NARRATOLOGY
While the study of storytelling techniques in the Western world dates back to Aristotle’s Poetics, the term “narratology” itself appeared in the 1960s, as an important part of French structuralism. This movement was a paradigm shift more than a single and precise theory, and centered on the belief that the structuring elements and relationships that bind semantic units together form a superstructure of meaning, which must be studied if we are to really understand the events and objects that are spawned through this structure. Given how games remain a process that unfolds from a core structure of rules, structuralism made the connection between game and narrative all the more visible. In the 1966 issue of Communications—which Marie-Laure Ryan refers to as the “birthday of narratology” (Ryan, 2006, p. 3)—Roland Barthes made a quite explicit statement in this regard:
[A] great many narratives set up two opponents at odds with each other over the possession of a stake … This “dual” is all the more interesting because it points out the affinity between narrative and the structure of certain (quite modern) games in which two equal opponents set out to conquer an object placed in circulation by a referee. This scheme recalls the actantial matrix proposed by Greimas, an analogy that is not surprising if one pauses to realize that play, considered as a language, possesses the same symbolic structure as that found in language and narrative.
(Barthes, [1966] 1975, p. 259)
This duel (as the original French reads, rather than dual) of equal opponents harkens back to Roger Caillois’s agôn category identified in Man, Play and Games (Caillois, [1958] 1961), and highlights the importance of conflict as a component of narrative. As H. Porter Abbott wrote in the Cambridge Introduction to Narrative:
[I]n almost every narrative of any interest, there is a conflict in which power is at stake. You might say that conflict structures narrative. The ancient Greek word for conflict (actually “contest” is closer) is agon, and how the agon played out formed the spine of any Greek tragedy.
(Abbott, [1993] 2002, p. 55)
Thus, understanding how conflict structures the agonistic forces at work throughout a narrative brings something of a game-like quality to it.
The Boiling Point: Ludology and Narratology
The structuralist connection between narrative and games has been one of the entry points in the formation of ludology (in the broadest sense of a “discipline that studies game and play activities,” as put forth by Frasca, 1999). In 1997, Espen Aarseth’s Cybertext and Janet Murray’s Hamlet on the Holodeck offered two opposed viewpoints on the issue of narrative and textuality. For Aarseth, the fundamental differences between narratives and games required that researchers develop novel frameworks and methods for studying the latter; for Murray, the computer as a medium and the principles of interactivity (including video games) were hinting at new narrative forms and modes, with a potential yet to be charted out. The table was set for the first debate of the nascent field of game studies, opposing narratology and ludology. While narratology was singled out as an example, the debate more broadly concerned the appropriateness of studying games by applying pre-existing theories and approaches, or by devising novel, specific conceptual tools. The debate did not last long, and was in fact repudiated by both “parties” as a non-event. Janet Murray remarked: “The ludology vs narratology argument can never be resolved because one group of people is defining both sides of it. The ‘ludologists’ are debating a phantom of their own creation” (Murray, 2005, p. 3), echoing Gonzalo Frasca’s previous interrogation: “Who are the narrativists?” (Frasca, 2003).
It appears the whole ludology vs narratology “debate” may have been overblown by Markku Eskelinen’s oft-cited hyperbolic (and provocative) claim: “Outside academic theory people are usually excellent at making distinctions between narrative, drama and games. If I throw a ball at you I don’t expect you to drop it and wait until it starts telling stories” (Eskelinen, 2001). Rune Klevjer extrapolated a position of “radical ludology” from this statement, to the effect that “everything other than the pure game mechanics of a computer game is essentially alien to its true aesthetic form” (Klevjer, 2002, pp. 191–192). While Eskelinen’s particular phrasing indeed appears excessive, most writings from both camps (the self-identified ludologists, and researchers vaguely defined by others as narratologists or narrativists) were a lot less polemical. Consider Celia Pearce’s call for a reworking of the definitions and tools of narrative theories so that they can account for the specificity of games:
It is very important to understand that narrative has a profoundly different function in games than it does in other narrative-based media.… although there is much to be learned from traditional narratives, and a great value in drawing comparisons between the two, without understanding the fundamental differences, the discourse becomes ultimately irrelevant because it entirely misses the fundamental point of what games are about.
