A medieval bronze image like the Pathur
Na

ar

ja, fabricated in the twelfth century for a small Hindu

aiva temple in southern India, would have served primarily as a processional icon. The main object of worship in the Pathur
temple would have been a
ivali
ga, a non-anthropomorphic stone icon fixed at the center of the inner sanctum of the temple. (By the 1970s, when the Pathur
Na

ar

ja was disinterred, the temple had fallen into
disrepair. Fragments of the original stone
li
ga were found in the ground near the temple ruins, but it was no longer usable for
ritual purposes.) As the principal cultic object, the
ivali
ga would have received daily offerings of worship, known as
p
j
, performed by priests on behalf of the entire local community. It is important to emphasize that the
ivali
ga was not simply a symbolic object of worship. According to local

aiva premises as articulated in priestly guidebooks (or
gamas), the
li
ga should be regarded and treated as a living instantiation of the god

iva. Local devotees considered the
li
ga to be the god himself, as he made himself present in this particular community, for the benefit of his votaries.

iva was
a universal god who also made himself manifest in many local
temples throughout southern India and beyond, in the form of icons fabricated by humans to receive his divine presence.
2
As well as being a manifestation of the universal god, the local embodiment of

iva was regarded as the “lord” and “owner” (
Skt.
sv
min, Tamil
u
aiy
r) of the
temple and all its properties. In the medieval South Indian context, these properties might be quite extensive, for the
temples acted as economic centers within their society. They received gifts of money, goods, and land; they leased or sold
land to receive commodities needed for
ritual; they employed persons to supply provisions and carry out all necessary ceremonial activities. The properties of the
temple owned by the deity could include also the various additional icons, such as the images taken in procession during the
regular temple festivals. In this sense it is appropriate to imagine that the Pathur
Na

ar

ja would once have been considered a “
property” belonging to the central
ivali
ga of the Pathur temple.
We can construct a clearer picture of medieval
temple practices and their underlying cultural presuppositions from inscriptions. On the walls of most old
temples in southern India may be found numerous epigraphs carved permanently into the stone. These inscriptional texts deal
predominantly with the affairs of the temple. This profuse corpus of documents can tell us a great deal about the presuppositions
and practices of the medieval South Indians who originally composed them.
3
The key tenet that lies at the foundation of the great corpus of medieval South Indian inscriptions is that the central images
or icons of Hindu
temples were identified as living deities. The inscriptional texts regularly
refer to and address these divine persons by name. Usually the deity’s name includes the location of the deity, as the “Lord
of such-and-such a place,” or alternatively the name of the
temple itself. In the common phrasing, the god “is pleased to dwell” in the earthly temple. There are no locutions that might
suggest a distinction between the icon and the deity. Rather, the inscriptions consider the enlivened icon to be a living
personal deity, a localized instantiation of a universal god (whether

iva,
Vi


u, the Goddess, or some other divine figure) who also lives in many other places, in other localized manifestations.
The

r

vai


ava school of medieval South India articulated this tenet as
Vi


u’s “icon incarnations” (
arc
-avat
ra). For the

r

vai


ava theologians, the god Vi


u makes himself present and accessible to human worshipers through various
incarnations. They identify several types or categories of incarnations. At times he becomes incarnate in the anthropomorphic
and zoomorphic forms we know as R

ma, K



a, the Tortoise, the Boar, and others. He manifests himself as an “inner controller”
(
antary
min) in the hearts of his human devotees. And Vi


u also enters into and enlivens the naturally occurring and human-fabricated
icons that serve as the supports for his divine presence in shrines and
temples.
4 These are Vi


u’s icon incarnations, just as real and animate as any other.
As a living being, the central deity of a
temple acts as recipient of all the gifts (
devad
na) that devotees donate to the institution. These gifts begin with the temple itself, as the palatial habitation fabricated
to house the deity, and they include the ancillary images that share the residence. The gifts would also include grants of
land whose revenue would be used to provide the material support for the
ritual ceremonies of honoring and celebrating the iconic deity at the center of all temple transactions.
The recipient of all these gifts also becomes their proprietor or owner. The inscriptions generally take for granted the god’s
ownership of the
temple and its properties. The deity, like any lord or
property owner, need not always administer his or her properties directly.
5
In some inscriptions from

