4
The Natural Numbers

In this chapter, it shall be shown that number theory can be embedded within set theory. One consequence of this embedding is that all of the theorems in number theory can be proven from the axioms of set theory.

In order to show that number theory is, in fact, a special branch of set theory, we must first represent each natural number as a set. How can one define the natural numbers in set theory? To answer this question, we next consider a set theoretic construction that makes sense for any set.

Definition 4.0.1. For each set , the successor is the set that is obtained by adjoining to the elements of , namely, .

We note the following three properties concerning the successor of a set :

1. .
2. .
3. .

Using the successor operation, we can now construct, in set theory, the first few natural numbers as follows:

We note some interesting properties that these “natural numbers” possess (see the above bulleted list):

1. .
2. .

4.1 Inductive Sets

The existence of an infinite set is crucial in modern set theory and mathematics. Zermelo realized that one cannot prove that an infinite set exists and thus found a fairly simple way to assert the existence of an infinite set.

Infinity Axiom. There is a set that contains the empty set as an element and whenever , then .

Using the infinity axiom, we shall prove that there is a set consisting of only the natural numbers; this set is denoted by . First, we define a property of a set that will ensure that each natural number belongs to such a set. A set that satisfies this property will contain the empty set and will be closed under the successor operation.

Definition 4.1.1. A set is said to be inductive if and only if

1. ,
2. , that is, is “closed under successor.”

An inductive set contains and also contains the successor of each one of its elements. Hence, an inductive set must contain all of the “natural numbers.” Clearly, the infinity axiom declares that there is an inductive set.

Definition 4.1.2. A natural number is a set that belongs, as an element, to every inductive set.

Therefore, is a natural number if and only if is in every inductive set. We now want to prove that there is a set consisting of just the natural numbers. To do this, we need to prove that the class

(4.1)

is a set. By the infinity axiom, we know that there is an inductive set . Hence, for each , if is in every inductive set, then . Theorem 2.1.3 therefore implies that (4.1) defines a set, and this set consists of the natural numbers.

Definition 4.1.3. The set consisting of the natural numbers is denoted by .

Of course, is the set , but we will identify as the set that satisfies

(4.2)

Theorem 4.1.4. The set is inductive and is a subset of every inductive set. Thus, is the smallest inductive set.

Proof. We first prove that is an inductive set; that is, we shall prove that

(1) ,
(2) .

Since is in every inductive set, (4.2) implies that . To prove (2), let . We thus conclude that is in every inductive set. So is also in every inductive set. Hence, and (2) holds. Now let be an inductive set and let . The above (4.2) implies that is in every inductive set. Therefore, and thus, .

We now prove the following simple corollary.

Corollary 4.1.5. Let be an inductive set. Then .

Proof. Let be an inductive set such that . Since is an inductive set, Theorem 4.1.4 implies that . Hence, .

Corollary 4.1.5 is, in fact, a restatement of the principle of mathematical induction. Suppose that is some property. To prove by induction that

is true, let and so, . If we can prove that

(1) ,
(2) ,

then is inductive and thus, by Corollary 4.1.5. Therefore, holds. Item (1) is often called the base step, and (2) is commonly refereed to as the inductive step. We apply this method of proof to establish our next theorem.

Theorem 4.1.6. For every , either or for some .

Proof. Let . Clearly, . Let . So either or for some . Therefore, or where . Thus, . Hence, by Corollary 4.1.5, .

Definition 4.1.7. A set is said to be a transitive set if ; that is, every member of is also a subset of .

Therefore, for any set we have that

Example 1. The empty set is, vacuously, transitive. Each of the following sets is also transitive:

On the other hand, the set is not transitive because and yet . Similarly, the set is not transitive.

Remark 4.1.8. Regrettably, we are now using the word “transitive” to refer to two different concepts. A relation on a set is transitive provided that for all , , in , if and , then (see Definition 3.2.11). A set is transitive, if whenever , then . If a set is transitive, then one cannot infer that the membership relation on is a transitive relation; that is, one cannot always conclude that if and , then , for all , ,  in .

Proposition 4.1.9. Let and be sets. Then .

Theorem 4.1.10. Let be a transitive set. Then .

Proof. Suppose that is a transitive set. Then

Therefore, .

Theorem 4.1.11. Every natural number is a transitive set.