(Pearce, 2004, p. 144)
Though Frasca (2003) implicitly includes Pearce among the “narrativists,” in the end, her position does not appear too far away from Frasca’s own call for identifying the specificities of games. The difference resides in whether narrative constitutes a worthwhile analytical frame, or if some other approach should be privileged:
[T]he real issue here is not if games are narratives or not, but if we can really expand our knowledge on games by taking whichever route we follow. So far, I am convinced that we should privilege other forms of representing reality, such as simulation, which are more coherent with the characteristics of games.
(Frasca, 2003)
The contrast between these positions is much more reasonable than an all-out “theory war,” to echo Pearce’s 2005 follow-up.
Making Sense of the Overlap
Both narrativists and ludologists agree with Aarseth’s initial contention that “[t]o claim that there is no difference between games and narratives is to ignore essential qualities of both categories” (Aarseth, 1997, p. 5). All in all, it appears the second part of this quote is needed as much as the first: “the difference [between games and narratives] is not clear-cut, and there is significant overlap between the two” (Aarseth, 1997, p. 5).
It is worth keeping the structuralist roots of narratology in mind when considering the utility and history of this discipline for video game studies. The focus on unearthing underlying structural principles of regularity is common to both structuralist narratology and the video game player’s experience: after all, one of the primary tasks which the gamer faces when engaging in gameplay is to build a mental image of the procedural computing process that is working to make the video game manifest (Arsenault and Perron, 2008). This fascination for underlying structural elements also characterized the study of narrative in game studies. Early theoretical inquiries aimed at uncovering game-like properties of narrative in the vein of Barthes’ initial structuralist claim. Arguing that “game designers are much less interested in telling a story than in creating a compelling framework for play,” Celia Pearce opted to “look at narrative in a play-centric context” (Pearce, 2004, p. 144) and remarked that “certain story genres are more innately gamelike to begin with,” citing examples such as “mysteries, mission or goal-based adventures, or combat scenarios” and “the world-based narrative” (Pearce, 2004, p. 153). Marie-Laure Ryan, arguably the person to have written the most on narrative and fiction in games to this day, has also used the video game as a new stepping stone or vantage point from which the central notions of story, plot, narrative, character, temporality, and fictional world can all be re-examined and redefined (see Ryan, 2001, 2004, and 2006, among others).
These studies reflect the shift that happened in the study of narrative as well, as the structuralist roots of narratology gave way to post-structuralist narratology in the 1980s. Rather than reducing the apparent divergences among narratives in quest for a single, unitary structure, post-structuralist narratology embraced the complexity of narrative across modes, media, and genres. Ultimately, narratology branched out to a plurality of other fields in what David Herman called “post-classical narratology”: “No longer designating just a subfield of structuralist literary theory, narratology can now be used to refer to any principled approach to the study of narratively organized discourse, literary, historiographical, conversational, filmic, or other” (Herman, 1999, p. 27). Through this change of perspective, games can be studied from a narrative standpoint by examining how they renew, complicate, or transform our understanding of what a narrative is, and of how narration can operate. For example, in many Japanese role-playing games from the 1980s and 1990s such as Final Fantasy (Square, 1987) or Dragon Warrior (Chunsoft, 1986), the player moves his party through towns and dungeons, but also on an “overworld map.” While the characters are represented identically in both instances, the scale of the game-world is very different: Brecconary Town and Tantagel Castle may be only seven steps apart on the overworld map, but those steps do not, in fact, represent the same kind of space-time travel as taking seven steps in the town square or in the castle. Every step the player-character takes on the overworld map results in the game effectively employing the visual channel of communication to narrate a summary of a journey through the lands, through manipulation of that fictional world’s spacetime continuum. Hence, Jesper Juul can reconcile the storytelling aspects of video game play through recourse to fiction instead of narrative, which allows a modular conceptualization of the video game playing activity depending on a given player’s particular interest:
That many fictional game worlds are incoherent does not mean that video games are dysfunctional providers of fiction, but that they project fictional worlds in their own flickering, provisional, and optional way. Of all cultural forms that project fictional worlds, the video game is a special form in which players can meaningfully engage with the game even while refusing to imagine the world that the game projects--the rules of a game are often sufficient to keep the player’s interest. Perhaps this places games on par with songs, opera, and ballet.
