God against the Gods: The History of the War between Monotheism and Polytheism (New York: Penguin, 2004), 63.
11. MacMullen quickly qualifies this description by noting that Romans were sometimes severe on Jews, Christians, Druids, and a few others, but he mitigates the observation with the explanation that in these instances “humanitarian views were the cause, not bigotry.” Ramsay MacMullen, Paganism in the Roman Empire (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), 2. See also Ramsay MacMullen, Christianity and Paganism in the Fourth to Eighth Centuries (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997), 2 (referring to classical paganism’s “spongy mass of tolerance and tradition”).
12. These rumors are reported in Minucius Felix, “Octavius,” in Ante-Nicene Church Fathers, Fathers of the Third Century, trans. Philip Schaff (London: Aeterna Press, 2014), vol. 8, chap. 9, pp. 10–11. See also Keith Hopkins, A World Full of Gods: The Strange Triumph of Christianity (New York: Penguin, 1999), 209; Gibbon, History of the Decline, 1:522.
13. See, e.g., Stephen Benko, Pagan Rome and the Early Christians (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984), 60–64; E. R. Dodds, Pagan and Christian in an Age of Anxiety (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 112. However, it is possible that one bizarre and renegade group associated with Christianity—the Carpocratians—did indulge in seriously licentious conduct. Benko, 64.
14. See James J. O’Donnell, Pagans: The End of Traditional Religion and the Rise of Christianity (New York: HarperCollins, 2015), 79.
15. True, he was called that by me. Steven D. Smith, “Lawyering Religious Liberty,” Texas Law Review 89 (2011): 917. But although not everyone would give the same assessment, Laycock’s stature in the field is undeniable. Thomas C. Berg, “Laycock’s Legacy,” Texas Law Review 89 (2011): 901 (“Douglas Laycock is a towering figure in the law of religious liberty”).
16. See, e.g., Douglas Laycock and Thomas C. Berg, “Protecting Same-Sex Marriage and Religious Liberty,” Virginia Law Review 99, in Brief 1 (2013): 9 (“Of course, no same-sex couple would ever want to be counseled by such a counselor. Demanding a commitment to counsel same-sex couples does not obtain counseling for those couples, but it does threaten to drive from the helping professions all those who adhere to other religious understandings of marriage”). On the practical futility of asking a counselor to counsel people contrary to the counselor’s religious commitments, see Joseph Turner, “Counselors like Me Need Conscience Protections like Tennessee’s,” Federalist, May 3, 2016, http://thefederalist.com/2016/05/03/counselors-like-me-need-conscience-protections-like-tennessees.
17. Laycock and Berg, “Protecting Same-Sex Marriage,” 9.
18. Douglas Laycock, “Religious Liberty and the Culture Wars,” University of Illinois Law Review 2014 (2014): 879.
19. See Steven D. Smith, “Die and Let Live: The Asymmetry of Accommodation,” Southern California Law Review 88 (2015): 703.
20. T. S. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” in Christianity and Culture (New York: Harcourt/Harvest, 1948), 36. Hereafter, page references from this work will be given in parentheses in the text.
21. See, e.g., White v. Tennant, 31 W. Va. 790 (1888).
22. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 47.
23. “Paganism,” he acknowledged, “holds all the most valuable advertising space.” Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 18.
24. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 18.
25. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 18–19.
26. See, e.g., Rousas John Rushdoony, Christianity and the State (Vallecito, CA: Ross House Books, 1986).
27. See, e.g., Margaret Atwood, The Handmaid’s Tale (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 1985).
28. Thomas Bulfinch, Bulfinch’s Mythology (New York: Collier Books, [1867] 1962), 13.
29. C. S. Lewis, “De Descriptione Temporum” (lecture, Cambridge University, Cambridge, 1954), https://archive.org/details/DeDescriptioneTemporum.
30. Ferdinand Mount, Full Circle: How the Classical World Came Back to Us (New York: Simon and Schuster, 2010).
31. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 5.
32. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 3.
33. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 6–7.
34. Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007).
35. See, e.g., United States v. Windsor, 133 S. Ct. 2675 (2013). For discussion, see Steven D. Smith, “The Jurisprudence of Denigration,” U.C. Davis Law Review 48 (2014): 675–701.
36. See, e.g., William Voegeli, “That New-Time Religion,” Claremont Review of Books 15, no. 3 (Summer 2015): 12 (reviewing several books that interpret current cultural conflicts as a clash of competing religiosities).
37. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 3.
38. Eliot, “The Idea of a Christian Society,” 5.