Proof. We prove that by induction. Let

Clearly, , as is a transitive set. Let . So is transitive. To prove that is transitive, we will show that (see 4.4). By Theorem 4.1.10, . Since (see item 3 on page 83), we conclude that . Hence, is a transitive set and thus, . By Corollary 4.1.5, we conclude that , and this completes the proof.

Theorem 4.1.11 implies that if and , then , whenever is a natural number. We now prove that the successor function on is one-to-one.

Theorem 4.1.12. For all and in , if , then .

Proof. Let and . It follows from Theorem 4.1.11 that and are transitive sets. Assume that . Thus, . Therefore, by Theorem 4.1.10.

Theorem 4.1.13. The set is a transitive set.

Proof. We shall prove that by mathematical induction. Let . Clearly, , because and . Let . So (IH)1 . We shall prove that . To do this, let . We must prove that . Since , we conclude that or . If , then by (IH). If , then because . Hence, . Therefore, .

Exercises 4.1

Exercise Notes: For Exercise 7, apply Theorem 4.1.12 for the inductive step. For Exercise 9, let and let . Prove that is inductive. Assume . To prove , let . So or . If , then implies that and thus, . If , then by Exercise 8.

4.2 The Recursion Theorem on

Induction is frequently applied in mathematical proofs. Moreover, one often defines a function by induction (recursion). A recursively defined function is one that is defined in terms of “previously evaluated values of the function.” A function on  is defined recursively if its value at is first specified and all of the remaining values are then defined using an earlier value, together with a given function. For example, let be a function. Suppose that the initial value of a function is given to be for a fixed , and to get the next value we use the initial value to obtain . Similarly, to get the next value we must evaluate . By continuing in this manner, we can evaluate more and more values of the function . A more succinct way of describing this function is to first define (i)  and then define the remaining values by (ii) . Thus, one can evaluate , , …, . Just because we can evaluate a finite number of values, do we really know that there is such a function with domain ? The existence of such a function seems quite reasonable. In mathematics, however, the acceptance of an existential statement requires a valid argument, that is, a proof. The proof of our next theorem shows that such a function does exist and that it is unique.

Recursion Theorem 4.2.1. Let be a set and . Suppose that is a function. Then there exists a unique function such that

The function in the recursion theorem, satisfying (1) and (2), is said to be defined by recursion. If a function has been defined by recursion, then proofs of statements about this function often use “proof by induction.” Before we prove the recursion theorem, we make an observation. First, let us assume that the function exists. When viewing as a set of ordered pairs, conditions (1) and (2) imply that

In our proof, we will show that there exists a function that satisfies the above bulleted conditions.

Proof. Let be a set, , and let be a function. Let us call a relation suitable if the following two conditions hold:

(i) .
(ii) If , then .

Our goal is to construct a suitable relation that is also a function.

Since every suitable relation is a subset of , Theorem 2.1.3 implies that the class is, in fact, a set. Because is a suitable relation, is nonempty. Let . Clearly, , and so is a relation. We now prove that is suitable and that it is a function.

Claim 1. is suitable.

Proof. We need to show that satisfies items (i) and (ii). Every relation in is suitable. So is an element in every relation in . Thus, ; that is, . To prove (ii), assume that . As , it follows that belongs to every relation in . Let . Since and is suitable, item (ii) implies that . So belongs to every relation in , and hence, . Thus, is suitable. (Claim 1)  

We now must prove that is a function from to .

Claim 2. is a function from to .

Proof. To prove that is a function from to , we must show that for each , there is exactly one such that . Let be defined by

We now prove that is an inductive set. To do this, we must first prove that . We know that . To prove that , we need to show there is no where . Suppose, for a contradiction, that where . Consider the relation

Clearly, () . As is suitable, it easily follows that is also suitable (because for all ). Hence, . Since , we conclude that , and thus, , which contradicts (). Consequently, is the only element in such that . Therefore, .

Let ; that is, assume that (IH) there is a unique such that . Because is suitable, we conclude that . To show that , we must show there is no where . Assume, for a contradiction, that where . Consider the relation

Clearly, () . We now show that is suitable. Since is suitable and , we have only to show that if , then . To do this, assume that . Thus, , and so . Since , , and , we conclude from (IH) that , and thus, . Because and , we infer that . So is suitable. Hence, . Since , we conclude that , and thus, , which contradicts (). Therefore, is the only element in such that . So , and thus, is inductive. Corollary 4.1.5 implies that , and as a result, is a function from to . (Claim 2)  

Because the function is suitable, it satisfies conditions (1) and (2) given in the statement of the theorem. To prove that is unique, suppose that also satisfies properties (1) and (2). Thus, is a suitable relation, and hence, . Since , we have that . Exercise 10 on page 68 implies that . Therefore, is unique.      (Theorem)

Example 1. Let and let . Theorem 4.2.1 implies that there is a function such that and , for all .

