Chapter 9

Toward a Psychology for the 21st Century

Edward F. Kelly

The problem of Myers still awaits us as the problem of far the deepest moment for our actual psychology, whether his own tentative solutions of certain parts of it be correct or not. (James, 1901, p. 18)

The rejection of any source of evidence is always treason to that ultimate rationalism which urges forward science and philosophy alike. (Whitehead, 1929/1958, p. 61)

The truest success of this book will lie in its rapid supersession by a better. (Myers, HP, vol. 1, p. 9)

We come now to the hardest task of all, that of weaving together the various threads of this book into an overall reassessment of Myers’s work and its implications for the future of scientific psychology. I will begin with what some major contemporaries had to say.

Contemporary Reviews of Human Personality

There were many early reviews of HP, ranging in tone from scornful derision to unalloyed praise (see Gauld, 1968, chap. 12), but the most useful for our purposes are those of Stout (1903), McDougall (1903), and James (1903), each of which offers serious criticism in combination with actual knowledge of the contents of the book. All are included on our digital version of HP.

The assessment by Stout, a distinguished British psychologist of that period, is wholly negative and proceeds along lines that many present-day mainstream reviewers would undoubtedly be inclined to follow. Precisely for these reasons, it is worth examining here in some detail. It will become evident that the fundamental issue at stake is that of unconscious cerebration (Stout) versus subliminal or transmarginal consciousness (Myers), as discussed in Chapters 2 and 5. Unconscious cerebration, in today’s terminology, comprises all the sorts of things a “cognitive unconscious” might accomplish by means of automatic brain activity.

Stout (1903) begins by describing what he regards as the principal novelty otHP:

The theory represented by Mr. Myers diverges in a startling way from all the various forms of the doctrine of subconscious or unconscious mental states and processes which have ever been current among psychologists. The theory has at least as much affinity with such conceptions as that of a tutelary genius or a guardian angel. The Subliminal Self is not to be identified with any organized system of mental traces or dispositions formed in the course of the conscious experience of the ordinary self…. The Subliminal Self is rather to be conceived as a primary and independent stream of personal consciousness having its own separate system of mental traces and dispositions formed in the course of its own separate experience, (pp. 45–46)

Despite Stout’s attempts to justify this description using quotes from HP, it is a caricature of Myers’s actual views. Myers does hold that some contents of the subliminal region do not derive from the conscious experience of the ordinary self, but he certainly does not hold that all of its contents are of this sort. Indeed, as shown in Chapters 2 and 5, Myers admits all the conventionally recognized forms of transmarginal content, including everything from momentarily forgotten or incompletely processed material to Janet’s well-characterized clinical cases of dissociated consciousness, and seeks only to extend these existing conceptions in order to embrace a still wider range of documented empirical phenomena. One of the strengths of his theory, in fact, is that it identifies previously unrecognized relationships and continuities underlying an enormous range and variety of phenomena, both normal and supernormal.

Stout next deploys his own caricature of Myers’s conception in an attempt to turn the generality itself into an argument against him. Specifically, the central strategy of Stout’s critique is to argue that the Subliminal Self as he has described it must provide at least part of the explanation of all “normal” phenomena, as well as any supernormal ones, and hence that if any normal phenomenon can be explained without recourse to it, Myers’s general theory is false. He then proceeds to describe how unconscious cerebration alone might explain recollection of momentarily forgotten names, problem-solving, alternate personalities, sleep and dreams, hypnosis, and other generally accepted phenomena discussed by Myers.

