Most empirical tests of the many competing theories of wage rigidity use publicly available data on pay rates and employment that reveal little about the institutions and motivations that explain wage behavior. In order to learn more, some economists have analyzed unusual sources of data or have conducted surveys and experiments. Management scientists and organizational psychologists have for years been collecting data relevant to wage rigidity. I here report on what I know of these sources of information about the origins of wage rigidity.
It is sensible to check whether wages really are downwardly rigid before considering why this is the case. This question is surprisingly hard to answer, because appropriate data are lacking. It is not even clear what the appropriate definition of the wage should be. A firm’s marginal costs depend on the average hourly nominal labor cost per job. Employee welfare depends on total nominal compensation per worker. A third possibility is nominal compensation for an employee with a given job tenure and continuing in the same position with the same employer under fixed working conditions. If the employee is paid by the hour, it is the hourly rate plus the fringe benefits that count. Total compensation is the relevant pay rate for salaried employees, where total compensation is the salary plus fringe benefits and bonuses. This third definition is the one most closely associated with employees’ and managers’notions of fairness and hence is most pertinent to the managerial concerns that explain downward wage rigidity. In order to adhere even more closely to the sense of fairness prevailing in business, it might be advisable to include only base pay and exclude variable components, such as bonuses. The three pay rates can change independently. For instance, the average hourly labor costs of a job can increase with no change in any worker’s pay, if the seniority of workers assigned to the job increases. Similarly, changes in hours worked or in job assignments can change an individual’s total pay without changing hourly pay rates or labor costs for any job. There are conceptual ambiguities associated with benefits. For instance, if an increase in the cost of a given medical insurance policy were shared between a firm and its workforce, the firm’s nominal labor cost per job would increase, but workers would probably feel that the total value of their medical benefits had decreased.
A wage cut should be defined as a reduction in the wage of the third definition above, the pay of an employee continuing to work under unchanged conditions. Unfortunately, this pay rate is the most difficult to measure, because it requires knowledge of much more than just total pay.
Lebow et al. (2003) is the only study I know of that measures the first definition of wage, the firm’s average labor costs. The authors use U.S. Bureau of Labor Statistics data and find that wage costs are somewhat rigid in the downward direction, though there is a considerable amount of wage reduction.
There is a large literature that uses surveys of the income of individual workers to study variation in the third kind of wage. The sources of data are household panel surveys and social security data. The studies include McLaughlin (1994, 1999), Lebow et al. (1995), Card and Hyslop (1997), Kahn (1997), Goux (1997), Altonji and Devereux (2000), Smith (2000, 2002), Beissinger and Knoppik (2001, 2003), and Fehr and Götte (2005). Some of these authors struggled with possible errors in the reporting of earnings. All of the studies suffer from ignorance of changes in hours worked, job assignments, bonuses, or working conditions, so that it is not clear that the data reveal the wage of the third definition. All the studies report large amounts of wage reduction. Goux is able to attribute about 60% of the pay reductions to better working conditions as from a change from night to day shift, a change in occupation, or a change in the annual bonus. She has no information on changes in hours worked. None of the other authors have had such detailed information. The difficulties of the surveys cited are discussed in Kramarz (2001) and Howitt (2002).
Surveys of firms reach conflicting conclusions on wage rigidity. Kaufman (1984), Blinder and Choi (1990), Agell and Lundborg (1999, 2003), Agell and Bennmarker (2002, 2003), and Bewley (1999) simply asked employers whether they had reduced pay. The responses probably apply to the third definition of wage, but one cannot be sure. None of the firms in Kaufman’s sample of twenty-six British firms had considered nominal wage cuts during the recession occurring at the time of his study. Blinder and Choi found a high incidence of pay reduction, in five of the nineteen American firms they studied. Agell and Lundborg, on the other hand, found almost no wage cutting; two out of 153 responding Swedish firms had experienced nominal wage cuts during the previous seven years, a period of high unemployment and low inflation. Agell and Bennmarker found that only 1.1% of workers received a pay cut during the deep recession in Sweden in the 1990s. The wage cuts that did occur were for just a few employees. Swedish laws that make it difficult to reduce pay may explain the near absence of wage cutting in the studies by Agell and his coauthors. Although I conducted my survey during a recession and actively sought out firms that had cut pay, I found a low incidence of pay cuts; of 235 businesses studied, 24 had reduced the base pay of some or all employees during the recession of the early 1990s.
Similarly conflicting results appear in surveys of union wage agreements. In Current Wage Developments and the Monthly Labor Review, the Bureau of Labor Statistics reports on general wage changes for both union and nonunion manufacturing production workers for the years 1959 through 1978. These data show a negligible number of wage reductions: cuts for less than 0.5% of the workers in every year.2 (The corresponding percentage for my sample was 0.14%.) Conflicting evidence has been found by Mitchell (1985), who uses Bureau of Labor Statistics data to calculate that 13% of all workers covered by major new contracts suffered wage cuts in 1983. Similarly, Fortin (1996) finds that 6% of 1,149 large non-COLA union wage settlements in Canada from 1992 to 1994 involved wage cuts.
Much less ambiguous evidence of downward rigidity in the third kind of wage is contained in the few studies that use company records to learn the histories of job assignments, hours worked, and pay of individual employees. The studies include Baker et al. (1994), Wilson (1997), Altonji and Devereux (2000), Dohmen (2003), and Fehr and Götte (2005). Unfortunately, these authors study only six firms. Baker et al. study one firm. Wilson studies two, one of which is the firm studied by Baker et al. Altonji and Devereux study a third. Dohmen studies a bankrupt Dutch firm, and Fehr and Götte study two Swiss firms. Altonji and Devereux, Dohmen, and Fehr and Götte report data on both hourly and salaried workers. The other two studies have information only on salaried employees. All five studies find a negligible number of pay reductions. Altonji and Devereux find that 2.5% of hourly workers experienced wage cuts, but almost all of these were “associated with changes between full-and part-time status, or with changes in whether performance incentives are part of compensation.” These findings are reinforced by a telephone survey that Akerlof et al. (1996) made of 596 people in the Washington, DC, area. The key question was: “Excluding overtime, commissions, and bonuses, has your base rate of pay changed since a year ago today?” A negligible number reported pay reductions. Given the form of the question, this evidence probably pertains to the third definition of wages. Contradicting this evidence are two similar surveys conducted in New Zealand in 1992 and 1993, where 8% and 5%, respectively, of the respondents reported hourly wage reductions (Chapple 1996, Tables 2 and 3). More work should be done: no one has yet conducted a large survey that accurately measures the incidence of cuts in pay according to the third definition.
There are eight surveys by economists of business managers responsible for compensation policy. The goal of seven of these was to learn the reasons for downward wage rigidity, the studies of Kaufman (1984), Blinder and Choi (1990), two surveys by Agell and Lundborg (1995, 1999, 2003), and single studies by Campbell and Kamlani (1997), Bewley (1999), and by Agell and Bennmarker (2002, 2003). The eighth study, that of Levine (1993), also contains relevant information. Although the findings of the studies differ to some extent, they give a consistent picture of the sources of wage rigidity. I also discuss a paper by Smith (2002), who analyzes a survey of British workers.
I first summarize my own findings, based on interviews with 246 company managers and nineteen labor leaders in the Northeast of the United States during the early 1990s, when unemployment was high because of a recession. I present my findings as reflecting the views of managers, though labor leaders had almost exactly the same opinions on the matters discussed. The primary resistance to wage reduction comes from upper management, not from employees. The main reason for avoiding pay cuts is that they damage morale. Morale has three components. One is identification with the firm and an internalization of its objectives. Another is trust in an implicit exchange with the firm and with other employees; employees know that aid given to the firm or to coworkers will eventually be reciprocated, even if it goes unnoticed. The third component is a mood that is conducive to good work. The mood need not be a happy one, though happiness is important for the performance of some jobs, such as those that involve dealing with customers. The mood could be dislike of an unpleasant job combined with grim focus on achievement or pride in accomplishment. Good morale is not equivalent to happiness or job satisfaction. Workers may be content, simply because they do nothing. Good morale has to do with a willingness voluntarily to make sacrifices for the company and for coworkers.
A general sense of fairness is conducive to good morale; it contributes to an atmosphere of mutual trust. The sense of fairness is created by having supervisors treat workers decently, by having impartial rules for settling disputes and determining promotions and job assignments, and by using reasonable standards for setting the relative pay of different employees. These standards are often elaborate systems and are termed internal pay structures. They fix pay differentials on the basis of such factors as training, experience, tenure at the firm, and productivity. The structures are extremely important, because perceived pay inequity within a firm can cause indignation and disrupt work. The standards of internal equity are somewhat arbitrary and can depend strongly on company tradition.
The pay standards often do not specify that pay be proportional to productivity. Many employers believe that productivity of the workforce as a whole is maximized if pay does not fully reflect productivity, though some individuals might produce more if given stronger financial incentives. There is a division of opinion within business about how sensitive pay should be to productivity. Big income differentials due to differences in productivity can cause resentment, especially if productivity is difficult to measure, which it often is. Many firms, nevertheless, use piece rates when productivity can be measured unambiguously, and, even when piece rates are impractical, ordinary notions of equity require that differences in people’s contributions be rewarded financially to some extent. The sensitivity of pay to productivity may be blunted by the influence on pay of other factors, such as longevity with the firm. No matter how sensitive the pay of individuals is to their productivity, firms automatically keep the average pay of broad categories of workers roughly equal to the average value of their marginal product by adjusting the number of workers in each category to the profit-maximizing level.
Managers are concerned about morale because of its impact on labor turnover, on recruitment of new employees, and on productivity. Disgruntled employees are likely to quit as soon as they find another job. A company’s best recruiters are its employees, so that it is important not to have them complain about their company. Morale has little impact on productivity in the sense of speed in carrying out routine tasks. Habit and working conditions largely determine this sort of productivity. Managers have in mind the impact of morale on workers’ willingness to do the extra thing, to encourage and help each other, to make suggestions, and to work well even when not supervised. Also, workers with bad morale waste time complaining to each other. In considering the impact of morale on productivity, it is important to realize that supervision is so expensive that many employees are not closely supervised and have a significant amount of freedom on the job. Except in some low-level jobs, employers rely on workers’ voluntary cooperation and do not simply give orders.
When considering why wage cuts hurt morale, it is necessary to distinguish new from existing employees. The morale of existing employees is hurt by pay cuts, because of an insult effect and a standard-of-living effect. Workers are used to receiving regular pay increases as a reward for good work and loyalty, and so interpret a pay cut as an affront and a breach of implicit reciprocity, even if the pay of all employees is reduced. Individual workers may take a pay cut less personally if everyone’s pay falls, but when everyone in a company suffers they stimulate each other’s discontent by griping. The standard-of-living effect is the resentment caused by the fall in income; workers blame their employer when they find their lifestyles curtailed. This effect is closely related to what experimental economists call loss aversion.