(Juul, 2005, p. 200)
This accounting for the player’s desire is a cornerstone of Roger Odin’s semio-pragmatic model of fiction (Odin, 2000), in which one produces an imaginary text from a string of signifiers provided by an object, and that depends on the mode of reading that is privileged by a given subject, one of these modes being, naturally, that of fictionalization. Some players may like narratively-heavy games such as Metal Gear Solid (Konami, 1998), Heavy Rain (Quantic Dream, 2010), or Dragon Age: Origins (BioWare, 2011), because of their strong emphasis on storytelling; other players may not like them for the very same reason; and yet some other players may still like them despite these storytelling ambitions.
Extrinsic Narrativity: Story Contents
The optional nature of the video game narrative legitimizes from the outset a certain type of study: narrative semiotics (which film narratologist André Gaudreault dubbed the “narratology of content”) that “privileges the study of narrative content (the story told), entirely independently of the medium through which it is recounted” (Gaudreault, 2009, p. 30). The other “school” of narratology, distinct from the first (though the two are always intertwined), is the “narratology of expression,” characterized by the fact that
narrative expression (the discourse of telling), for this school, is more important than the content […] The principal concern here is the means of expression […] by which a piece of information is communicated to the auditor.
(Gaudreault, 2009, p. 30)
Out of this double helix of narratology, Gaudreault infers two types of narrativity:
We might call one kind of narrative extrinsic: it deals solely with narrative content, independent of its means of expression. The other kind could be called intrinsic narrativity in that its narrative quality derives directly from the means of expression.
(Gaudreault, 2009, p. 31)
These two types of narrativity have wildly different implications and importance in the field of game studies. As Henry Jenkins (2004) and I (2008, pp. 29–33) pointed out, it is a fact that some video games include a story and expend great effort to make it the most important point of the experience they offer, while others feature a very limited story (or even better, no story at all). While it is certainly feasible to study select stories or some narrative figures and tropes, in and of themselves, rather than the means by which they are put into play by the unique properties of the video game, doing so tells us nothing about games themselves, as Herman and Vervaeck’s statement illustrates:
[I]t is the way in which a story is narrated that turns it into what it is. Those who insist on denying the importance of the method of narration by reducing a story to content might just as well go to the movies or watch television because both of them can offer similar content.
(2005, p. 7)
Incidentally, not much academic work has followed this path: by and large, it is rather video game criticism that addresses the narrative contents of games, such as plot twists, narrative inconsistencies, rhythm, script and writing quality of games, and which sometimes offers insights of a theoretical nature.
That video games can serve as a host medium for extrinsic narrativity (by way of adapting already-existing narratives for the medium, for instance) does not say much of the video game’s narrative potential in itself; if some games feature extensive storytelling while others have none at all, then the relationship between games and narratives can be seen as contingent and arbitrary, and the presence of a narrative is wholly incidental to whether something can be called a game or not, as Jesper Juul remarked (2005, p. 13). This is why in many game genres, narrative plays second fiddle to gameplay. For instance, many shooters, fighting, and action games feature stories whose sole purpose is to justify a diverse array of levels, enemies and obstacles to be tackled. And yet, to have narrative not be the main focus of the play experience is not a reason to either discredit the study of narrative, or to discredit the narratives found in games themselves. The ludological line of thought rightly stated that narrative need not be the central, privileged subject of game studies. A constructive reply would be that gameplay need not be the only subject of game studies, and that perhaps this “gameplay” word is, in itself, a handy construct that conflates a myriad of different features (point of view, physical interaction, spatial exploration, constant cognitive reframings, etc.) that can in reality only be understood by cross-disciplinary examination from related fields.