Two principal features of Stout’s “explanations,” however, merit special emphasis—first, his heavy reliance on promissory materialism in regard to accepted or “normal” phenomena, and second, his systematic unwillingness to take seriously Myers’s heavy documentation of supernormal phenomena. Both tendencies are fully evident in regard to hypnosis, for example:

Setting aside alleged cases of telepathy, clairvoyance, etc., hypnosis presents no phenomena so extraordinary as to justify our regarding them as beyond the reach of explanation in accordance with the ordinary methods and principles of physiology and psychology. The way is dark, but it is not blocked by unsurmountable barriers. We need not have recourse to a flying-machine, (p. 57)

I cannot resist noting here the irony that Stout’s dismissive final sentence was penned in the same year in which the Wright brothers made their first successful flight at Kitty Hawk. More to the point scientifically, however, are the many parts of our Chapter 3 that undermine his unquestioning faith in the reach of conventional forms of explanation, even in regard to the psychophysiological aspects of hypnotism. Similar comments apply to the other “normal” phenomena he discusses.

Finally, having resorted repeatedly to his “setting aside” approach to Myers’s documentation of psi-type phenomena occurring in conjunction with hypnosis, dreams, and so on, and mistakenly believing himself already to have successfully disproven Myers’s general theory of the Subliminal Self, Stout turns to a brief statement (pp. 62–64) of his own “personal attitude” toward psi phenomena generally. He acknowledges “that after all criticisms are allowed for, the evidence is still decidedly impressive, and that it is sufficient to constitute a good case for further investigation,” but he is not persuaded by it. Most of the “reasons” he offers in defense of this attitude, however, amount to generic suspicions, devoid of reference to specific experiments or cases, about possible failures of memory, conscious or unconscious cheating, and the like, issues that had long since been identified and controlled in ongoing investigations by Myers and his SPR colleagues. The one specific opinion he advances is that a proposed skeptical explanation of ostensible evidence for telepathy in terms of “unconscious whispering” is “peculiarly probable.” What Stout neglects to mention here, however, is that this hypothesis—also eagerly embraced by the even more skeptical American psychologist Titchener in the pages of Science—had been thoroughly discredited in papers already published by William James and Henry Sidgwick (see Burkhardt, 1986, chap. 22; E. Taylor, 1996, pp. 108–111). In short, like many present-day scientists Stout is simply unable to come fully to grips with the relevant evidence and chooses instead to ignore it.

McDougall and James, unlike Stout, accept the reality of psi phenomena and find much to admire in the character and content of Myers’s book, but they too have problems with his general theory. McDougall’s complaints run partly parallel to Stout’s and rest on the same primary misapprehensions, in particular that Myers fails to recognize routine contributions of unconscious cerebration to everyday mental life, and that he holds a rigidly duplex theory in regard to the supraliminal and subliminal streams of consciousness.1 Two additional factors also seem to drive his somewhat convoluted and turgid critique: First, he is already beginning to develop his own very different “monadic” theory (discussed in Chapter 5), according to which the everyday consciousness or self is the real self, and the apex of personality. This leads him to be hostile to Myers’s conception of psychological automatisms as expressions of a larger and in some ways superior transmarginal consciousness. Secondly, he thinks that Myers has failed to appreciate his true “main difficulty” (p. 526), the fact that post-mortem survival seems to be precluded by the normal dependence of mind and consciousness on an intact brain. Although McDougall’s language here is carefully guarded, he appears at this time to hold something close to a standard production model of mind-brain relations.

Two crucial points should be noted, however. First, McDougall himself soon moved beyond the production model, driven in part by the findings of psychical research and also by his own ruminations on other topics, such as memory, meaning, and the unity of consciousness, discussed in the present volume. His book Body and Mind (1911/1974) is in fact subtitled “A History and a Defense of Animism,” where by animism he means the following:

The essential notion, which forms the common foundation of all varieties of Animism, is that all, or some, of those manifestations of life and mind which distinguish the living man from the corpse and from inorganic bodies are due to the operation within him of something which is of a nature different from that of the body, an animating principle generally, but not necessarily or always, conceived as an immaterial and individual being or soul. (p. xx)

McDougall ultimately arrived at a variety of animism, his “psychophysical dualism,” which embraces the notion of a psyche or soul without presuming it to be ontologically distinct from the body or capable of surviving bodily death. Indeed, McDougall himself was not convinced of survival. The principal obstacle remained for him the same “main difficulty” he had identified in his review of HP, a difficulty which he found the survival evidence then available insufficient—though just barely—to overcome: “Again and again the evidential character of the observations has fallen just short of perfection; the objections that stand between us and the acceptance of the conclusion seem to tremble and sway, but still they are not cast down” (McDougall, 1911/1974, p. 347).