The arguments just given do not apply to newly hired workers. They probably would hardly care if their firm had a general pay cut just before they were hired. It is possible, however, to reduce the pay of newly hired workers while continuing to give normal pay increases to existing employees; new workers hired after a certain date would simply be paid according to a reduced pay scale. Firms have experimented with such two-tier pay structures, and managers say that new workers hired in the lower tier may be glad at first to have their jobs, but that later their attitude changes after they learn that their pay violates the traditional internal pay structure. They believe they were being treated unfairly, their resentment hurts their morale, and their discontent can spread to the senior workers on the old pay scale.
Resistance to wage reduction and the need for internal pay equity both stem from ideas of fairness that usually refer to some reference wage. The reference wage for pay cuts is the past wage. The reference wage for internal equity is that of other workers at the work place with similar qualifications and a similar job. The fairness of wages has little to do with profits or productivity, though both workers and managers find it appropriate that employees share in the success of their company. Although managers attempt to use reasonable criteria when establishing an internal pay structure, once a structure is established, tradition by itself makes it a standard of fairness.
The explanation of downward pay rigidity just given is closely related to the morale theory proposed by Solow (1979), Akerlof (1982), and Akerlof and Yellen (1988, 1990). They assert that morale and hence productivity increase with the wage and that the trade-off between labor costs and productivity determines a wage that is independent of the unemployment rate. Akerlof (1982) uses his gift-exchange model to explain the link between the wage and morale. According to this model, workers offer more effort than is demanded by the employer in exchange for pay rates in excess of market clearing levels, so that effort increases with the wage level. I do not believe that this theory is fully accurate, because employers say they do not see much connection between effort or morale and wage levels; productivity and morale do not increase when pay levels rise, though they can be hurt by pay reductions or disappointingly small raises. Even generous pay raises do not increase morale or productivity, because workers quickly get used to increases and grow to believe they have a right to them. They soon lose track of any idea that they should offer extra effort in exchange for higher pay. Employers do not think about a trade-off between labor costs and the productivity of existing employees when setting pay, though managers do consider the trade-off between labor costs and the quality of labor that a firm can attract and retain. In the theory of Akerlof, Solow, and Yellen, morale depends on the level of the wage, whereas in the explanation I have described, wages affect morale only when reduced. What is accurate in the Akerlof–Solow–Yellen theory is the idea that employers avoid cutting pay because doing so would hurt morale. What the theory misses is that employees usually have little notion of a fair or market value for their services and quickly come to believe they are entitled to their existing pay, no matter how high it may be. Workers usually do not use pay rates at other firms as reference wages, for they know too little about them.
Although pay cuts are unusual, they do occur and those that occur usually do not have the harmful effects described by managers when arguing that pay should not be cut. The explanation for this inconsistency is that pay cuts are accepted by the workforce if they prevent a firm from closing or if they save a large number of jobs. Managers were confident they could convince the workforce that a pay cut was necessary, if it were in fact so, and they do not cut pay unless they view the reduction as necessary.
One of the puzzles discussed in the literature on wage rigidity has been why firms lay off workers rather than reduce their pay. I found that most managers believe that the elasticity of their company’s demand for labor is so low that pay cuts would not reduce an excess supply of labor within the firm. The elasticity is small, because direct labor is a small fraction of marginal costs and the price elasticity of product demand is far from infinite. Only in firms with a high elasticity of product demand, such as construction companies, is it believed that pay cuts would significantly increase the demand for labor. Many of the pay cuts that occurred were made in such firms or in those that were in danger of closing. Other firms where pay reduction was an alternative to layoff were those that laid off workers simply to save money, not to get rid of excess labor, and there were many such companies. The main argument for preferring layoffs to pay cuts is that layoffs do less damage to morale. Laid off workers suffer, but they are no longer in the firm. In the words of one manager, “Layoffs get the misery out the door.” Good management practice is to save up potential layoffs, make a large number all at once, and then to assure workers who remain that there will be no more for some time. Any damage to morale from layoffs is temporary, whereas that from a pay reduction is long-term. Other arguments are that layoffs increase productivity, whereas pay cuts hurt it, and layoffs give management some control over who leaves, whereas the best workers are likely to quit when pay is reduced. The tendency for the best to quit is a concern in many firms, because the leveling effects of internal equity on pay mean that pay for workers within a job category increases less than their contribution to profits. Another consideration is that feasible layoffs often save much more money than feasible pay cuts, which usually cannot be more than about 20% of base pay. Layoffs save the fixed costs of employment, which are often substantial, whereas cuts in pay reduce only its variable part.
Another puzzle appearing in the economics literature is why unemployed workers do not try to take jobs away from employed people by offering to replace them at lower pay. Solow (1990) has proposed that the unemployed do not engage in such undercutting because of a social convention against it. I found that explicit undercutting is impossible for most people, because they do not know exactly what job they are applying for or what its pay is. However, it is not uncommon during periods of high unemployment for job applicants to offer to work for extremely low pay. These offers are not frowned upon, but are almost never accepted, because accepting the offers would violate the internal pay structure and could demoralize the new hire. Low offers may, however, lead to reduced pay during the initial probationary period of employment.
A similar puzzle is why firms do not take advantage of recessions to replace employees with cheaper unemployed ones. Lindbeck and Snower (1988) proposed, with their insider–outsider theory, that firms seldom replace workers because the employees who had not been replaced would harass and refuse to cooperate with and train the new ones, thereby reducing their productivity. I found that the main reasons employers do not replace employees are that the new ones would lack the skills of the existing ones and replacement would demoralize the workforce. The skills would be lost in part because many of them are specific to the firm. Managers agreed that, after replacement, workers who had not been replaced might boycott the new ones, but asserted that other factors took precedence over this possibility as an explanation of why employees were not replaced.
Keynes (1936) proposed that downward wage rigidity is explained by employees’ preoccupation with pay differentials with respect to workers in similar jobs at other firms. I found, however, that such external pay differentials are not an issue, except in highly unionized industries. In most companies, employees know so little about pay rates at other firms that they do not know whether they are underpaid. Although labor unions do try to keep their members informed of pay rates at other companies, unions are weak in the United States.
A popular explanation of wage rigidity is the “no shirking” theory of Shapiro and Stiglitz (1984). According to their model, managers induce workers to perform well by firing them if their productivity falls below a prescribed level. Job loss is more costly to the worker the higher is his or her wage, so that higher wages make it possible to insist on greater productivity. According to the theory, managers set the wage so as to optimize the trade-off between wage costs and productivity. This theory does not really explain downward wage rigidity, because it implies that wages should decline when unemployment increases. As unemployment rises, it becomes harder to find a new job, so that firing is more costly to the worker and the theory implies that firms can then obtain the same productivity at lower wages. Despite this drawback, the theory is so popular among economists that I frequently asked managers and labor leaders about it and was almost always told that it did not apply. As was explained in connection with Akerlof’s gift-exchange model, employers do not believe there is much connection between pay and morale, except when pay is reduced. Nor do employers obtain cooperation by threatening to fire shirkers. To do so would create a negative atmosphere that could damage morale and encourage rebeliousness. Workers may malinger on the job, but are seldom dismissed for doing so, except during the short probationary period after hiring. Shirking is usually dealt with through discussions and reprimands, and workers are normally fired only because of a pattern of egregious behavior. Managers elicit effort by explaining clearly what is expected, facing employees with their shortcomings in a constructive manner, pointing out the importance of the tasks performed, showing interest and appreciation, and making workers feel they are valued members of the organization. Most employees like to work and to cooperate and want to please their boss.
Despite the inapplicability of the “no shirking” theory, the incentive mechanism posited in it can be effective. For instance, employees do work harder during economic slowdowns, when new jobs are difficult to find and layoffs are imminent, especially if layoffs are made on the basis of performance, that is, if the least productive workers in a job category are laid off first. The increase in effort occurs both because job loss becomes more dangerous during a slowdown and because workers try to avoid layoff by being cooperative and productive. Because layoffs stem from circumstances not controlled by management, they do not generate the hostility that might be generated by systematically firing slackers.3
Although firing is not used to incite work effort, financial incentives are thought to be very effective in doing so and are believed not to impair morale. Incentives can even improve morale, because workers find it fair that they be rewarded for their contributions to the company. When incentives are not exaggerated, they contribute to internal equity. Discipline and even firing can do so as well, because workers who make the effort to do their job well and obey company rules can be outraged if they see others get away with flagrant misbehavior. The main purposes of firing are to protect the company from malefactors and incompetents and to maintain internal equity. Dismissals that are managed correctly earn managers respect. What is to be avoided is an atmosphere of retribution that menaces everyone. This assertion appears not to apply, however, to low-level jobs. There was evidence that employers do sometimes use coercion to motivate workers in low-paid jobs that require little training and where employees are easily supervised.
Another popular explanation of wage rigidity is the adverse selection model of Weiss (1980, 1990). There are two versions, having to do with quits and hiring, respectively. In the quits version, managers prefer layoffs to pay cuts, because the best workers leave if pay is reduced, whereas if managers lay off workers they can select those who leave. According to the hiring version, managers believe that the higher the level of pay that a job applicant is willing to accept, the higher is his or her unobservable quality, and pay offers to new hires are determined by the trade-off between worker quality and pay. Weiss asserts that the relation between pay and job candidate quality is determined by alternative employment in the secondary sector, where quality is perfectly observable. The secondary sector is home production or jobs that have high turnover and are usually part-time. The hiring version of Weiss’s adverse selection theory applies to the primary sector, where jobs are long-term and usually full-time. He assumes that real wages in the secondary sector are downwardly rigid because of constant returns to labor in production there. According to the theory, this downward rigidity is then transferred to the primary sector through the impact of adverse selection on hiring pay.
I found strong support for Weiss’s theory as it applies to quits, but none as it applies to hiring. Although managers do believe that a pay cut would cause their best employees to quit, I found no evidence that recruiters use pay aspirations as an indicator of job candidate quality. Job recruiters treated the trade-off between pay and worker quality as a basic fact of life, but they did not infer candidate quality from pay demands. Recruiters used the trade-off as a reason for not reducing pay only for skills that were in short supply despite the economic slowdown. For most skills, they believed they could hire all the workers they needed during the recession at lower rates of pay. The secondary sector does not sustain candidates’ reservation wages. Hiring pay is more flexible in the secondary than the primary sector: the opposite of the situation predicted by Weiss’s theory. Two-tier or multiple-tier wage structures are commonplace in the secondary sector, because the part-time and casual nature of the jobs keeps workers from getting to know each other well and so reduces the need to maintain internal pay equity.