When can we be assured that the function in Theorem 4.2.1 is one-to-one? Our next theorem provides an answer.

Theorem 4.2.2. Let be a set, , , and be a function. Suppose that satisfies

If is one-to-one, then is also one-to-one.

Proof. Let be one-to-one, , , and let satisfy (1) and (2). We prove that for all and all , if , then . Let be defined by

We shall show that is an inductive set. To prove that , we must show that

(4.5)

So let and assume that . By (1), we have . Hence, . Suppose that . Then for some by Theorem 4.1.6. Since , we conclude that . The above item (2) now implies that . Thus, , which contradicts the fact that . Hence, . Therefore, (4.5) holds, and so .

Let . In other words, assume the induction hypothesis

We shall prove that ; that is, we will prove that

Let and suppose that () . Because , the above (4.5) and () imply that . So for some . Hence, . Item (2) implies that . Since is one-to-one, we conclude that . Our induction hypothesis (IH) implies that , and thus, ; that is, . Hence, , and so is an inductive set. Therefore, and is a one-to-one function.

4.2.1 The Peano Postulates2

The Peano postulates offer an axiomatic foundation for the natural numbers. These postulates were first presented by the nineteenth-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed a set of axioms about the natural numbers. Peano then published a more precisely formulated version of these axioms in his 1889 book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method [13]. The essence of the Peano postulates shall be summarized by means of the following two definitions.

Definition 4.2.3. Let and let . Then is said to be closed under if for all , if , then .

Let denote an ordered triple, that is, .

Definition 4.2.4. Let be an ordered triple that consists of a set , a function , and a particular element . Then is a Peano system if the following three conditions hold:
(1) .
(2) is one-to-one.
(3) For all , if and is closed under , then .

The above condition (3) is referred to as the induction postulate. Figure 4.1 illustrates a Peano system.


Figure 4.1. A Peano system

Theorem 4.1.4 shows that is inductive. Thus, we can define the function by for all . We can now prove that a Peano system exists.

Theorem 4.2.5. The triple is a Peano system.

Proof. Since is inductive, we have that and that for all . Clearly, for all , as and . Thus, . Theorem 4.1.12 shows that is one-to-one. Finally, we need to show that satisfies the induction postulate. Let be such that and is closed under . So is inductive. Corollary 4.1.5 implies that . Therefore, is a Peano system because it satisfies conditions (1)–(3) of Definition 4.2.4.

Definition 4.2.6. Let and be Peano systems. Then is isomorphic to when there is a bijection such that

(1) , and
(2) for all .

The function is said to be an isomorphism from onto .

Two Peano systems are isomorphic if they are essentially the same structure. We now prove that is isomorphic to any Peano system. Thus, the set of natural numbers is “the same” as the set that is used in calculus.

Theorem 4.2.7. Let be a Peano system. Then is isomorphic to .

Proof. Let be a Peano system. So is one-to-one, , and . Since , Theorem 4.2.1 implies that there is a function such that

(1) ,
(2) , for all .

As and is one-to-one, Theorem 4.2.2 implies that is one-to-one. To show that is onto , we use the induction postulate (Definition 4.2.4(3)). Clearly, . Since , we see that . Let . Thus, for some . Hence, . By (2), we conclude that . So , and is thereby closed under . The induction postulate implies that , that is, is onto . Therefore, is an isomorphism from onto .

Theorem 4.2.7 implies that the Peano postulates characterize the system of natural numbers (up to isomorphism). Theorem 4.2.7 also implies that any two Peano systems are isomorphic to each other (see Exercises 78).

Exercises 4.2

Exercise Notes: Exercises 45 do not involve Theorem 4.2.1, but they do apply some of the ideas in its proof. For Exercise 4(e) and for Exercise 5(e), in the direction (), prove that . For Exercise 6, item (a) implies (c); to prove (d), use (b) and (c) together with the results of Exercise 5(c)(d) to show that and .