That being said, a number of useful studies can be undertaken to examine how the extrinsic narrative elements brought into games can contribute to the game system, or to the player’s gameplay activity. Rune Klevjer’s short paper “In Defense of Cut-Scenes” (2002), for example, argues that while no relationship of necessity binds narrative to games, the framing narrative still plays an important role in the game experience; this also includes the cut-scene, a moment of non-interactive narrative development that performs a number of gameplay functions such as establishing rhythm, building tension and suspense, and acting as a reward for player progression.
Story Structures
By and large, the most common research conducted on narrative content in games so far has focused on the narrative structures or topologies of games, in an attempt to identify the recurrent ways in which interactivity can gate or deploy narrativity and vice versa. These studies forego the semantic contents of game narratives to examine the syntactic structuring of these narrative entities and events. Structures of interactive narrative could easily fill entire books, but it is possible to provide a brief overview of the key recurring figures identified across multiple sources (Phelps, 1996; Samsel and Wimberley, 1998; Ryan, 2001, pp. 246–258; DeMarle, 2006; Chandler, 2007, pp. 101–115). All structures of interactive narrative provide ways to balance the usual conflicting demands of story and game. These structures may be placed at any point on an axis between two poles, which Chandler identifies as logocentric design and mythocentric design: “Logocentric design is linear and controlled and has been plotted out and documented by the designer” (Chandler, 2007, p. 102), while
mythocentric design is wide-open and free-ranging and consists of arenas for player action that have been created by the developers. The player, as author of the core experience, gets to choose the goals and means of the game experience. Unlike logocentric design, the developers are facilitators, not creators, of the events that transpire.
(Chandler, 2007, p. 108)
The two approaches could be contrasted by comparing Heavy Rain’s heavily pre-scripted (even if it has branching storylines) narrative with The Sims (Maxis, 2000) and the emergent narrative that arises out of the interactions of its rules, objects, and player decisions. In their most basic dimension, the structures allow different ranges of player freedom while maintaining narrative coherence, and the importance given to one or the other will determine their position on the logos/mythos axis.
It is important to realize that structures of interactive narrative should always be taken as approximate types and general schemata, rather than exact transcriptions of actual game narratives; while many researchers, game designers, and writers may elaborate theoretical story structures out of general principles or typical cases, and even offer some limited examples to demonstrate their models, almost any game examined in its entirety will feature multiple narrative structures over the course of its ergodic traversal (Aarseth, 1997). “Sandbox” games such as Grand Theft Auto III (Rockstar North, 2001) typically combine moments of logocentric design, expressed through their linear story missions, with mythocentric design, present in the free-roaming nature of their game environments in between missions. This relativistic stance is also made necessary by practical realities: the game’s structures can rarely be empirically verified for consistency, as this would require access to production documents, source code analysis, and extensive testing to confirm that no unintended behaviors can emerge out of the game system; moreover, even short and relatively straightforward narratives can seldom be charted out in their entirety without arriving at unusable (and often undecipherable) packs of nodes and links crisscrossing wildly.
The baseline, unmarked structure out of which alternatives can be envisioned is the linear narrative (Phelps, 1996), which progresses from one textual unit to the next with no variation between different experiences. Mary DeMarle (2006) introduces the idea of the gated story (equivalent to Phelps’s interactive structure) to illustrate how some games integrate interactivity into an otherwise linear narrative: the player is free to play around and experience a range of different minor game-events in-between the sequential, important story-events. In practice, very few games can be said to be entirely linear. Even Dragon’s Lair (Advanced Microcomputer Systems, 1983), the quintessential full-motion video game in which the player must perform quick time events (as they would come to be called much later) to simply keep the film rolling, adds challenges randomly from a select pool of possibilities. Any game in which the player can freely explore his/her surroundings is bound to contain some minor events that can take place between story points.