Kaufman’s (1984) results support my main findings. He conducted interviews in twenty-six British firms in 1982 during a period of high unemployment. He too found that employers “believed they could find qualified workers at lower wages.” He found that employers avoid replacing workers with cheaper ones because of the value of skills and of long-term employment relationships. Employers avoid pay cuts because of concern about productivity. Because supervision is costly, employers rely “heavily on the goodwill of their employees.” Workers view wages as “a reward for performing competently” and would regard a wage cut as an “affront.” Employers avoid hiring new employees at lower pay rates than existing ones because doing so would create “intolerable frictions,” especially with “the newer workers who would eventually become disgruntled about the two-tier wage structure.” Managers feel they can cut nominal pay if “severe cutbacks or closure will be necessary unless the nominal wage cuts are enacted.”
Blinder and Choi (1990) interviewed managers in nineteen firms, and their findings largely agree with my own. They found little evidence to support Weiss’s idea that job candidates’ wage demands are useful indicators of productivity. Few of Blinder and Choi’s nineteen respondents thought that a higher wage would induce greater work effort, though a majority thought that a wage cut would diminish effort. The majority said effort would decrease because of reduced morale. None mentioned the decreased penalty for being fired. A majority of the respondents believed that higher unemployment would bring greater work effort. All respondents answering the question felt that a wage cut would increase labor turnover, though only one of the five firms that had recently reduced pay had experienced a significant increase in quits. “The reason for the wage cut seemed to matter. . . . Generally, wage reductions made to save the firm from failure or to align wages with those of competitors are viewed as justifiable and fair while those made just to raise profits are not.” Managers felt strongly that having a wage policy viewed as unfair “would affect work effort, quits, and the quality of future applicants. . . . Attitudes like this must be strong deterrents to implementing an ‘unfair’ wage policy though . . . that does not necessarily rule out wage reductions under the right circumstances” (Blinder and Choi 1990, pp. 1008–9). Blinder and Choi found strong support for the idea that worker concern about relative wages is a reason for downward wage rigidity. The question asked, however, did not distinguish between internal and external pay comparisons, so that the support given to Keynes’s relative wage theory is ambiguous.
Campbell and Kamlani (1997) surveyed 184 firms, sending questionnaires to managers, who were asked to rate the importance of various statements on a scale from one to four. Most of their findings agree with my own and those of the other surveys. Their respondents attached the greatest importance to the idea that wage cuts would induce the best workers to quit, which is Weiss’s adverse selection idea as it applies to quits (Weiss 1990). Campbell and Kamlani found that the best workers are valued because pay does not increase as rapidly as productivity, and employees’ skills are often firm specific. Other important management concerns were that a wage cut would increase turnover and hence hiring and training costs and would generate bad feeling that would lead to less work effort. Campbell and Kamlani found less support for the idea that pay cuts would make recruitment more difficult and found no support for the “no shirking” model. Managers did not agree that cutting pay would decrease effort because of a reduced fear of job loss, but did agree that effort would decline because of decreased gratitude and loyalty. Furthermore, good management–worker relations were thought to have a much greater impact on effort than high wages, close supervision, and high unemployment. There was also no support for the insider–outsider theory. Most managers did not believe that if the firm discharged some of its current workers and replaced them with new ones at a lower wage, the old workers who remained would harass and refuse to cooperate with the newly hired ones. The reasons for a pay cut matter; its negative impact on effort would be greater if the firm were profitable than if it were losing money. There is an asymmetry between the impact of wage increases and decreases; the deleterious effect on effort of a decrease would greatly exceed the positive effect of an increase. Similarly, a wage decrease would have a worse impact on effort and morale than having paid the lower wage for a long time.
Agell and Lundborg (1995, 1999, 2003) carried out questionnaire surveys of managers in Swedish manufacturing firms, obtaining responses from 179 firms in 1991 and from 157 of those firms in a follow-up survey in 1998. A large majority of the respondents felt that a nominal wage cut would be strongly resisted by employees and that at least 50% of the firm’s jobs would have to be threatened to make a cut acceptable. The respondents gave strong support to Keynes’s theory that the desire to preserve external wage relativities explains downward wage rigidity. The inconsistency between this finding and my own is probably explained by the much greater importance of labor unions in Sweden than in the United States. This explanation is supported by the finding of Agell and Bennmarker (2002, 2003) that the importance attributed to external pay comparisons as an explanation of wage rigidity increases with a firm’s degree of unionization. Agell and Lundborg found little or no support for the “no shirking” model. Managers did not regard shirking as very common, and “employees who were repeatedly caught shirking were punished by a simple verbal rebuke” (Agell and Lundborg 1999, p. 11). Like Campbell and Kamlani, they found that good management–worker relations were much more important to work effort than high wages, supervision, or unemployment. When managers were asked to list the factors most important to worker motivation, “they answered that their employees ought to be given stimulating work assignments, and to feel involved in decision-making. Some stressed that it was important that all employees felt noticed and trusted, and were provided with continuous feedback and appreciation” (Agell and Lundborg 2003, p. 25, footnote 16). As the authors note, these answers were very similar those I heard from U.S. managers (Agell and Lundborg 1999, p. 13). Managers reported that higher unemployment increased worker effort, and workers seemed to be providing more effort in 1998, when there was high unemployment, than in 1991, when there was little unemployment. These findings on the effect of unemployment confirm those of myself and of Kaufman. Like Blinder and Choi, Agell and Lundborg found little support for Weiss’s idea that job candidates’ reservation wages are a useful signal of productivity (Agell and Lundborg 1999, Table 6). Agell and Lundborg also found little support for Solow’s theory about undercutting. They found, as did I, that offers to work for little pay were not uncommon, though fewer such offers occurred in 1998 than in 1991, perhaps because the much higher unemployment rate in 1998 discouraged job search. Managers usually rejected low offers, because accepting them would create pay inequities within the firm and low bidders were thought to have poor skills (Agell and Lundborg 1995, p. 299). In my survey, I often heard the first explanation, but seldom the second.
The findings of Agell and Bennmarker (2002, 2003) are largely consistent with those of Agell and Lundborg. Agell and Bennmarker also obtained information on the influence of firm size and employee gender on the explanation of wage rigidity—matters that are not germane to this chapter.
Levine (1993) obtained responses to questionnaires on pay policy from 139 compensation managers of large U.S. corporations. The questions focused on the determinants of wages and salaries rather than on the reasons for downward wage rigidity. Nevertheless, he found that the unemployment rate and other measures of excess demand for labor had almost no impact on pay. Also, internal equity considerations take precedence over changes in market pay rates in the determination of relative pay rates for closely related jobs and skills.
In summary, the eight surveys of managers are largely consistent and point to an explanation of wage rigidity based on morale rather than on the work incentives that play a role in the “no shirking” model.
I now turn to the analysis by Smith (2002) of data from the British Household Panel Study of 6,000 employed workers from 1991 to 1999. She uses data on the 70% of workers who did not change employer or job grade during the nine years. The data include monthly income and responses to questions about satisfaction with pay and job. She finds that, in a typical month, about 28% of workers suffered nominal reductions in their monthly income and the pay of about 6% was frozen (in that their monthly nominal income did not change). She studies the association between changes in satisfaction and monthly income and finds that workers who suffered cuts were on average less satisfied than those who enjoyed pay increases, though the difference in satisfaction is not striking. She also finds that those whose pay was frozen were just as satisfied as those whose income declined. She interprets this last finding as evidence against the morale theory of wage rigidity outlined above, because according to that theory pay cuts should cause greater unhappiness than do pay freezes. The theory, of course, may be wrong, but it is not clear what conclusions should be drawn from her analysis, because she probably does not have data on pay cuts and freezes in the sense of the third definition given in the previous section, and this is the definition that is relevant to downward wage rigidity. Monthly incomes can fluctuate for a great many reasons, such as changes in overtime, shifts, job assignments, bonuses, or hours, and she has information on none of these except hours, and she is not sure the data on hours are accurate. Pay raises, freezes, and cuts have to do with the rules by which pay is calculated. A great deal more information is required than total monthly income in order to detect changes in these rules. I find it extremely unlikely that on average 28% of the workforce suffered pay cuts from one month to the next according to the proper definition of pay cut. Another issue is that actual pay cuts often turn out to do little harm to morale, because they are done for a good reason and are accepted by workers as fair. When managers say that pay cuts would hurt morale, they refer to unjustified cuts. Also, job and pay satisfaction are probably not good measures of morale.
A question of interest to macroeconomists is whether downward wage rigidity is real or nominal. In other words, do workers suffer from money illusion? Would they be as offended by a 10% reduction in nominal wages when the consumer price level had declined by 5% as they would be by a wage freeze when inflation was 5%? It is hard to address this issue using surveys without asking hypothetical and hence confusing questions of informants. Most surveys have been done during periods of low inflation, when inflation does not seem relevant. The answers that managers gave Agell and Bennmarker (2002, 2003) to a question similar to the one posed above indicate that managers believe that their workers suffer from money illusion. In my own work, I obtained similar responses on the few times I asked such questions. It is hard to know how to evaluate such findings because of the speculative nature of the questions. Although there is ample evidence that many people do suffer from money illusion (Kahneman et al. 1986; Shafir et al. 1997; Fehr and Tyran 2001), it is not clear that money illusion is a significant factor in downward wage rigidity.
Experimental evidence is accumulating that, for the most part, agrees with what managers say about their own choices and about worker motivation. The most important finding is the prevalence of reciprocity. Many people, when placed experimentally in the role of worker or employer, offer extra effort when offered extra pay or offer extra pay after receiving extra effort, even when no quid pro quo is required. People also reciprocate bad for bad. In experiments, subjects incur a cost in order to harm others who have hurt them. The general willingness to reciprocate good for good is the essence of good morale. Negative reciprocity is what underlies the insult effect of pay cuts, which is resentment caused by the firm’s perceived breach of positive reciprocity; workers expect employers to offer pay increases, not cuts, in exchange for loyalty and effort. The pervasiveness of negative reciprocity probably explains managers’ belief that the systematic use of firing would not motivate employees to work well. Another finding is that financial incentives do inspire effort, provided they are framed in a way that avoids an impression of menace. Surveys of the experimental literature are given in Fehr and Gächter (1998b, 2000), Fehr and Falk (2002), and Fehr and Fischbacher (2005).