4.3 Arithmetic on

In this section, the recursion theorem will be used to define the operations of addition, multiplication, and exponentiation on the natural numbers. We will also prove the properties of arithmetic that we were taught as children. We first establish the following result.

Theorem 4.3.1. Let and be functions. Then there is a unique function such that for each ,

Proof. For each , by the recursion theorem (viewing as a constant), there is a unique function such that

(a) ,
(b) , for all .

Since is unique for each , the connection thus produces a function with domain . We can now define the function by . The function easily satisfies conditions (1) and (2) for all , and it is unique.

The function in Theorem 4.3.1 is defined in terms of two known functions. Thus, before one can apply Theorem 4.3.1, one must first introduce the two relevant functions and .

Recalling Definition 3.5.3, a function of the form is called a binary operation on . Our next definition is an application of Theorem 4.3.1; that is, using the functions and , we define addition on the natural numbers.

Definition 4.3.2. Let be the unique function satisfying
(1) ,
(2)

for all natural numbers and . The function shall be referred to as addition, and we define the binary operation on to be

for all and in .

Theorem 4.3.3. For all natural numbers and ,

Proof. Let and be elements in . Recalling that , we see that (1) and (2) in Definition 4.3.2 immediately produce (A1) and (A2).

The next proposition shows that is equal to , the successor of . After we prove this proposition, we will show that .

Proposition 4.3.4. For all , .

Proof. Let . Since , we obtain

and thus, .

We can now prove that as follows:

Now that we have the operation of addition, we can apply Theorem 4.3.1 to define multiplication on the natural numbers using the functions and .

Definition 4.3.5. Let be the unique function satisfying
(1) ,
(2)

for all natural numbers and . The function is called multiplication, and we define the binary operation on to be

for all and in .

Theorem 4.3.6. For all natural numbers and ,

Proof. Let and be elements in . Recalling that , we see that (1) and (2) in Definition 4.3.5 yields (M1) and (M2).

Having presented the set-theoretic definitions of addition and multiplication, we will now show that some of the familiar laws of arithmetic are provable within set theory. Afterwards, we shall define exponentiation.

Theorem 4.3.7 (Associative Law for Addition). For all , , and in ,

Proof. Let and be elements in , and let

We shall show that is an inductive set. To show that , observe that

and thus, , and so . Assume that . Then

Therefore, , and hence, .

For , we know that by (A1). Since we have not proven that addition is commutative, we cannot immediately infer that , and thus, we must prove that this latter equation holds for all .

Lemma 4.3.8. For all , we have .

Proof. We prove that by induction. Let

We prove that is inductive. Since (A1) implies that , we have that . Let . So . We prove that as follows:

Therefore, , and this completes the proof.

Item (A2) states that for natural numbers and . We will now prove that we also have that . Then we will be able to prove that addition is commutative.

Lemma 4.3.9. For all and , we have .

Proof. Let be arbitrary. We prove that by induction. Let

To prove the lemma, we just need to show that is inductive. First, we verify that by showing that as follows:

Thus, . Suppose that . Then

and hence, . Therefore, and is inductive.

Lemmas 4.3.8 and 4.3.9 will be used to prove that addition is commutative.

Theorem 4.3.10 (Commutative Law for Addition). For all and in ,

Proof. Let be any element in and let

We prove that is an inductive set. Observe that by Lemma 4.3.8 and (A1). So . Assume that . Then

Hence, , and therefore, .

Using proof by induction, we will now show that the familiar distributive law of arithmetic holds. We will thus have additional evidence to support the assertion “Mathematics can be embedded in set theory.”

Theorem 4.3.11 (Distributive Law). For all natural numbers , , and ,

Proof. Let and be in . Now let

We will show that is an inductive set. To verify that , we have

Thus, , and so . Now, suppose that . Then

Hence, , and thus, .

Our next two theorems verify two fundamental properties of multiplication.

Theorem 4.3.12 (Associative Law for Multiplication). For all , , and in ,

Proof. Let and be elements in and let

We shall show that is an inductive set. To show that , observe that

and thus, , and so . Assume that . Then

Therefore, , and hence, .

Theorem 4.3.13 (Commutative Law for Multiplication). For all and in ,

Proof. See Exercise 6.

We will now apply Theorem 4.3.1 to define exponentiation on the natural numbers, using the functions and .