Marie-Laure Ryan’s vector with side branches features a linear “main plot,” out of which the player can venture into a side-quest a couple of nodes deep before returning to the same point in the main quest. Slightly moving away from the logos pole, we find Ryan’s tree structure, in which the player makes decisions at key choice points that spin the narrative in a different direction. By itself, this principle is not sustainable: if the player can make a choice between two possibilities only 8 times through his experience, 256 theoretical possibilities have to be planned for. This is why such narratives will quickly collapse and fold back some of the choices into a common path, a structure christened by Phelps as the braided multi-linear story. In Fahrenheit/Indigo Prophecy (Quantic Dream, 2005), detective Carla must retrieve a tape from the dark and densely-packed archive room, even though she suffers from claustrophobia. The player must control her breathing to keep calm and carry on the task. If the player fails, then the story continues and it is Carla’s partner Tyler who will retrieve the tape instead in the next chapter, so that by that time both possibilities fold back together.
The narrative structures more closely associated with mythocentric design proceed from the figure of the network rather than that of the tree; in a network, the player is free to go back and forth through the game’s topological structure in order to explore previously unexplored nodes and links, as is typically the case in adventure and role-playing games. As can be gleaned from this short sampling of structures, the study of extrinsic narrative is largely associated with game design and criticism.
Intrinsic Narrativity: Actions Speak Louder Than Words
Turning to intrinsic narrativity brings about a change in both scope and focus. Now the idea is not to examine how clearly identified narrative strategies, deployed in some delimitated subset of video games, are used or contribute to the total sum of its parts, but rather to unearth some deep-running connection making narrative an essential part of the gameplay activity. This question ties into the video game’s specificity amongst ludic practices, for how could we consider a form of intrinsic narrativity for video games and not for other traditional, classical games or sports, without positing that they present some unique properties that are more narrative-prone? As such, it has consisted so far, and still remains, at the core of game studies, from Juul’s exposition of a “classic game model” (Juul, 2005), which video games move away from on a number of counts, including a stronger focus on fictional elements, to Jenkins’s resort to “environmental storytelling” (2004) as a way of accounting for the alternative means of providing narrative contents through spatial exploration and enactment of actions during gameplay.
For now, we can only envision a general direction that further research could take. The video game narrative was alluded to by Rune Klevjer when he stated that the actions which players perform when playing games are symbolic, holding meanings preconfigured by another entity (the game’s authorial instance), so that “my own actions speak to me in a voice which is not mine” (Klevjer, 2002). The player-characters we guide through the fictional worlds of video games, and who we routinely identify with to the point of referring to the actions they perform as our actions, never cease to surprise us, whether it is Duke Nukem expressing a sudden burst of machismo or Ezio Auditore using an unexpectedly brutal assassination move against his target. A narratological conception of the video game can be erected if the video game play activity is envisioned as a refinement, through real-time image processing, of the same interactive process that governs the playing of text adventures or interactive fiction, and more largely, of tabletop role-playing games in general. Video game narration occurs when the algorithm, acting as a Game Master in role-playing games, orders the events and relays the effects of actions and current state of the fictional world through visual semiotics. While video games are perfectly capable of upholding extrinsic, embedded narratives by emulating cinematographic or literary techniques, the player’s actions can be intrinsically narrativized by a fictionalizing player, given that they hinge on the same elements that are central to action theory. By situating themselves at the confluence of games and visual media, video games draw on both of these traditions and lend themselves to the discursive organization of elements at which narrative excels.