A series of laboratory experiments demonstrate the importance of reciprocity in mock employment relationships (Fehr et al. 1993, 1998a,b; Kirchler et al. 1996; Gächter and Falk 2002). In these experiments, there are two types of subjects (employers and workers) and two stages of interaction. At the first stage, each employer makes a wage offer, which is either accepted or rejected by some worker. Acceptance leads to employment and to the second stage, where either the worker or the experimenter chooses an effort level. An employer can employ only one worker, and a worker can work for only one employer. An employed worker’s payoff is the wage minus a cost, which is increasing in the effort level. The employer’s payoff increases in the effort level and, of course, decreases with the wage. Notice that the employer has no way to enforce the worker’s effort choice. The two stages are repeated, usually ten to fifteen times. In some experiments, one worker and one employer are paired for all the repetitions. In others, the experimenter changes the pairings after every repetition. In still another version, the pairings are established at each repetition by competitive bidding for workers and jobs. In such market interactions there are more workers than employers, so that market-clearing wages should be little more than the workers’ reservation level, which is their cost of effort. Experimenters consistently find that if workers choose the effort level, then the average wage is considerably higher than the reservation level, even when competitive bidding should force wages down to it. Furthermore, the worker’s average effort is higher than the minimum allowed and increases with the wage offered. In addition, the wage equals little more than the reservation level, if the experimenter chooses effort and there is competitive bidding with an excess supply of labor. These results hold, even if the employer and worker interact only once. That is, workers offer extra effort in exchange for a higher than minimal wage, even though wages are agreed on before workers choose effort levels and employers never have another opportunity to reward or punish workers. Employers anticipate and exploit workers’ reciprocity by offering generous wages.
The experiments show that only some people reciprocate. Others do not do so and behave selfishly. Selfish workers offer the minimum amount of effort. Some employers who would probably otherwise behave selfishly are induced to offer generous wages by the expectation that some workers will react to them by offering liberal amounts of effort. Because wages fall to minimal levels when the experimenter fixes the effort level, we may tentatively conclude that employers’ behavior is driven mainly by the expectation of reciprocation, not by a sense of fairness, that is, by a desire to divide evenly the economic surplus generated by the worker–employer interaction.
The tendency to reciprocate may be built into the human psyche. Rilling et al. (2002) used magnetic resonance imaging to study the reactions of the brain to repeated playing of the prisoner’s dilemma game and found that experiencing cooperative responses and deciding to cooperate were both accompanied by patterns of brain activity normally associated with pleasure.4
All these findings support the explanation of wage rigidity proposed by Akerlof (1982) in his gift-exchange model. I pointed out earlier that this theory does not seem to apply in business contexts because workers quickly grow to believe that they deserve whatever pay they receive. Experiments do not continue for long enough to capture this habituation effect.
What is important about the experiments is that they reveal that a significant fraction of the population reciprocates. In addition, the experimental findings do reflect some of the practices that managers describe. When setting the pay of new hires, recruiters sometimes offer a little more than applicants expect in order to get the relationship with them started off on the right footing and to create excitement about the new job. One of the many reasons recruiters dislike hiring overqualified applicants is that they are likely to be disgruntled because their pay disappoints their expectations.
Fehr and Falk (1999) perform interesting modifications of the experiments of Fehr et al. (1993) and others described above. Fehr and Falk make the bidding for jobs and workers two-sided rather than one-sided in the situation with competitive bidding and an excess supply of workers. That is, workers as well as employers can make wage offers. The authors find that, when the experimenter determines effort, the employers accept only the lowest offers and wages are forced down almost to the reservation level. When the workers choose the effort level, however, the wage is higher, just as in experiments where only employers make offers. Workers make many low offers to try to obtain a job, but these are refused, apparently because the employers hope to incite high effort by paying good wages. The experimental employers’ behavior corresponds to that of actual firms, who do usually refuse workers’ offers to work for very little.
Burda et al. (1998) have performed experiments involving wage cuts. In their work, an employer and worker are matched for two periods, and the employer makes a wage offer in each of them, which the worker may accept or reject. If the worker rejects the offer, the employer may, after paying a fixed training cost, hire a fictitious worker at a market wage, which the actual worker also receives, as if hired by some other fictitious firm. The market wage is predetermined by the experimenters and declines from the first to the second period. In the experiments, there is little wage rigidity; the wages that employers and employees agree on tend to decline along with the market wage. The employer and worker in effect play two successive ultimatum games, the bargaining position of the worker weakens from the first to the second game, and as a result the wage declines. There is no reciprocation of effort for income that could give rise to an insult effect, and the standard-of-living effect does not apply, since the workers do not live off their earnings. The experiments, therefore, provide evidence that without these two effects wages would be downwardly flexible.
Experimental evidence supports the view of businesspeople that financial incentives are effective, even when negative, provided they are not presented in a hostile manner. For instance, Nagin et al. (2002) report on a field experiment performed by a telemarketing firm. In this firm, the telemarketers’ pay increased with the number of successful solicitations they claimed, and the company monitored these claims by calling back a fraction of the people declared to be successes. The company secretly varied the fraction of bad calls reported to employees while increasing the true callback rate. By analyzing the company’s data, the authors found that cheating increased as the fraction of bad calls reported declined, so that workers did respond to variation in the negative incentive.
Laboratory experimental work by Fehr and Gächter (1998a) and Brown et al. (2004a) shows that the possibility of negative rewards does not keep reciprocation from being a powerful incentive. Fehr and Gächter (1998a) performed the two-stage experiments of Fehr et al. (1993) with the modification that at stage one the employer requested an effort level. The authors compared the results with experiments where in a third stage the employer could reward or punish the worker. The amount of the reward or punishment was chosen by the employer and was not announced in advance. The employer incurred a cost that increased with the absolute magnitude of the reward or punishment. Despite the cost, many employers did reward high effort and punish low effort, and workers on average offered more effort and earned lower wages in the three-stage than in the two-stage experiments. Brown et al. (2004a) repeated the two-stage experiments of Fehr et al. (1993) fifteen times under two conditions. Under one, employers and workers could identify each other by a number, and employers could make offers to a particular worker. This arrangement made it possible for an employer and worker to form a long-term relationship. In the other condition, the identifying numbers were reassigned in every period, so that long-term relationships were impossible. When identity numbers remained stable, individual workers and employers did form relationships that were valuable to both, because they established a pattern of exchanging high effort for high wages. Employers could and many did punish workers for low effort by dismissing them, that is, by ceasing to make them offers. Average wages and effort were considerably higher when identity numbers were stable than when they were reassigned, so workers were not discouraged from reciprocating by the threat of dismissal that was made possible by stable identity numbers. When Brown et al. (2004b) repeated the experiments just described while allowing there to be more firms than workers, long-term relationships formed even though workers could quickly obtain work with another firm if they were let go. The fact that the negative incentives were not made explicit in these experiments may have diminished any bad impression they made. Another explanation for the effectiveness of the negative incentives may have to do with the presence of both selfish and reciprocating workers. Although the reciprocating workers might have been offended by the possibility of punishment, selfish ones might have been induced to offer more effort by the prospect of reward and risk of punishment.
Other experiments that imitate the “no shirking” model provide additional evidence that punishments do not necessarily crush reciprocation and discourage effort. These experiments are described in Fehr et al. (1996, 1997, 2001), and Fehr and Gächter (2002). The experiments have the form of the two-stage experiments described in Fehr et al. (1993), except that the employer requests a certain effort level and a worker is fined with a fixed probability if the effort level offered falls short of that demanded by the employer, that is, if the worker shirks. In its offer, the employer specifies a wage, the fine, and the effort level demanded. The “no shirking” model of Shapiro and Stiglitz (1984) also has a probability of being caught shirking, and the fine in the experiment corresponds to being fired. One finding is that the threat of being fined elicits more than the minimum possible level of effort. Also, some reciprocation exists, in that employers obtain effort above the level they demand when they offer generous wages. Probably because employers hope for reciprocation, they often request effort levels that are too high to be enforced by the fine. The average level of actual effort is reduced by a considerable amount of shirking that may reflect reciprocation of the hostility perceived in the possibility of being fined.
The evidence is mixed on the degree to which the specification of fines discourages reciprocity. Fehret al. (2001) and Fehr and Gächter (2002) compare experimental labor relations models imitating the “no shirking” model, as in Fehr et al. (1996), with labor relations models that depend for success solely on reciprocity or trust, as in Fehr et al. (1993). In the trust model, the employer offers a wage and makes a nonbinding effort request, and the worker then offers an effort level. The “no shirking” model is as described in the previous paragraph. The two papers report opposite results. In Fehr and Gächter (2002), the trust model achieves higher actual effort than the “no shirking” model.5 In Fehr et al. (2001), the “no shirking” model achieves higher effort. I see no way of explaining the discrepancy, as the payoffs are nearly the same in the two experiments and the differences between them do not seem relevant.6 Fehr and Gächter (2002) go on to make another comparison that shows that the fine may vex workers to some extent. They compare the “no shirking” model with a mathematically equivalent bonus model, in which the punishment is not a fine but the deprivation of a bonus. The bonus model gives rise to greater effort than the “no shirking” model, but less than the trust model.
Further experimental evidence of the harmful effects of negative incentives is given in Fehr and Rockenbach (2003). In their experiments, subjects play a game, in which an investor chooses a quantity of money to give to a respondent and specifies the amount he or she would like the respondent to return. The amount given is tripled by the experimenter, so if the investor gives x, the respondent receives 3x. The respondent then chooses how much to return to the investor. In another version of the game, the investor, when making the gift to the respondent, may commit to imposing a fine on the respondent if he or she returns less than the amount requested by the investor. On average, respondents were least generous when the fine was imposed, next most generous when there was no possibility of a fine, and most generous when the investor could impose a fine but chose not to do so.
Experiments by Falk and Kosfeld (2004) show that efforts to control people can also diminish their willingness to cooperate. They had two people play a game in which one is an agent and the other a principal. The agent is given 120 units of money and gives x units of it to the principal. The experimenter doubles this quantity, so that the principal receives 2x. The principal can either oblige the agent to give at least 10 units or do nothing. A majority of agents give less if the principal restricts them in this way, and on average agents give less when so constrained.
Gneezy and Rustichini (2000) provide other evidence on the destructive effects of negative incentives. They made an experiment with a day-care center in which they imposed for the first time a monetary fine on parents for picking up their children late. The introduction of the fine increased parents’ lateness, and the lateness did not diminish after the fine was removed. It seems likely that the increase in lateness occurred because parents interpreted the fine as a fee charged for keeping their children longer.