Here, however, the second point comes into play. McDougall seems never to have taken fully on board the significance of James’s (1898/1900) discussion of transmission theory (see our Chapter 1). It is not even mentioned in his review of HP as a possible way around the difficulty, and one, moreover, that is compatible with Myers’s theory. In addition, when McDougall later does come to discuss it, in the last chapter of Body and Mind, he grossly misrepresents James’s actual views, as I will demonstrate later.

Meanwhile, let us turn even more briefly to the appraisal of Myers’s work by William James. The two main sources for this are his 1901 memorial address and his 1903 review of HP (both on our digital version of HP). Both pieces are vintage James, marvels of incisiveness, clarity, warmth, and felicity of expression, and I beg all readers—especially my fellow psychologists—to study them with care in conjunction with this chapter. James was more intimately acquainted with Myers and his work than either Stout or McDougall, understood the theory better, and appreciated it far more:

It is a vast synthesis, but a coherent one, notwithstanding the vagueness of some of the terms that figure in it. No one of the dots by which his map is plotted out, no one of the “corners” required by his triangulation, is purely hypothetical. He offers empirical evidence for the concrete existence of every element which his scheme postulates and works with. In logical form the theory is thus a scientific construction of a very high order. (James, 1903, p. 30)

As to the truth of Myers’s theory, however, as distinct from its formal merits, James withholds final judgment, for three primary reasons: First, he thinks some of the “corners” or “stepping-stones” may themselves be too frail, or insufficiently well documented. Second, he wonders whether Myers perhaps generalized too hastily from conditions that in fact have been adequately documented only in a few special situations, such as deep hypnosis and multiple personality disorder, involving small numbers of highly unusual persons. Third, and for James the most troubling, is Myers’s inability to explain to his satisfaction how the subliminal region can serve equally as “rubbish-heap” and “treasure-house” (HP, vol. 1, p. 72), “so impartially the home of both evolutive and of dissolutive phenomena” (James, 1903, p. 32). All of these concerns are legitimate and remain relevant today, and I shall attempt to deal with them in the course of what now follows.

A Re-assessment of Myers’s Theory of Personality

Principles which I have tried to follow in constructing this assessment, and which I must ask readers to follow as well, include in particular the following four: First, many contemporary readers, and especially scientific readers, are likely to find certain aspects of Myers’s writing at times jarring or even distasteful. His sentences are often long and complex, his prose sometimes startlingly ornate and lyrical, and the text loaded with quotations from multiple foreign languages including in particular Greek and Latin.2 All of this can make for hard going, but it involves only superficial stylistic matters characteristic of Myers and his time. The effort necessary to penetrate his meanings is almost always worthwhile, in my opinion, and it must be made in order to appreciate in full the richness and beauty of his theory. Related to this, what we must attempt now to appraise is the theory that Myers actually held, and not the sorts of caricatures of it served up by critics such as Stout and McDougall, and by Freud’s biographer and disciple Ernest Jones (1918, p. 122) in service of their own very different theoretical outlooks. Third, we must respond to the whole theory and take all the associated data into account, not artificially restricting our attention, as did Stout, to those elements of Myers’s vision with which we happen to be comfortable at the moment. Finally, and most importantly, we must try to take into account all of the additional relevant evidence that has come forward in the intervening century, most of which has been summarized, or at least pointed to, in the present volume.

Our assessment will proceed at three general levels: (1) Myers’s methodological principles and commitments; (2) his natural history of the mind; and (3) the theoretical structure which he elaborated in order to account for his data. The first two of these sections can be relatively short and should, I think, be uncontroversial.