aiva
temples, another semi-divinity in image form, Ca


e

a, acts as the assigned administrator (
nibandhana) for the
temple possessions of his lord and master,

iva. More practically, various human agents take care of the material transactions involved in the
administration of temple properties. These might include priests, temple trustees, village
assemblies, local elites, or members of the royal family. The multiple activities of these human agents, as reflected in the
prolix temple inscriptions, have enabled social historians to learn a great deal about South Indian society during medieval
times.
6 However, for our purposes, the most important underlying cultural fact is that the administrators of temple properties organized
their transactions as agents dealing with possessions that belonged ultimately to the divine beings residing in the central
sanctuaries of Hindu
temples.
As Leslie Orr observes, these inscriptions were meant “to serve as legal documents, sanctioning the transfer of
property, the undertaking of various responsibilities, and the acquisition of rights and privileges” (
2006: xiii). The exhortations and avowals regularly included in the inscriptions, she points out, give the texts “the force of
a
charter, if not a
contract.” The inscriptions point to arrangements that are to be maintained, ideally, “as long as the sun and moon endure.”
But in the realm of human beings, all sorts of departures from the ideal may ensue. Properties of the gods may be mismanaged
or expropriated, just as any other property. A number of inscriptions record such misappropriations and the efforts made to
restore the proper order. We do not hear of
temple gods suing in court in medieval South India, but there are many indications that the deities found agents among human
political authorities, such as officers of the
king or local authorities, to act on their behalf.
Not everyone in classical or medieval India agreed with the South Indian perspective on divine images articulated in medieval
inscriptions. The primary legal literature of medieval India grows out of a different tradition of religious practice and
reflects an uneasy accommodation with, or more strongly a critical skepticism toward, the conceptual bases of Hindu
temple practice.
Dharma


stra literature recognizes the Vedas as the fundamental textual source of authority, and it considers
yajña, fire offerings made to immaterial divine figures, as the paradigmatic
ritual means by which humans ought best to interact with the divine.
Dharma


stra authors and commentators certainly were aware of the common practices of Hindu image worship. A few passages
in the Dharma


stra literature acknowledge the worship of images as a positive practice, and even set forth procedures for
proper worship. For example, the
Vi
u Sm
ti prescribes the worship of Vi


u V

sudeva in the form of a divine image (
dev
rc
) as one of the regular daily duties of a householder (
VDh 65).
7 Likewise the
Baudh
yana G
hya Pari
i
a S
tra, an appendix to the text of the Baudh

yana school on household rites, provides instructions for installing and worshiping
images of
Vi


u,

iva, and other deities (Harting
1922). While some
Vedic schools evidently accepted the theistic practices of image worship and selectively incorporated these rites into their
own rules of conduct, other
Brahmin schools were clearly not so accommodating. Indeed, in the Dharma


stra literature, the predominant attitude toward
worship of images was hostile. And there was good reason for this hostility, since image worship and the growing cult of
temple
Hinduism were supplanting the
Vedic sacrificial system as the dominant form of public Hindu
ritual practice in India. As Heinrich von Stietencron has argued, this shift involved a conflict within the Brahmin class,
with “bitter feuds between traditionalists and innovators.”
8
An excellent example of a “traditionalist” perspective may be seen in the most influential of the
dharma
stras, the
M
nava Dharma
stra, composed around the second century
CE. In his instructions for
Brahmin householders,
Manu does not provide any guidelines for the worship of images. However, he does take note of a new category of
ritual specialist, the
devalaka, a priest who attends images in a shrine or
temple. He recommends that
Brahmins concerned with their personal purity shun the temple priest. For instance, in the monthly ancestral offerings (
r
ddha), a good Brahmin householder maintains the continuity and status of his own lineage. Therefore, Manu recommends, it is important
to exclude from these rites anyone who might detract from the purity of the ritual or of the person offering it. Among those
to be shunned are the
devalakas: “Physicians, temple priests, meat sellers, and those who live by trade – these should be avoided at divine and ancestral
offerings” (
MDh 3.152).
9 Manu cites these among a larger set of the disinvited: not only doctors and butchers, but also
men with deformed nails or black teeth, people with one eye, actors, singers, gamblers, drunks, Buddhists (
n
stikas), and many others should be avoided at the ceremonies of ancestral solidarity (
MDh 3.150–66). In the end, Manu concludes, wise
Brahmins “should avoid those lowest of the twice-born, men of despicable conduct alongside whom it is unfit to eat” (
MDh 3.167).
Manu’s later commentator
Kull