References
Aarseth, E. (1997). Cybertext: Perspectives on ergodic literature. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Abbott, H. P. [1993] (2002). The Cambridge introduction to narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Arsenault, D. (2008). Narration in the video game: An apologia of interactive storytelling, and an apology to cutscene lovers. Saarbrücken: VDM Verlag.
Arsenault, D., and Perron, B. (2008). In the frame of the magic cycle: The circle(s) of gameplay. In B. Perron & M. J. P. Wolf(Eds.), The video game theory reader 2 (pp. 109–132). New York: Routledge.
Barthes, R. [1966] (L. Duisit, trans. 1975). Introduction to the structural analysis of narrative. New Literary History, 6(2), 237–272.
Caillois, R. ([1958] 1961). Man, play and games. Glencoe, IL: Free Press of Glencoe.
Chandler, R. (2007). Game writing handbook. Boston: Charles River Media.
DeMarle, M. (2006). Nonlinear game narrative. In C. Bateman (Ed.), Game writing: Narrative skills for videogames (pp. 71–84). Boston: Charles River Media.
Eskelinen, M. (2001). The gaming situation. Game Studies, 1(1). Retrieved October 22, 2012, from www.gamestudies.org/0101/eskelinen/.
Frasca, G. (2003). Ludologists love stories, too: Notes from a debate that never took place. Level up (Digital Games Research Association Conference 2003 Proceedings). Retrieved October 22, 2012, from www.ludology.org/articles/frasca_levelUp2003.pdf.
Frasca, G. (1999). Ludology meets narratology: Similitude and differences between (video) games and narrative. Retrieved October 22, 2012, from www.ludology.org/articles/ludology.htm.
Gaudreault, A. (2009). From Plato to Lumière. Narration and monstration in literature and cinema. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Herman, D. (1999). Narratologies: New perspectives on narrative analysis. Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press.
Herman, L., and Vervaeck, B. (2005). Handbook of narrative analysis. Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska Press.
Jenkins, H. (2004). Game design as narrative architecture. In N. Wardrip-Fruin and P. Harrigan (Eds.), First person: New media as story, performance, and game (pp. 118–130). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Juul, J. (2005). Half-real: Video games between real rules and fictional worlds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Klevjer, R. (2002). In defense of cut-scenes. In F. Mäyrä (Ed.), Proceedings of computer games and digital cultures conference (pp. 191–202). Retrieved October 22, 2012, from www.digra.org/digital-library/publications/in-defense-of-cutscenes/.
Murray, J. (1997). Hamlet on the holodeck: The future of narrative in cyberspace. New York: Free Press.
Murray, J. (2005). The last word on ludology v narratology in game studies. Preface to keynote talk at DiGRA 2005, Vancouver, Canada. Retrieved October 22, 2012, from http://lmc.gatech.edu/~murray/digra05/lastword.pdf.
Odin, R. (2000). De la fiction. Bruxelles: De Boeck Université.
Pearce, C. (2004). Towards a game theory of game. In N. Wardrip-Fruin and P. Harrigan (Eds.), First person: new media as story, performance, and game (pp. 143–153). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pearce, C. (2005). Theory wars: An argument against arguments in the so-called ludology/narratology debate. In Changing views: Worlds in play (Digital Games Research Association Conference 2005 Proceedings). Retrieved October 22, 2012, from http://lmc.gatech.edu/~cpearce3/PearcePubs/PearceDiGRA05.pdf.
Phelps, K. (1996). Story shapes for digital media. Retrieved October 22, 2012, from www.glasswings.com.au/modern/shapes/.
Ryan, M.-L. (2001). Narrative as virtual reality: Immersion and interactivity in literature and electronic media. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Ryan, M.-L. (Ed.) (2004). Narrative across media: The languages of storytelling. Lincoln, NB: University of Nebraska Press.
Ryan, M.-L. (2006). Avatars of story. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Samsel, J., and Wimberley, D. (1998). Writing for interactive media: the complete guide. New York: Allworth Press.