Myers’s Methodological Principles

Myers was reared chiefly on literature and history, with primary interests in poetry and religion, but that he successfully transformed himself into a serious scientist can scarcely be doubted by anyone who takes the trouble to study his contributions to psychology. As described in Chapter 2, he was deeply committed to the ultimate lawfulness of nature, and to the use of empirical methods in ferreting out its secrets. Where he differs from most contemporary scientists is in refusing to rest content with scientific theories, facts, or methods in their existing state of development. No topic is to be banned a priori as beyond the reach of science. Indeed, Myers’s central impulse and long-term goal is to overcome the historical opposition between science and religion by means of an expanded and enlightened science capable of penetrating into the psychological territory previously occupied by the historical religions alone, with their mutually inconsistent teachings and decidedly mixed impacts on human welfare. He aspires ultimately to re-ground this entire domain of vital human experience in real scientific knowledge rather than faith and dogma; see, for example, his “Provisional Sketch of a Religious Synthesis” in HP (vol. 2, pp. 284–292). In pursuit of this and all the related goals of psychical research, what seems to him most needed is not unthinking mechanical application of any existing method to every new problem, but constant effort to adapt our research methods creatively to all new situations as they arise, and as we find them.

Myers would therefore certainly have lamented—correctly, I believe—the subsequent withering of psychical research, and of psychology more generally, into disciplines preoccupied to the extent they presently are with laboratory-based experimental investigations as the only road to knowledge.3 This is not because he doubted the value of experimentation, when appropriate, but because he also appreciated the value of other kinds of empirical research such as detailed individual case studies and field investigations. Both HP itself and the present volume illustrate, I believe, the power of the broader concept of empiricism advocated by Myers and James for psychology as a whole.

It also merits emphasis here that there are many scientific options in the region between one-shot case studies and full-fledged factorial experimental designs. Methodologists D. T. Campbell and Stanley (1966), for example, identified numerous useful though less rigorous experimental designs that are still capable of producing reliable and valid scientific knowledge, and they explicitly stated that the goal of their efforts was to “encourage an open-minded and exploratory orientation to novel data-collection arrangements and a new scrutiny of some of the weaknesses that accompany routine utilizations of the traditional ones” (p. 61). From the opposite direction, cases initially studied and reported in detail individually, such as apparition cases, NDEs, and cases of the reincarnation type, can also be encoded according to appropriate descriptive schemes and entered into cumulative databases which, when they become sufficiently large, afford important new opportunities for quantitative study of internal patterns, predictive relationships, and so on, governing the relevant domains.4

A broadened empiricism has similarly been advocated for psychology as a whole by Toulmin and Leary (1985):

It is not only thinking that suffered because of American psychology’s cult of empiricism…. Empiricism itself suffered because of the rigid, experimental fetters that were placed upon it. Surely there should be room too for a retreat, at least by some, from experimental empiricism. All science, and probably all speculation, originates at a more basic level of empiricism: the level of experience. In a discipline that is often confused about its subject matter, it is not a bad idea to return to basic experience from time to time. The natural taxonomy that arises therefrom is much more likely to provide a useful framework for experimental work than the artificial taxonomies that structure so much of the field today, (p. 612)5

Myers’s Natural History of the Mind

This leads immediately, of course, to Myers’s own “taxonomy,” and on this subject all serious students agree. His natural history of the mind, quite apart from the theoretical constructions he based upon it, has been hailed by many as a scientific achievement of great value in itself. Let James again speak here for all: In his 1901 memorial address he describes Myers as “the pioneer who staked out a vast tract of mental wilderness and planted the flag of genuine science upon it” (p. 23), largely through exercise of the kind of taxonomic genius described in our Chapter 2. In his later review of HP, James (1903) was if anything even more explicit:

Reading him afresh in these two volumes, I find myself filled with an admiration which almost surprises me. The work, whatever weaknesses it may have, strikes me as at least a masterpiece of co-ordination and unification. The voluminous arsenal of “cases” of which the author’s memory disposes might make the most erudite naturalist or historian envy him, and his delicate power of serially assorting his facts, so as to find always just the case he needs to fit into a gap in the scheme, is wholly admirable. He shows indeed a genius not unlike that of Charles Darwin for discovering shadings and transitions, and grading down discontinuities in his argument, (p. 30)

One of the “weaknesses” James had in mind, as indicated above, was the possible frailty of some individual elements of Myers’s taxonomy. James unfortunately does not identify which particular elements he had in mind, but in any event it seems to me undeniable that this “natural history” aspect of Myers’s work has only been further strengthened by the large amounts of additional evidence generated during the subsequent century and summarized in the present volume. We now have far more detailed evidence, for example, regarding the existence of psi phenomena in general and their association with altered states of consciousness such as dreams and hypnosis (see Appendix), supernormal control of bodily processes (Chapter 3), problems in regard to conventional trace theories of memory (Chapter 4), psychological automatisms including the full-blown dissociative phenomena of automatic writing, hypnosis, and MPD/DID (Chapter 5), NDEs and OBEs occurring under extreme physiological conditions (Chapter 6), genius (Chapter 7), and mystical and psychedelic experiences (Chapter 8), all of which maps smoothly onto—and hence reinforces—Myers’s basic descriptive framework. I should also reiterate here that Myers not only provided a useful taxonomy of subliminal contents and processes but also strove to develop or improve various means of putting these “on tap” for more efficient experimental investigation (Chapter 2). It seems to me a virtual certainty that we have barely scratched the surface in terms of exploiting these techniques—such as hypnosis, automatic writing, and crystal-gazing or “scrying”—in the manner Myers envisaged (E. F. Kelly & Locke, 1981a).

I turn now to the third level of our reassessment, a far more difficult subject.

Myers’s General Theory of the Psyche: The Subliminal Self

Chapter 2 has set forth what we believe to be the correct understanding of what Myers (1885c) really meant by his “Subliminal Self” (uppercase)—briefly, the totality of the psyche, soul, or Individuality, comprising both supraliminal and subliminal elements, regions, or functional systems. The supraliminal or everyday self constitutes only a small portion of the psyche, formed out of some few of its “elements” (p. 387) in response to the demands of the environment. One or more “subliminal selves” (lower-case) may also occasionally emerge in a similar way under certain unusual conditions. But the Subliminal Self—the underlying, comprehensive Self—is the centerpiece of Myers’s theoretical construct, for it is at this level that he seeks to reconcile the “colonial” (Ribot) versus “unitary” (Reid) accounts of human personality in favor of a more profound unity.6

As noted in Chapter 2, there has been much confusion about this conception in the literature, and it cannot be denied that Myers himself was to a considerable extent responsible for it. His terminology is unfortunate and confusing, and even Myers himself did not use it altogether consistently. It seems likely, though we cannot be sure, that he was still ironing out details of the exposition at the time of his death. This might have helped clarify things, but it is certain in any event that the conception is not only inherently difficult, but also highly counter-intuitive for many commentators—myself included. Nevertheless, I have come to think that it is more or less correct, for reasons I will next try to explain.

The starting point for Myers’s scheme, his “measured base,” consists of various forms of evidence for the existence of dissociated streams of consciousness existing outside the awareness of the ordinary self, rising in complexity and coherence in some cases to the level of true secondary personalities or “subliminal selves.” As shown in Chapters 2 and 5, James and many others found the evidence Myers marshaled for this purpose already cogent, and much additional evidence of related types has subsequently come to light that is further supportive of his interpretations. Chapter 5, for example, provides what to me is a convincing demonstration that there have been cases of multiple personality which cannot be satisfactorily interpreted in terms of “periodic sharp alterations in a single stream of consciousness” (Gauld, 1968, p. 279). In this light it is rather sad to find unconscious cerebration once again being trumpeted as the proper explanation of all psychological automatisms, as though these old and vigorous debates had never occurred (see, e.g., Wegner, 2002, and its review by E. F. Kelly, 2003), and despite the fact that other modern workers such as Hilgard (1977), Kihlstrom (1993b), and Oakley (1999) have moved toward positions much closer to that adopted by Myers and James over a century ago.