ka gives a further reason for excluding
temple priests from the
r
ddha ceremonies. Kull

ka glosses the term “
devalaka” as “an attendant of images” (
pratim
-paric
raka), and explains that they obtain their livelihood from god’s treasures. Food given to the temple deities ends up in the bellies
of temple priests. Like physicians, butchers, and
merchants, they act for the sake of profit, Kull

ka says, not for the sake of
dharma. It is noteworthy that Kull

ka here accepts the tenet that gifts to a temple ought to be considered the
property of the presiding deity. In this light,
devalakas can be viewed as thieves who appropriate the donations given to gods to satisfy their own needs.
10
Later in his
dharma
stra,
Manu explains what will happen to the greedy
temple priests: “If a man seizes what belongs to a god [
devasva] or a
Brahmin out of greed, in the next world that evil man will live on the leftovers of vultures” (
MDh 11.26). Here Manu also seems to accept the theistic principle that what is given to a temple belongs to the god of that temple.
For Manu’s commentators, though, it was not so simple, for the concept of
deva, “god,” was itself problematic.
Manu and other
Dharma


stra authors might seek to exclude
temple priests from the ceremonies of pious
Brahmins, but a more subtle and far-reaching critique of the practices of Hindu temple worship came in the definitional struggle
over the category of divinity. Here we need to consider another branch of orthodox exegetical literature concerned with
dharma, the P

rva
M

m


s

school of Jaimini and his successors. As
Robert Lingat (
1973) (and
McCrea, in this volume) have observed, the M

m


s

school provided the Dharma


stra commentators with their basic interpretive principles.
The
Vedic
exegesis of
M

m


s

starts from the axiom that
dharma has been established completely and authoritatively in the Vedas. The task is therefore one of interpretation. If proper
human action follows directly
from the words of the Vedas, the question is: Which of those words possess an
injunctive force (
vidhi), and which are simply rhetorical (
arthav
da). The Vedas clearly enjoin humans to perform sacrifice, but what is the basis for the efficacy of this
ritual practice?
This reciprocal-exchange theory may well reflect the common or worldly understanding of sacrifice. However, in his second
or “conclusive view” (
siddh
nta), Jaimini argues against it. Sacrifice does not require any outside intervention to attain its effects. Rather, sacrifice
is inherently efficacious. That is, by obeying the
injunction of the
Veda to perform sacrifice, one attains the “intrinsic self-completion of the sacrifice,” which
M

m


s

authors call the
ap
rva. If the sacrifice fulfills itself and accomplishes
dharma, then there is no need to be concerned with divine agency.
The problem with excluding the
Vedic gods from a role in
Vedic sacrifice is that this appears to go against the contents of the
Vedic texts. The hymns of the Vedas repeatedly address the gods as if they have bodies, eat and drink the sacrificial offerings,
enjoy their meals, and reward the human hosts accordingly. But this, the
M

m


s

exegetes reply, is a mistaken view. The gods do not have bodies, argues the M

m


s

scholar

abara in his commentary
on Jaimini’s earlier work. If they lack bodies, then they do not need the sacrificial sustenance, nor do they have the ability
to reward their votaries.