Definition 4.3.14. Let be the unique function satisfying

(1) ,
(2)

for all natural numbers and . The function is called exponentiation. We define the binary operation, denoted by , to be

for all and in .

Theorem 4.3.15. For all natural numbers and ,

Exercises 4.3

Exercise Notes: For Exercise 1, suppose and then use Theorem 4.1.6. For Exercise 2, assume that and use Exercise 1 to prove that . For Exercise 3, Theorem 4.1.12 can be used in the inductive step.

4.4 Order on

We now want to develop a theory of order on the natural numbers. First, we define the “less than” relation on the natural numbers. Then we prove that this relation satisfies the trichotomy law (see Theorem 4.4.9) as well as the standard connections with addition and multiplication. How can we get such a relation in set theory?

Recall that for each , we defined the successor of to be the natural number , and thus, . As a result, we have the following infinite membership list:

which is very much like the usual relation on the natural numbers; that is,

It turns out that the order relation that we need is just “,” and, in fact, we will prove that this is the “less than” relation that we were looking for.

Definition 4.4.1. We say that is less than if and only if , whenever and are in .

In this section, we will view “” as the “less than” relation on the natural numbers, and we shall no longer use the symbol in our initial discussion of ordering on . We will show that the relation on satisfies the trichotomy law, and we will show that is preserved under the operations of addition and nonzero multiplication.

Theorem 4.1.11 and Theorem 4.1.13 assert, respectively, that each natural number is a transitive set and that is a transitive set. Hence, we have the following result.

Proposition 4.4.2. Let be a natural number. Then

Item (2) proclaims that is a transitive relation on . One can also prove, without using the regularity axiom, that no natural number is “less than” itself.

Lemma 4.4.3. Let . Then .

Proof. See Exercise 10 on page 88.

Using Definition 4.4.1, we can now easily define the “less than or equal” relation on the natural numbers.

Definition 4.4.4. We write if and only if or , whenever and are in .

Since is a transitive relation on , it thus follows that is also a transitive relation on . Clearly, is reflexive. We will now show that it is antisymmetric (see Definition 3.4.1).

Lemma 4.4.5. Let and . If and , then .

Proof. Let and satisfy and . Thus, and by Proposition 4.4.2(1). Therefore, .

Hence, is a partial order on . Is the relation a total order on ? To show that it is, we shall prove that the relation satisfies the trichotomy law on . First, we establish two lemmas.

Lemma 4.4.6. For all , we have that .

Proof. We shall prove that the set

is inductive. Clearly, . Assume . Hence, . So either or . If , then, as , we see that . If , then we have and . By transitivity (see Proposition 4.4.2(2)), we conclude that . Thus, in either case, and so, . Therefore, is inductive and .

Lemma 4.4.7. For all natural numbers and , if , then .

Proof. Let . We prove that by induction. Let

Clearly, as is true vacuously. Let . To prove that , assume that . We shall show that . Observe that () . Because , either or . If , then as . Since , we see that () and transitivity imply that . If , then . Thus, () implies that . Therefore, .

Corollary 4.4.8. If and are in , then if and only if .

Proof. Assume that and . By Lemma 4.4.7, we just need to prove if , then . So let . Recall that () . Since , we have either or . If , then by () and transitivity. Also, if , then () implies that .

The following theorem shows that is a total order on ; that is, for all and in , either or .

Theorem 4.4.9 (Trichotomy Law on ). For all and in , exactly one of the three relationships holds.

Proof. First, we show that any two of the relations , , cannot hold at the same time, whenever and are natural numbers. To do this, we just have to show that the following two conjunctions do not hold:

when and . Conjunction (a) implies that , which contradicts Lemma 4.4.3. Conjunction (b), by transitivity, also implies that . Hence, both (a) and (b) do not hold.

We now prove that . To prove this statement, let and let

We will show that is inductive. Lemma 4.4.6 implies that . Let , that is, assume that

We must show that

(4.6)

To do this, we consider each of the three cases in (IH) separately. If , then by the fact that and transitivity. If , then since . If , then Lemma 4.4.7 implies that . Thus, either or . So in each of these three cases in (IH), we obtain one of the conjuncts in (4.6). Therefore, , and the proof is complete.