Two papers by Falk et al. (2000, 2003) provide experimental evidence that perceived intentions as well as the desire for a fair division affect reciprocation. Falk et al. (2000) report on experiments with a variant of the game, described above, of Fehr and Rockenbach (2003). On the first move, the investor may take money away from or give money to the respondent, and the respondent may then in turn give or take money away from the investor. In another version of the game, the experimenter determines the investor’s move according to a random distribution. In both versions, respondents on average react by taking money back if it is taken from them and give money back when it has been given to them. Their responses are, however, of a larger magnitude when the first move is chosen by the investor rather than by the experimenter. This behavior shows that the respondents’ behavior was driven to some extent by a desire to even the winnings from the game, but above all by an urge to reciprocate the good or bad intentions of the investor. Falk et al. (2003) reach similar conclusions from experiments with various ultimatum games. Player A can propose one of two possible splits of ten monetary units to a respondent. One possibility is always an (8, 2) split: eight for the proposer and two for the respondent. Alternatives are (5, 5), an even split, or (2, 8), (10, 0), or even (8, 2), which means that there is really no alternative. Respondents reject the (8, 2) split more frequently, the less fair it seems in comparison with the alternative. For instance, (8, 2) is rejected most often if (5, 5) is the alternative, and least often if (10, 0) is the alternative.
These results provide some (but not strong) support for managers’ assertions that using firing systematically to stimulate effort would dampen morale and depress productivity. I suspect that the effects managers refer to are difficult to capture experimentally, because firing is a much more severe punishment than can be imposed in the laboratory and it is hard to reproduce in a laboratory the menacing atmosphere that could be created in a work place by frequent firings and by the explicit threat of firing.
Although early investigations by managerial scientists and organizational psychologists of the relations between pay, morale, and productivity contradicted some of what managers say about these matters, the subject has since evolved and now much of what they say has been corroborated. Recall that managers assert that pay levels have little impact on motivation or performance, but that financial incentives linked to performance can increase productivity considerably. These conclusions have been supported by a large amount of research by management scientists and psychologists, which I do not describe. The relevant literature is reviewed in Vroom (1964, p. 252) and Lawler (1971, p. 133). The management intuitions that did not receive much support in early research had to do with the link between morale and productivity. Morale was measured from questionnaire evidence on job satisfaction and organizational commitment or loyalty, and performance was measured through direct observation or by supervisors’ evaluations. There is a huge literature on this subject that has been reviewed by many (Brayfield and Crockett 1955; Herzberg et al. 1957, Chapter 4; Vroom 1964, pp. 181–86; Locke 1976, pp. 1330–34; Iaffaldano and Muchinsky 1985; Mathieu and Zajac 1990). The general conclusion is that the correlations between the measures of morale and performance are positive, but small. The measures of performance include those of both individuals and groups. In a way, these findings confirm what managers say, because most of them assert that good morale is not the same as happiness.
There is a considerable amount of evidence that job satisfaction is negatively related to quitting and absences. The literature on this subject is reviewed in Brayfield and Crockett (1955), Herzberg et al. (1957, pp. 106–7), Vroom (1964, pp. 175–80), Locke (1976, pp. 1331–32), Price (1977, p. 79), Steers and Rhodes (1978), Mobley (1982, pp. 95–105), Staw (1984, pp. 638–45), and Mathieu and Zajac (1990).
There was interesting research in the 1950s which did support management feelings about the importance of morale. The investigators made experimental changes in management practices to determine the relation between attitudes and performance of work groups (Viteles 1953, Chapter 8; Seashore 1954; Whyte et al. 1955, 1961; Likert 1961, Chapter 3). One of the main conclusions was that performance is positively associated with pride in the work group or firm, but is not related to other attitudes.
In response to the failure to find a significant relation between job satisfaction and performance, researchers studied the link between job attitudes and workers’ doing things for employers that are outside normal duties. Contact with business may have led scholars to look for such a connection, because managers claim that the impact of good morale on productivity is felt mainly through employees’ willingness to do more than the minimum required of them. Investigators have given “doing more than the minimum” various names, such as spontaneous behavior (Katz 1964), pro-social behavior (O’Reilly and Chatman 1986, Brief and Motowidlo 1986), extra-role behavior (O’Reilly and Chatman 1986), and, most commonly, organizational citizenship behavior (Organ 1988). These concepts differ to some extent. Organ (1988) defines five categories of organization citizenship behaviors, altruism (helping other workers), conscientiousness (obeying company rules, being punctual, and showing up for work regularly), sportsmanship (good-humored toleration of inconveniences), courtesy (considerate treatment of fellow workers), and civic virtue (participation in the internal political life of the organization).
An initial question is whether good morale increases organizational citizenship behavior. Organizational psychologists have done most of the research on this topic. They typically start with a number of loosely defined concepts, such as job satisfaction, perceptions of fairness in the work place, and organizational citizenship behavior, and then try to determine how these are related by analyzing responses of a sample of several hundred people to questionnaires. Each concept is usually broken into several components, such as Organ’s five categories of organizational citizenship behavior, and a list of questions is associated with each component. Employees answer questions on job satisfaction and perceptions of fairness. Employees or their supervisors answer questions on organizational citizenship behavior. Factor analysis is used to check whether responses to the questions are such that those corresponding to one conceptual component are highly correlated with each other and have less correlation with responses to other questions. The relations among the concepts and their components are then estimated using regression analysis. The advantage of such surveys over laboratory experiments is that they can investigate real-life situations in which there are long-term associations between workers and employers. The subjects in laboratory experiments are usually college students and do not know each other well. A disadvantage is that causation is much harder to establish in surveys than it is in experiments.
The findings of organizational psychologists do not all agree, but their work supports the conclusion that typical measures of morale, such as job satisfaction and organizational commitment, do have a positive relation with organizational citizenship behavior. What is more important is that a perception of fairness within a business organization has a positive relation with both job satisfaction and organizational citizenship behavior and may be the dominant factor affecting both. Furthermore, procedural justice, and especially the interactional aspect of procedural justice, is more closely related to job satisfaction and organizational citizenship behavior than is distributive justice. Distributive justice has to do with the allocation of rewards to employees, whereas procedural justice has to do with the system used to arrive at the allocation. Interactional justice has to do with the consideration, politeness, and respect with which superiors treat subordinates. Another conclusion is that organizational citizenship behavior depends less on the employees’ mood than on their conscious perceptions about their jobs. The impact of fairness on organizational citizenship behavior is discussed in Organ and Konovsky (1989), Moorman (1991, 1993), Folger (1993), Moorman et al. (1993), Niehoff and Moorman (1993), Podsakoff and MacKenzie (1993), Organ and Ryan (1995), Konovsky and Organ (1996), and Netemeyer et al. (1997). Moorman (1991) discusses the relative impacts of the various forms of justice. The impact of mood is discussed in Organ and Konovsky (1989), George (1991), and Moorman (1993). The relative impacts of mood and cognitive job satisfaction are discussed in Organ and Konovsky (1989) and Moorman (1993). The impact of job satisfaction and commitment on organizational citizenship behavior is discussed in O’Reilly and Chatman (1986), Puffer (1987), Farh et al. (1990), Moorman (1991), Organ and Lingl (1995), Organ and Ryan (1995), Konovsky and Organ (1996), Netemeyer et al. (1997), and MacKenzie et al. (1998). Good reviews of the impact of fairness on organizational citizenship behavior are Organ (1988, 1990), Schnake (1991), Greenberg (1993), and Organ and Moorman (1993).
Another connection between morale and organizational citizenship behavior is made through studies of the impact of leadership style on subordinates’ organizational citizenship behavior. A distinction is made between transactional and transformational leadership. The transactional style asserts itself by means of praise and admonishment, whereas the transformational style inspires people to go beyond their personal interests and think of those of the company or task. The transformational style persuades people to identify with the company, and the transactional style focuses on people’s self-interest. The transformational style is intended to create good morale in the sense that businesspeople seem to have in mind. Investigators have found that transformational leadership has a strong positive impact on both in-role job performance and organizational citizenship behavior, that its impact exceeds that of transactional leadership, and that the impact of transformational leadership is due in part to increased trust in the leadership. The relevant studies are by Podsakoff et al. (1990, 1996) and MacKenzie et al. (2001).
An obvious question is whether organizational citizenship behavior increases a company’s profitability. Managers apparently think that it does, because there is evidence that supervisors’ performance evaluations of subordinates are strongly and positively influenced by organizational citizenship behavior. Papers that establish this connection are MacKenzie et al. (1991, 1993) and Podsakoff et al. (1993). A few studies have measured the impact of organizational citizenship behavior on the performance of work groups in various settings and have found the effects to be positive. These studies include George and Bettenhausen (1990), Podsakoff and MacKenzie (1994, 1997), Walz and Niehoff (1996), and Podsakoff et al. (1997). The observed correlations may be spurious, however, because there is evidence from laboratory experiments that the high performance of a work group may have a positive influence on perceptions within the group of organizational citizenship behavior (Bachrach et al. 2001). The subject is reviewed in Podsakoff et al. (2000).
Some interesting recent work has explored the connection between identification with an organization on the one hand, and quits and performance, especially extra-role performance, on the other hand. Tyler has participated in much of this work. He thinks of identification with a company as internalization of its goals and asserts that identification occurs as a result of judgments about organizational status, which he calls pride, and about status within the organization, which he calls respect. Pride has to do with a favorable view of the organization as a whole, and respect has to do with being treated well within it. Status judgments can be comparative or autonomous, where a comparative judgment relates an organization or person to others and an autonomous judgment is an absolute one. Tyler believes that if people identify with an organization, they will want it to succeed, because its success will strengthen their own self-image. Identification with an organization is, in my opinion, a much better interpretation of what managers mean by good morale than are job satisfaction and even organizational commitment. Tyler and his coauthors find that identification is a dominant explanation of voluntary cooperation with organizations. In the context of business organizations, identification with the company is a much more important explanatory factor than financial rewards received from it. These investigators find that the greatest impact of identification is on organizational citizenship, extra-role, or discretionary behavior as opposed to in-role or mandatory behavior, that is, behavior required by a job description. The primary impact of pride is on rule following or conscientiousness, whereas the primary impact of respect is on helping behavior, that is, assisting coworkers. Autonomous judgments of status have a much bigger effect than comparative ones. Tyler and his coauthors assert that perceptions of fairness and especially procedural justice have an important impact on judgments about the status of an organization and hence on willingness to identify with it. Recall that management scientists cited earlier (Viteles 1953; Seashore 1954; Whyte et al. 1955; Likert 1961) also found a connection between pride in an organization and performance. The work of Tyler and his colleagues is reported in Tyler (1999) and Tyler and Blader (2000, 2001). Abrams et al. (1998) observe a close association between identification with an organization and intentions to quit. Much of the work of Tyler and his coauthors on identification and cooperation with organizations has been done in the context of political, social, and educational institutions, but the recent work just cited has to do with businesses. This interesting work raises the question of why people identify with organizations. Status is an incomplete explanation, since the term status has little independent content and includes all possible reasons for liking an organization. It is interesting that fairness has a strong influence on status and that people are proud of organizations that treat them and others fairly, but researchers have given no explanation of why this is so.