abara interprets all
Vedic passages that offer anthropomorphic images of the gods as figurative or inconclusive. When the
g Veda says “we have taken hold of Indra’s hand,” says

abara, it means only “we depend on Indra.” This, he goes on, is just a rhetorical
reinforcement (
arthav
da) to the
injunction (
vidhi) that one should offer sacrifice to Indra. What then is left of the god Indra? In

abara’s austere hermeneutics,
the only reliable existence of the gods lies in the sound (
abda) of their names or the mantras addressed to them. “Divinity is only sound,” proclaims the M

m


s

school. The god Indra has
no necessary existence apart from the name “Indra” and its usage in sacrificial activities compelled by the
Veda and performed by humans.
The
M

m


s

masters Jaimini and

abara argue against a theistic understanding of the
Vedic sacrifice, but their rigorous interpretation can easily be extended against the premises of Hindu image worship as well.
Writing in the fifth century,

abara was certainly aware of the growing popularity of the Hindu gods
Vi


u and

iva and their expanding
temples. If the worship of icons depends on the assumption that gods exist as autonomous beings and enter into physical forms
like images to receive the offerings of their devotees, then

abara’s denial of divine embodiment subverts this practice at
its most fundamental level. Further, the M

m


s

restriction of divine agency reappears in the writings of
Dharma


stra commentators like
Medh

tithi, the ninth-century Kashmiri author whose explication of
Manu, the
Manubh
ya, is one of the preeminent authorities in the genre.
12
We have seen already that
Manu mentions the “
property of the gods” (
devasva) in the context of theft and its consequences. One who seizes the property of the gods or
Brahmins, says Manu, is liable for severe
punishment in the next world (
MDh 11.26).
Medh

tithi informs us, however, that this “property of the gods” in fact belongs to humans of the three twice-born classes.
Devasva denotes the wealth that has been set aside for the purpose of rituals like sacrifice directed toward the gods. But it must
belong in fact to human proprietors, for it is not possible for gods to have direct
ownership (
sva-sv
min) of property. Divinity cannot make volitional use of wealth, nor can it exercise protection over it.
Medh

tithi does recognize the more common viewpoint, that in ordinary or worldly usage (
loka),
devasva may indicate the
property connected with four-armed images (
pratim
) of the gods. However, he rejoins, the fact that one refers to the four-armed icon as an “image” indicates already that it
is not itself divine. Further, there is no definition of god that can be applied to such an image. Therefore, as he has argued
previously (in his comments on
MDh 2.189), one must take
Manu’s reference to “god’s property” as figurative (
gu
av
da), just as the
Vedic passages referring to Indra’s hand and the like are to be understood as figurative expressions.
After surveying several
Dharma


stra works,
Günther-Dietz Sontheimer has summarized the position of the commentators succinctly: “We can see from the texts which we have
cited above that the main argument against the corporality of a
devat
and its capacity to hold
property is derived from the
p
rvam
m
s
doctrines according to which deities are purely hypothetical entities, posited to assist in the performance of a sacrifice
and subordinate to it” (
1964: 68). At the same time, as
Sontheimer recognizes, this placed the legal perspective of the
Dharma


stra masters at odds with the broader public practices of Hindu
temple worship: “It appears that in practice there existed no difficulty in the donor’s dedicating
property to the deity, whose servants appropriated the property on behalf of the deity and used the property for the benefit
of the deity. The property in the eyes of the public belonged to the deity” (
1964: 69). It is difficult to know if the constrictive orthodox
Dharma


stra interpretation of divine agency made any impact on South Indian
temple practices of the medieval period. Inscriptions generally indicate that the icon-deities continued to act as lords and
proprietors of the temple properties, despite the
M

m


s

view. However, the discrepancy between Dharma


stra principle and public practice did pose a problem for legal theory
in the
colonial period. This led to the new concept of the deity as a “
juristic person.”
As the British began to assume direct political rule over territories in India, starting in the mid-eighteenth century, they
faced a series of practical administrative and legal quandaries. One fundamental decision was taken by Governor-General
Warren Hastings, when he chose to establish the legal system of British India, as far as possible, on indigenous or Indian
principles. “We have endeavoured to adapt our Regulations,” he explained to the
East India Company directors in 1772, “to the Manners and Understandings of the People, and the Exigencies of the Country,
adhering as closely as we are able to their ancient uses and institutions.”
13 In the sphere of law, this required the British to seek out, and seek to understand, the existing legal codes of India. For
the Hindu population, they identified the
Dharma


stra genre as the most pertinent legal literature. The result was an extensive effort of collaborative scholarship
on Dharma


stra literature
by British administrators and
Brahmin
Sanskrit
pandits, aimed at developing a usable “Hindu law” from the great mass of Dharma