The trichotomy law will now allow us to do the following:

(1) identify an interesting connection between the relations and on the natural numbers;
(2) prove that addition and multiplication on the natural numbers preserve the “less than” relation;
(3) prove that , the set of natural numbers, satisfies the crucial well-ordering principle.

Corollary 4.4.10. If and are in , then if and only if .

Proof. Let and . Assume that . Because is transitive, we have that . Since , Theorem 4.4.9 implies that . So . To prove the converse, assume . Thus, . From Theorem 4.4.9, we have either or . If , then we would have that , as . This contradicts Theorem 4.4.3. Thus, .

Corollary 4.4.10 implies that for all natural numbers and ,

When and are natural numbers, we can now define , which is the larger of the two natural numbers and (see Exercise 5).

Our next theorem shows that the expected properties of “inequality” hold for the natural numbers.

Theorem 4.4.11 (Properties of Inequality). For all natural numbers , , and , the following hold:

Proof. Item (1) follows from Exercises 6 and 7 of this section. Similarly, (2) is established via Exercises 8 and 9.

Corollary 4.4.12 (Cancellation Laws). For all natural numbers , , and , the following hold:

Proof. See Exercise 10.

Corollary 4.1.5 (page 85) confirms the fact that the principle of mathematical induction is provable from the first seven axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. Virtually every undergraduate text in mathematics (e.g., number theory, real analysis, and abstract algebra) just cites this principle and does not attempt to prove it directly. Our next theorem shows that these seven axioms also imply the well-ordering principle: Every nonempty subset of has a least element.

Theorem 4.4.13 (Well-Ordering Principle). Let be a nonempty subset of . Then has a least element; that is, there is an such that for all .

Proof. Let be a nonempty subset of . Suppose, for a contradiction, that has no least element. Let . So is the set of that are less than or equal to every element in . Note that () because if , then and would be a least element in .

We will now show that is inductive. Clearly, , by Lemma 4.4.6. Let ; that is, suppose that for all . Since has no least element, it follows that . Therefore, for all . Hence, for all by Exercise 3. So and is inductive. Thus, and () now implies that . Nevertheless, because and is nonempty, we also conclude that . This contradiction completes the proof.

We end this section with a proof of the strong induction principle on .

Theorem 4.4.14 (Strong Induction Principle on ). Let be a subset of and suppose that

(4.7)

Then .

Proof. Let satisfy (4.7). Suppose, to the contrary, that there is a natural number that is not in . Thus, the set is nonempty. Theorem 4.4.13 now implies that has a least element . Hence, and if , then . Therefore, . As satisfies (4.7), we infer that , a contradiction.

We can now define a special relation symbol with which we are all familiar. Let and be in . We define if and only if , and define if and only if . So in the future there may times when we shall use the symbols and , rather than and , if it seems appropriate.

Remark 4.4.15. Using the system of natural numbers , one can give set-theoretic constructions of the set of integers, the set of rational numbers, and then the set of real numbers. A method for constructing the set of integers is suggested in Exercise 9 on page 82. In [5], Enderton gives a more detailed description of this method and constructs the set of rational numbers and the set of real numbers.

Exercises 4.4

10. Use Theorem 4.4.11 and Theorem 4.4.9 to prove Corollary 4.4.12.
20. Let be in with . Assume that where , and where . Prove that and . To prove that , suppose to the contrary that (without loss of generality). By Exercise 12, there is a so that . Complete the following:
(a) Show that .
(b) Show that and . Then show that , which is a contradiction. Conclude that .
(c) Now show that .

Exercise Notes: For Exercise 3, apply Theorem 4.4.9. For Exercise 4, apply Exercise 3. For Exercise 6, use induction. For Exercise 7, apply Exercise 6 and Theorem 4.4.9. For Exercise 8, use induction. For Exercise 9, use Exercise 8 and Theorem 4.4.9. For Exercise 13, use Exercises 1112. For Exercise 14, let and prove that is inductive. For Exercise 15, one can apply Theorem 4.4.13 and proof by contradiction: Assume that there is such function . Let . Let be the least element in . Thus, for a . For Exercise 16, use the well-ordering principle and Exercise 2. For Exercise 17, use induction and review 3.3.8(3) on page 60. For Exercise 18, prove that

is an inductive set. For Exercise 19, in the inductive step one can use Exercise 3. Exercises 1920 yield a proof the Division Algorithm: Let and be natural numbers, where . Then there exist unique natural numbers and such that and .