An obvious question is: “What evidence has been collected on the impact of actual pay cuts or pay freezes on morale?” The only works I have found on the subject are by Greenberg (1989, 1990) and Schaubroeck et al. (1994). In the first paper, Greenberg finds from a survey that workers did feel underpaid after a 6% pay cut, but job satisfaction did not decline and employees instead paid more attention to the nonfinancial advantages of their jobs. In the second paper, Greenberg reports that, at another business, theft of company property increased after a 15% pay cut. In this chapter, he conducted an experiment in which he gave employees a good explanation of the pay cut in one plant where the pay cut occurred but not in another. In the plant where the explanation was made, feelings of pay inequity and pilferage were fewer than in the other plant. This evidence supports the assertions managers make that employees tolerate pay cuts more easily if they feel they are justified and that it is possible to persuade workers that cuts are necessary. These conclusions are further reinforced by the work of Schaubroeck et al. (1994), who studied the reactions of salaried employees to a pay freeze. These investigators also conducted an experiment, giving a good explanation to some of the employees and not to others. The explanations of the freeze diminished resentment. For those who did not receive the explanation, job dissatisfaction increased with self-reported economic hardship resulting from the freeze, and there was no such relation for those who did receive the explanation.
Perhaps the outstanding conclusion to be drawn from the works discussed is the importance of fairness to labor performance. It is not easy to judge what fairness means. Fairness certainly does not mean an equal distribution of the benefits from a company’s operations, for pay levels within firms are far from egalitarian. Even workers doing the same job may receive very different pay because of many factors, such as longevity with the company, skills acquired, and productivity. Fairness is recognized in business as being inherently ambiguous. For instance, judgments about the fairness of internal pay structures are said to depend strongly on company tradition. Another indication that fairness does not mean equality of gains is the evidence from organizational psychology that procedural and interactive justice are more important to an impression of fairness than is distributive justice. A very significant finding, I believe, is that of Tyler and Blader (2000, 2001): perceptions of procedural justice contribute to pride in an organization.
We do not know why people so urgently desire fairness. Is it because it contributes to an atmosphere of positive reciprocation and people like to exchange favors? Does fairness make people feel more secure? Do people feel that fairness is right and want their surroundings to accord with their moral principles? Do people simply want to have a level playing field on which to compete? It is to be hoped that further empirical work will give more insight into these questions.
A sense of fairness is probably the most important determinant of good company morale. Other important factors are close ties among coworkers and the significance attached to the firm’s output. One reason pay cuts can be resented is that they can dissolve the sense of fairness. Workers accept a pay cut that they feel is fair and they see it as fair when it saves a great many jobs.
Another important conclusion is that firms try to gain the cooperation of employees by getting them to identify with the company and to internalize its objectives. As Tyler and Blader (2000, 2001) have emphasized, an atmosphere of fairness makes workers more willing to do these things. For an understanding of wage rigidity and of how organizations obtain cooperation, it would be useful to know why people value fairness, why it promotes identification with a company, and why people identify with organizations at all. That they do so is clear.
Abrams, D., K. Ando, and S. Hinkle. 1998. Psychological attachment to the group: cross-cultural differences in organizational identification and subjective norms as predictors of workers’ turnover intentions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 24:1027–39.
Agell, J., and H. Bennmarker. 2002. Wage policy and endogenous wage rigidity: a representative view from the inside. CESifo Working Paper 751.
——. 2003. Endogenous wage rigidity. CESifo Working Paper 1081.
Agell, J., and P. Lundborg. 1995. Theories of pay and unemployment: survey evidence from Swedish manufacturing firms. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 97:295–307.
——. 1999. Survey evidence on wage rigidity and unemployment: Sweden in the 1990s. Office of Labour Market Policy Evaluation, Uppsala, Sweden, Discussion Paper 1999-2.
——. 2003. Survey evidence on wage rigidity and unemployment: Sweden in the 1990s. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 105:15–29.
Akerlof, G. A. 1982. Labor contracts as partial gift exchange. Quarterly Journal of Economics 97:543–69.
Akerlof, G. A., and J. Yellen. 1988. Fairness and unemployment. American Economic Association, Papers and Proceedings 78:44–49.
——. 1990. The fair wage-effort hypothesis and unemployment. Quarterly Journal of Economics 105:255–83.
Akerlof, G. A., W. T. Dickens, and G. Perry. 1996. The macroeconomics of low inflation. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity 1:1–59.
Altonji, J. G., and P. J. Devereux. 2000. The extent and consequences of downward nominal wage rigidity. In Worker Well-Being (ed. S. W. Polachek), Research in Labor Economics, Volume 19, pp. 383–431. Elsevier.
Angier, N. 2002. Why we’re so nice: we’re wired to cooperate. New York Times, Science Section, July 23.
Bachrach, D. G., E. Bendoly, and P. M. Podsakoff. 2001. Attributions of the “causes” of group performance as an alternative explanation of the relationship between organizational citizenship behavior and organizational performance. Journal of Applied Psychology 86:1285–93.
Baker, G., M. Gibbs, and B. Holmström. 1994. The wage policy of a firm. Quarterly Journal of Economics 109:921–55.
Beisiinger, T., and Ch. Knoppik. 2001. Downward nominal rigidity in West German earnings. German Economic Review 2:385–417.
——. 2003. How rigid are nominal wages? Evidence and implications for Germany. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 105:619–41.
Bewley, T. F. 1999. Why Wages Don’t Fall During a Recession. Harvard University Press.
Blinder, A. S., and D. H. Choi. 1990. A shred of evidence on theories of wage stickiness. Quarterly Journal of Economics 105:1003–15.
Brayfield, A. H., and W. H. Crockett. 1955. Employee attitudes and employee performance. Psychological Bulletin 52:396–424.
Brief, A. P., and S. J. Motowidlo. 1986. Prosocial organizational behaviors. Academy of Management Review 11:710–25.
Brown, M., A. Falk, and E. Fehr. 2004a. Competition and relational contracts. Discussion Paper, University of Zürich, Switzerland.
——. 2004b. Relational contracts and the nature of market interactions. Econometrica 72:747–80.
Burda, M., W. Güth, G. Kirchsteiger, and H. Uhlig. 1998. Employment duration and resistance to wage reductions: experimental evidence. Tilburg University, Center for Economic Research, Discussion Paper 9873.
Campbell, C., and K. Kamlani. 1997. The reasons for wage rigidity: evidence from survey of firms. Quarterly Journal of Economics 112:759–89.
Card, D., and D. Hyslop. 1997. Does inflation “grease the wheels of the labor market”? In Reducing Inflation: Motivation and Strategy (ed. C. D. Romer and D. H. Romer). University of Chicago Press.
Chapple, S. 1996. Money wage rigidity in New Zealand. Labour Market Bulletin 1996(2):23–50.
Dohmen, T. J. 2003. Performance, seniority, and wages: formal salary systems and individual earnings profiles. Working Paper, Institute for the Study of Labor (IZA), Bonn, Germany.
Falk, A., and M. Kosfeld. 2004. Trust and motivation. Discussion Paper, University of Zürich, Switzerland.
Falk, A., E. Fehr, and U. Fischbacher. 2000. Testing theories of fairness: intentions matter. Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, University of Zürich, Working Paper 63.
——. 2003. On the nature of fair behavior. Economic Inquiry 41:20–36.
Farh, J.-L., P. M. Podsakoff, and D. W. Organ. 1990. Accounting for organizational citizenship behavior: leader fairness and task scope versus satisfaction. Journal of Management 16:705–21.
Fehr, E., and A. Falk. 1999. Wage rigidity in a competitive incomplete contract market. Journal of Political Economy 107:106–34.
——. 2002. Psychological foundations of incentives. European Economic Review 46:687–724.
Fehr, E., and U. Fischbacher. 2002. Why social preferences matter: the impact of non-selfish motives on competition, cooperation and incentives. The Economic Journal 112:C1–33.
——. 2005. The economics of strong reciprocity. In Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in Economic Life (ed. H. Gintis, S. Bowles, R. T. Boyd, and E. Fehr), Chapter 5. MIT Press.
Fehr, E., and S. Gächter. 1998a. How effective are trust- and reciprocity-based incentives? In Economics, Values and Organizations (ed. A. Ben-Ner and L. Putterman), Chapter 13. Cambridge University Press.
——. 1998b. Reciprocity and economics: the economic implications of Homo reciprocans. European Economic Review 42:845–59.
——. 2000. Fairness and retaliation: the economics of reciprocity. Journal of Economic Perspectives 14:159–81.
——. 2002. Do incentive contracts undermine voluntary cooperation? Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, University of Zürich, Working Paper 34.
Fehr, E., and L. Götte. 2005. Robustness and real consequences of nominal wage rigidity? Journal of Monetary Economics 52:779–804.
Fehr, E., and B. Rockenbach. 2003. Detrimental effects of incentives on human altruism. Nature 422:137–40.
Fehr, E., and J.-R. Tyran. 2001. Does money illusion matter? American Economic Review 91:1239–62.
Fehr, E., G. Kirchsteiger, and A. Riedl. 1993. Does fairness prevent market clearing? An experimental investigation. Quarterly Journal of Economics 108:437–59.
Fehr, E., G. Kirchsteiger, and A. Riedl. 1996. Involuntary unemployment and non-compensating wage differentials in an experimental labour market. Economic Journal 106:106–21.
Fehr, E., S. Gächter, and G. Kirchsteiger. 1997. Reciprocity as a contract enforcement device: experimental evidence. Econometrica 65:833–60.
Fehr, E., E. Kirchler, A. Weichbold, and S. Gächter. 1998a. When social norms overpower competition: gift exchange in experimental labor markets. Journal of Labor Economics 16:324–51.
Fehr, E., G. Kirchsteiger, and A. Riedl. 1998b. Gift exchange and reciprocity in competitive experimental markets. European Economic Review 42:1–34.
Fehr, E., A. Klein, and K. M. Schmidt. 2001. Fairness, incentives and contractual incompleteness. Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, University of Zürich, Working Paper 72.
Folger, R. 1993. Justice, motivation, and performance: beyond role requirements. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal 6:239–48.
Fortin, P. 1996. The great Canadian slump. Canadian Journal of Economics 29:761–87.
Gächter, S., and A. Falk. 2002. Reputation and reciprocity: consequences for the labour relation. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 104:1–26.
George, J. M. 1991. State or trait: effects of positive mood on prosocial behaviors at work. Journal of Applied Psychology 76:299–307.
George, J. M., and K. Bettenhausen. 1990. Understanding prosocial behavior, sales performance, and turnover: a group-level analysis in a service context. Journal of Applied Psychology 75:698–709.
Gneezy, U., and A. Rustichini. 2000. A fine is a price. Journal of Legal Studies 29:1–17.