stra literature.
14 This label is not really accurate, since the legal system that grew out of British administrative application of Dharma


stra
principles was in fact a complex
colonial-period hybrid. Not just Dharma


stra, but also Roman, British, and
Muslim legal concepts were drawn on by both British and Indian jurists, in new institutional settings created by British rulers,
resulting in something altogether different from anything
Manu and Medh

tithi could have imagined.
Early juristic decisions of the British
colonial period involving
temple properties tended to allow the deities their
agency and their
ownership, as
Sontheimer has shown (
1964: 78–80). The
judges of the early nineteenth century appear to have supported what they considered popular Hindu understandings and practices.
However, by the late nineteenth century, Indian jurists began to revise this legal view and to grant greater weight to the
Dharma


stra perspective. Specifically they divested the icons of their claims to full
identity. Following the Dharma


stra notion of “figurative” divinity, they introduced the Roman legal concept of “
juristic personhood” as a way to accept the religious intentions of a donor who gave
property to a temple image without accepting the donor’s theological premise that god was embodied in that image. The deity,
they argued, holds property only in an “ideal sense,” since it, as a “merely artificial person,” only personifies the pious
motivation of the donor. Thus they ruled out the idea underlying South Indian temple practice that deities could become embodied
in physical icons, and shifted the legal focus to the intentions or motivations of human benefactors of religious institutions.
Sontheimer expertly traces the development of this new legal doctrine through a series of court cases and decisions (
1964: 80–97). The results can be found in twentieth-century legal compendia of Hindu law by learned jurists like Dinshah Fardunji
Mulla (
Principles of Hindu Law,
1929), Satish Chandra Bagchi (
Juristic Personality of Hindu Deities,
1933), and Bijan Kumar Mukherjea (
The Hindu Law of Religious and Charitable Trust,
1952). Mukherjea summarizes the resulting legal status of divine images in several propositions. First, neither God nor any supernatural
being can be a person in law. This means that the Supreme Being which an icon represents cannot own
property in a legal sense. If it did, Mukherjea explains, then the Supreme Being of one
temple icon might be able to make a claim against the Supreme Being of another. Second, the property given to a temple by
its
founder is disposed for the pious spiritual purposes of the donor. And third, that pious aim of the founder continues to reside
in the physical icon, which represents or symbolizes that intention. Echoing
Medh

tithi, Mukherjea cautions that a deity can be said to exercise
ownership only in a secondary or ideal sense. “The deity as owner represents nothing else but the intentions of the founder”
(Mukherjea
1952: 46). This is in briefest form what is meant by the
juristic personhood of the divine icon.
Mukherjea’s propositions bring the economic activities of Hindu
temples as “endowments and charitable trusts” within the scope of a state administrative and legal system that does not recognize
the claims of gods and other supernatural beings.
15 Through the notion of a god’s
juristic personality, the human administrators of a
temple may conduct its affairs as if the deity embodied in the icon were the actual proprietor of all its properties. The
“popular view” of a divine icon’s agency may not cohere with the more restricted legal perspective of its juristic personality,
but the two viewpoints can accommodate one another.
When the bronze image of dancing

iva from Pathur,
Tamil Nadu, appeared in the UK High Court in London, the Indian legal formulation of

iva’s
juristic personality reached beyond the national boundaries of India. Quoting Mukherjea’s
authoritative propositions,
Justice Kennedy held that

iva, embodied in the
ivali
ga at the ruined Pathur
temple, could act as a plaintiff, as a juristic personality embodying the pious intention of the anonymous twelfth-century
founder of the temple. Further,

iva’s claim on the bronze processional image was superior to that of Robert Borden, the Canadian
collector who had purchased it in London. The image would be returned to India.
For
Justice Kennedy and the lawyers directly involved in the Pathur
Na

ar

ja case, the role of the god

iva in recovering the Na

ar

ja as his
property may have been limited to the purely symbolic role of an embodiment of a past donor’s pious intentions. Modern-day
Hindus in southern India, however, understood the dynamics of the case differently. As one Tamil Nadu state official put it,
“I can only say that lord Na

ar

ja himself won the case appearing before courts in the form of the idol” (Vidyasagar
1991).