Goux, D. 1997. Les salaries nominaux sont-ils rigides à la baisse? Mimeo, Institut National de la Statistique et des Études Économiques.
Greenberg, J. 1989. Injustice and cognitive reevaluation of the work environment. Academy of Management Journal 32:174–84.
——. 1990. Employee theft as a reaction to underpayment inequity: the hidden cost of pay cuts. Journal of Applied Psychology 75:561–68.
——. 1993. Justice and organizational citizenship: a commentary on the state of the science. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal 6:249–56.
Herzberg, F., B. Mausner, R. O. Peterson, and D. Capwell. 1957. Job Attitudes: Review of Research and Opinion. Pittsburgh, PA: Psychological Service of Pittsburgh.
Howitt, P. 2002. Looking inside the labor market: a review article. Journal of Economic Literature 40:125–38.
Iaffaldano, M. T., and P. M. Muchinsky. 1985. Job satisfaction and job performance: a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 97:251–73.
Kahn, S. 1997. Evidence of nominal wage stickiness from microdata. American Economic Review 87:993–1008.
Kahneman, D., J. L. Knetsch, and R. H. Thaler. 1986. Fairness as a constraint on profit seeking: entitlements in the market. American Economic Review 76:728–41.
Katz, D. 1964. The motivational basis of organizational behavior. Behavioral Science 9:131–46.
Kaufman, R. 1984. On wage stickiness in Britain’s competitive sector. British Journal of Industrial Relations 22:101–12.
Keynes, J. M. 1936. The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money. London: Macmillan.
Kirchler, E., E. Fehr, and R. Evans. 1996. Social exchange in the labor market: reciprocity and trust versus egoistic money maximization. Journal of Economic Psychology 17:313–41.
Konovsky, M. A., and D. W. Organ. 1996. Dispositional and contextual determinants of organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of Organizational Behavior 17:253–66.
Kramarz, F. 2001. Rigid wages: what have we learned from microeconomic studies? In Advances in Macroeconomic Theory (ed. J. H. Drèze). Oxford University Press.
Lawler III, E. E. 1971. Pay and Organizational Effectiveness: A Psychological View. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Lebow, D. E., D. J. Stockton, and W. L. Wascher. 1995. Inflation, nominal wage rigidity, and the efficiency of labor markets. Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System, Finance and Economic Discussion Series Paper 94-45.
Lebow, D. E., R. E. Saks, and B. A. Wilson. 2003. Downward nominal wage rigidity: evidence from the employment cost index. Advances in Macroeconomics 3(1), article 2.
Levine, D. I. 1993. Fairness, markets, and ability to pay: evidence from compensation executives. American Economic Review 83:1241–59.
Likert, R. 1961. New Patterns of Management. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Lindbeck, A., and D. J. Snower. 1988. Cooperation, harassment, and involuntary unemployment: an insider–outsider approach. American Economic Review 78:167–88.
Locke, E. A. 1976. The nature and causes of job satisfaction. In Handbook of Industrial and Organizational Psychology (ed. M. D. Dunnette), pp. 1297–356. Chicago: Rand McNally.
MacKenzie, S. B., P. M. Podsakoff, and R. Fetter. 1991. Organizational citizenship behavior and objective productivity as determinants of managerial evaluations of salespersons’ performance. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 50:123–50.
——. 1993. The impact of organizational citizenship behavior on evaluations of salesperson performance. Journal of Marketing 57:70–80.
MacKenzie, S. B., P. M. Podsakoff, and M. Ahearne. 1998. Some possible antecedents and consequences of in-role and extra-role salesperson performance. Journal of Marketing 62:87–98.
MacKenzie, S. B., P. M. Podsakoff, and G. A. Rich. 2001. Transformational and transactional leadership and salesperson performance. Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science 29:115–34.
Mathieu, J. E., and D. M. Zajac. 1990. A review and meta-analysis of the antecedents, correlates, and consequences of organizational commitment. Psychological Bulletin 108:171–94.
McLaughlin, K. J. 1994. Rigid wages? Journal of Monetary Economics 34:383–414.
——. 1999. Are nominal wage changes skewed away from wage cuts? Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review 81:117–32.
Mitchell, D. J. B. 1985. Shifting norms in wage determination. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity 1985:575–99.
Mobley, W. H. 1982. Employee Turnover: Causes, Consequences, and Control. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Moorman, R. H. 1991. Relationship between organizational justice and organizational citizenship behaviors: do fairness and perceptions influence employee citizenship? Journal of Applied Psychology 76:845–55.
——. 1993. The influence of cognitive and affective based job satisfaction measures on the relationship between satisfaction and organizational citizenship behavior. Human Relations 46:759–76.
Moorman, R. H., B. P. Niehoff, and D. W. Organ. 1993. Treating employees fairly and organizational citizenship behavior: sorting the effects of jobs satisfaction, organizational commitment, and procedural justice. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal 6:209–25.
Nagin, D., J. Rebitzer, S. Sanders, and L. Taylor. 2002. Monitoring, motivation, and management: the determinants of opportunistic behavior in a field experiment. American Economic Review 92:850–73.
Netemeyer, R. G., J. S. Boles, D. O. McKee, and R. McMurrian. 1997. An investigation into antecedents of organizational citizenship behaviors in a personal selling context. Journal of Marketing 61:85–98.
Niehoff, B. P., and R. H. Moorman. 1993. Justice as a mediator of the relationship between methods of monitoring and organizational citizenship behavior. Academy of Management Journal 36:527–56.
O’Reilly III, C., and J. Chatman. 1986. Organizational commitment and psychological attachment: the effects of compliance, identification, and internalization on prosocial behavior. Journal of Applied Psychology 71:492–99.
Organ, D. W. 1988. Organizational Citizenship Behavior. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books.
——. 1990. The motivational basis of organizational citizenship behavior. In Research in Organizational Behavior (ed. B. M. Staw and L. L. Cummings), Volume 12, pp. 43–72. Elsevier.
Organ, D. W., and M. Konovsky. 1989. Cognitive versus affective determinants of organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of Applied Psychology 74:157–64.
Organ, D. W., and A. Lingl. 1995. Personality, satisfaction, and organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of Social Psychology 135:339–50.
Organ, D. W., and R. H. Moorman. 1993. Fairness and organizational citizenship behavior: what are the connections? Social Justice Research 6:5–18.
Organ, D. W., and K. Ryan. 1995. A meta-analytic review of attitudinal and dispositional predictors of organizational citizenship behavior. Personnel Psychology 48:775–802.
Podsakoff, P. M., and S. B. MacKenzie. 1993. Citizenship behavior and fairness in organizations: issues and directions for future research. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal 6:257–69.
——. 1994. Organizational citizenship behaviors and sales unit effectiveness. Journal of Marketing Research 31:351–63.
——. 1997. Impact of organizational citizenship behavior on organizational performance: a review and suggestions for future research. Human Performance 10:133–51.
Podsakoff, P. M., S. B. MacKenzie, R. H. Moorman, and R. Fetter. 1990. Transformational leader behaviors and their effects on followers’ trust in leader, satisfaction, and organizational citizenship behaviors. Leadership Quarterly 1:107–42.
Podsakoff, P. M., S. B. MacKenzie, and C. Hui. 1993. Organizational citizenship behaviors and managerial evaluations of employee performance: a review and suggestions for future research. In Research in Personnel and Human Resources Management (ed. G. R. Ferris), Volume 11, pp. 1–40. Elsevier.
Podsakoff, P. M., S. B. MacKenzie, and W. H. Bommer. 1996. Transformational leader behaviors and substitutes for leadership as determinants of employee satisfaction, commitment, trust, and organizational citizenship behaviors. Journal of Management 22:259–98.
Podsakoff, P. M., M. Ahearne, and S. B. MacKenzie. 1997. Organizational citizenship behavior and the quantity and quality of work group performance. Journal of Applied Psychology 82:262–70.
Podsakoff, P. M., S. B. MacKenzie, J. B. Paine, and D. G. Bachrach. 2000. Organizational citizenship behaviors: a critical review of the theoretical and empirical literature and suggestions for future research. Journal of Management 26:513–63.
Price, J. L. 1977. The Study of Turnover. Iowa State University Press.
Puffer, S. M. 1987. Prosocial behavior, noncompliant behavior, and work performance among commission salespeople. Journal of Applied Psychology 72:615–21.
Rilling, J. K., D. A. Gutman, T. R. Zeh, G. Pagnoni, G. S. Berns, and C. D. Kits. 2002. A neural basis for social cooperation. Neuron 35:395–405.
Schaubroeck, J., D. R. May, and R. W. Brown. 1994. Procedural justice explanations and employee reactions to economic hardship: a field experiment. Journal of Applied Psychology 79:455–60.
Schnake, M. 1991. Organizational citizenship: a review, proposed model, and research agenda. Human Relations 44:735–59.
Seashore, S. 1954. Group Cohesiveness in the Industrial Work Group. University of Michigan Press.
Shafir, E., P. Diamond, and A. Tversky. 1997. Money illusion. Quarterly Journal of Economics 112:341–74.
Shapiro, C., and J. E. Stiglitz. 1984. Equilibrium unemployment as a worker discipline device. American Economic Review 74:433–44.
Smith, J. C. 2000. Nominal wage rigidity in the United Kingdom. Economic Journal 110:C176–95.
——. 2002. Pay cuts and morale: a test of downward nominal rigidity. Warwick Economic Research Paper 649, Department of Economics, University of Warwick, U.K.
Solow, R. M. 1979. Another possible source of wage stickiness. Journal of Macroeconomics 1:79–82.
——. 1990. The Labor Market as a Social Institution. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.
Staw, B. M. 1984. Organizational behavior: a review and reformulation of the field’s outcome variables. Annual Review of Psychology 35:627–66.
Steers, R. M., and S. R. Rhodes. 1978. Major influences on employee attendance: a process model. Journal of Applied Psychology 63:391–407.
Tyler, T. R. 1999. Why people cooperate with organizations: an identity-based perspective. Research in Organizational Behavior 21:201–46.
Tyler, T. R., and S. L. Blader. 2000. Cooperation in Groups: Procedural Justice, Social Identity, and Behavioral Engagement. Philadelphia, PA: Psychology Press.
——. 2001. Identity and cooperative behavior in groups. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations 4:207–26.
Viteles, M. S. 1953. Motivation and Morale in Industry. New York: W. W. Norton.
Vroom, V. H. 1964. Work and Motivation. Wiley.
Walz, S. M., and B. P. Niehoff. 1996. Organizational citizenship behaviors and their relationship with indicators of organizational effectiveness in limited menu restaurants. In Academy of Management Best Papers Proceedings (ed. J. B. Keys and L. N. Dosier), pp. 307–11. Statesboro, GA: George Southern University.
Weiss, A. 1980. Job queues and layoffs in labor markets with flexible wages. Journal of Political Economy 88:526–38.
——. 1990. Efficiency Wages: Models of Unemployment, Layoffs, and Wage Dispersion. Princeton University Press.
Whyte, W. F. et al. 1955. Money and Motivation: An Analysis of Incentives in Industry. New York: Harper and Row.
——. 1961. Men at Work. Homewood, IL: Corsey Press.
Wilson, B. A. 1997. Movements of wages over the business cycle: an intra-firm view. Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System (U.S.), Finance and Economics Discussion Series, 1997-1.
Bewley presents a very interesting survey of the recent empirical microresearch on wage formation and on reasons for wage rigidity. Much of this work is behavioral in its underpinnings and the results show how notions of fairness and reciprocity play an important role in wage determination. An important aspect of the reviewed empirical work is that these studies are based not just on published statistics but rather on a variety of approaches including questionnaires, field studies, surveys, and experiments. His own work (see Bewley 1999) of course stands out as a particularly meticulous example of this brand of empirical economics.
I am a consumer and not a producer of this kind of research. I am, however, an interested consumer since questions of wage formation and wage rigidity are central to macroeconomics. My comments focus on what macroeconomics can learn from the microresearch discussed in this chapter. I will also take up an important open issue in the surveyed literature.
The first lesson from this chapter is that the notion of (downward) wage rigidity is not as simple as it sounds. Different concepts of the wage have been used. It could in principle mean a firm’s marginal labor costs or total compensation per worker, or total compensation for employees with given job and work conditions. The empirical work has been ambiguous with respect to the different notions. While the results are not fully clear-cut, there seems to be a fair amount of evidence that basic compensation of employees, excluding bonuses, overtime and the like is subject to considerable downward rigidity.
This is not a surprising answer. In some form it has been used as casual evidence for a long time in much of macroeconomics.7 Numerous models and reasons for wage rigidity have been developed and discussed in macroeconomics over nearly seven decades since the publication of Keynes’s General Theory and the birth of Keynesian economics.
Explicit analysis of the motivations behind wage rigidity is a new and interesting aspect of the research discussed by Bewley. The reasons for rigidity given in this behavioral literature can be seen as tests on the different economic theories of wage rigidity. I personally found this aspect of the paper quite interesting as it provides a novel perspective to the different models of wage rigidity used in modern macroeconomics.
An important observation from the microresearch is that pay cuts are resisted because they damage morale, and it is the management who seems to think this way.8 There is a second important observation that morale is damaged when wages are cut, while wage levels have less to do with morale. Bewley suggests that “employees usually have little notion of a fair or market value for their services,” which leads to an important question about the determinants of the reference point for judging fairness. The related literature has some ideas about this and I will return to this point later.
The observation about wage changes and morale runs counter to some earlier models of labor markets. These were largely based on levels of wages and productivity or morale (see, for example, Akerlof 1982; Akerlof and Yellen 1988; Solow 1990). Correspondingly, Keynes’s notion of workers’ concern about relative wages in similar jobs in different firms does not seem to get much support from the work of Bewley and others.9 Interestingly, the model of insiders and outsiders (Lindbeck and Snower 1988) fares somewhat better, as harassment and refusal to cooperate can perhaps be interpreted as consequences of the loss of morale.
Bewley’s basic observation about pay changes and morale does not provide any support for the model of shirking and wages (Shapiro and Stiglitz 1984). Apparently, cooperation between managers and firms is not obtained by threats of firing of shirkers (or workers with low productivity). This is not to say that incentives are not important. Workers do work harder in times of recession but not because management threatens them. The incentives come directly from a tougher external environment.
Another fairly popular model emphasizing information problems and incentives is the adverse selection model of Weiss (1990). Here the micro evidence is interestingly in agreement with that theory when it concerns quits. Managers prefer layoffs to pay cuts, since using the latter would lead to departure of the best workers. However, the other half of Weiss’s model, the connection between high wages and hiring of high-productivity workers, is not supported by the micro studies.
These descriptions are just a few examples of the ideas from Bewley’s comprehensive survey. Many macroeconomists have for a long time thought that labor markets and wage determination/rigidity involve large degrees of social interactions and that they are not just relatively anonymous markets of commodity exchange.10 This recent micro work provides support and makes these notions more precise.
There are important methodological questions in the micro evidence that Bewley reviews. In particular, the idea of interviewing not only about wage determination but also about the respondents’ reasoning can be problematic. Observations are somehow more reliable about “facts” than about responses to questions about motivation. Do we know enough about the respondents’ incentives during the interviews? Yet, it must be acknowledged that these answers are often fascinating.
I now move away from the micro studies and take up a particular aspect of these models, relating to norms or reference points, which are a central part of the new applied models of fairness in wage setting. Let me conduct my discussion by means of a recent interesting work by Driscoll and Holden (2002, 2004) about fairness and inflation persistence. Driscoll and Holden suggest that inclusion of fairness considerations in a standard model of wage bargaining leads to a range of equilibria and this feature can in turn be useful for explaining inflation persistence in the data.11
The Driscoll–Holden model depicts a symmetric economy with many monopolistically competitive firms and worker insiders bargaining over wages. The workers are concerned about fair treatment and in particular they resent being worse off than identical workers elsewhere.12 Moreover, the dissatisfaction from being paid less is stronger than the satisfaction from being paid more. There is thus a kink in the utility function of workers at the wage level of other workers in their reference group. This is a form of loss aversion, which is often employed in the literature on wage norms. Finally, there are several symmetrical groups of workers in the economy.
In this kind of model, Nash wage bargaining is characterized by the existence of two thresholds. There is a unique outcome, which is equal to what is perceived to happen in the reference group when the reference group wage is within the thresholds. If the reference group wage is either above the upper threshold or below the lower threshold, then the bargaining outcome is equal to the corresponding threshold. The thresholds depend on the reference group wage, the economy-wide average wage, and other macro variables.
Assume for simplicity that there are only two groups in the economy, and that the aggregate demand function specifies demand as being equal to real balances. A log-linearized version of the model can be written as follows. The contract wage xJt of a group J is determined as13
where are threshold parameters and the log price level is
The idea is that there are thresholds within which the wage must lie. Note that I have added the superscript “e” to the reference wage of the other group. This is to emphasize the reaction function of the workers in response to perceived wages elsewhere. mt and pt are the logs of the money supply and price level, respectively.
Taking account of the definition of the price level we can write the model as
where
Here the notation means or . Since the economy is symmetric, a rational expectations equilibrium (REE) obtains when xJt = and it is easy to represent the possible REE by Figure 5.1. There is clearly a whole range of equilibria, represented by the segment (A, B).
Changes in the money supply will move the graph of the best response map. Yet, inside the range (A, B), the REE contract wage may well be unresponsive to money supply variations. This depends on the perceptions of the workers in wage bargaining. Driscoll and Holden assume that workers are just concerned about the wages elsewhere and use past data as a way of generating their perceptions. In this case the whole segment is indeed REE and an interior equilibrium is pinned down by history and it will not respond to current policy variations. On the other hand, the perceptions of workers might be more subtle. In particular, the perceptions could well incorporate money supply variations, especially if systematic patterns in money supply movements are apparent. If this is the case, then monetary policy variations will not leave the contracted wages unaffected, as workers will incorporate such systematic patterns into their wage formation.
I will not pursue the analysis any further; I just wanted to make a basic point: we need to know much more about the determination of fairness reference points and how the environment in which agents operate (in particular, macro variables) affects their reference points.
The recent research on wages and fairness surveyed by Bewley is highly interesting and thought provoking. It has already provided useful evidence on what might be empirically the more interesting models of labor markets as part of the macro economy. There is clearly potential for further theoretical and empirical work concerning the determination of reference points in different economic environments and how these considerations affect range of potential equilibria and the effects of economic policy.
Akerlof, G. A. 1982. Labor contracts as gift exchange. Quarterly Journal of Economics 97:543–69.
Akerlof, G. A., and J. Yellen. 1988. Fairness and unemployment. American Economic Review 78:44–49.
Bewley, T. 1999. Why Wages Don’t Fall During a Recession. Harvard University Press.
Driscoll, J. C., and S. Holden. 2002. Coordination, fair treatment and inflation persistence. Working Paper, Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System.
——. 2004. Fairness and inflation persistence. Journal of the European Economic Association 2:240–50.
Ireland, P. 2001. Sticky-price models of the business cycle: specification and stability. Journal of Monetary Economics 47:3–18.
Lindbeck, A., and D. Snower. 1988. Cooperation, harassment and involuntary unemployment: an insider–outsider approach. American Economic Review 78:167–88.
Roberts, J. M. 1997. Is inflation sticky? Journal of Monetary Economics 39:173–96.
Shapiro, C., and J. E. Stiglitz. 1984. Equilibrium unemployment as a worker discipline device. American Economic Review 74:433–44.
Solow, R. A. 1990. The Labor Market as a Social Institution. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.
Weiss, A. 1990. Efficiency Wages: Models of Unemployment, Layoffs and Wage Dispersion. Princeton University Press.
1I am grateful to Professor Jennifer Smith of the University of Warwick for comments. An earlier version of this chapter appears in H. Gintis, S. Bowles, R. T. Boyd, and E. Fehr (eds). (forthcoming). Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in Economic Life. MIT Press.
2These data are cited in Akerlof et al. (1996, p. 8).
3In the United States, a legal distinction is made between layoffs and firings. Layoffs occur because of lack of work, whereas workers are fired for wrongdoing.
4I owe this reference to Angier (2002), who makes the connection with the experimental work of Ernst Fehr.
5See Figure 6 in Fehr and Fischbacher (2002).
6In Fehr et al. (2001), the employer chooses the type of model used, there is no excess supply of labor, and the experimenter matches one worker to one employer in each period, whereas in Fehr and Gächter (2002) the experimenter chooses the model, there is an excess supply of labor, and the matching of workers to employers is determined by market bidding.
7New Classical Macroeconomics and Real Business Cycle theory is, however, largely based on fully flexible wages and prices.
8Note that pay cuts are more easily accepted if they save a large number of jobs or possibly the whole firm.
9However, unionization of workers leads to more clear-cut formulation of the workers’ notion of market wages.
10Of course, there is the other main line of macroeconomics, which purports to explain wage formation as part of competitive contracting leading to market efficiency.
11The role of inflation versus price level persistence has been discussed a great deal in the recent macro literature. The verdict is still out (see, for example, the most recent papers by Ireland (2001) and Roberts (1997), who argue against inflation persistence).
12This assumption is not supported by Bewley’s paper, except when there are unions, as is the case here.
13My notation is somewhat different from that of Driscoll and Holden.