Chapter 5 in effect provides what might be called an “existence proof” for the possibility that multiple, concurrent, and overlapping streams of consciousness can sometimes coexist in conjunction with a single human organism. Much of that evidence, however, derives from very unusual persons and circumstances. Myers argued that subliminal consciousness of this sort is at work in all of us, all the time, but this raises James’s second issue: Is such far-reaching generalization justifiable? This is a fair and realistic concern, but Myers himself addresses it fairly effectively, I think, and we can certainly do substantially better today. To document this adequately would take much more space than can be devoted to it here, but let me at least briefly indicate the main lines along which the argument would run.

For one thing the database of individuals displaying major automatisms of the sort relied upon by Myers has greatly expanded in the subsequent century. Many additional and sometimes even better cases of multiple personality, automatic writing and drawing, and trance mediumship, for example, have come to light more recently here in the West. Furthermore, the enormous 20th-century expansion of cultural anthropology has made evident that the core phenomena of psychological automatism have a truly world-wide distribution and reflect in all likelihood fundamental capacities which we all to some degree share. Like the trance medium Mrs. Piper, for example, shamans sometimes report ecstatic journeys undertaken during periods when to external observers they appeared to be ritually possessed by identifiable spirits, displaying behaviors appropriate to that state. Also relevant here is the fact that ritualized procedures for induction of trance and possession trance in preliterate societies often exert powerful effects on Western bystanders or observers, sometimes including quite skeptical ones intent upon defeating any such effects (Deren, 1972; Sargant, 1975). Myers certainly knew about this in general terms, but he could scarcely have imagined the wealth of relevant evidence that has since become available (Bour-gignon, 1973; E. F. Kelly & Locke, 1981b; R. G. Locke & Kelly, 1985).

Myers also underestimated, if anything, the relevance of dreaming and allied phenomena to his central argument. Subsequent research has amply confirmed his original contention that dreams have a strong propensity to serve as carriers of supernormal information, both spontaneously (e.g., Stevenson, 1970, p. 2) and in experimental studies (Child, 1985). But what modern research has also shown, and Myers did not know, is that this intensified power of involuntary inward visualization, a sensory automatism, is essentially universal among humans, as revealed in particular by the subsequent discovery of physiological correlates of dreaming itself (REM sleep) as well as by investigations of psychedelic agents, sensory deprivation, and other “hallucinogenic” conditions (Siegel & West, 1975). Although we humans differ widely in terms of access to this “cosmogonic” capacity, we all apparently have it, and as argued especially by Schiller (1905, 1915) the maker of these phantasms must be recognized as some sort of highly creative agency that resides within the personality but is distinct from everyday consciousness in the way postulated by Myers (see also Globus, 1987). That this agency is constantly at work behind the scenes is further suggested by the phenomenology of hypnagogia, in which involuntary dream-like mentation unstably commingles with drowsy ordinary consciousness (Mavroma-tis, 1987), by intrusive apparitional experiences occurring under conditions of full waking consciousness (Chapter 6), and by the “subliminal uprushes” of genius, which can occur at any time of day or night (Chapter 7).

I will return to the generality issue shortly in a different context, but let me first say a word about James’s third concern, the mingling of rubbish-heap and treasure-house in the subliminal region, the fact that “the parasitic ideas of psycho-neurosis, and the fictitious personations of planchette-writ-ing and mediumship reside there side by side with the inspirations of genius, with the faculties of telepathy and telaesthesia, and with the susceptibility of genuine spirit control” (James, 1903, p. 32). The key words here are “side by side,” which are more James’s than Myers’s. James immediately goes on to acknowledge the manner in which Myers himself actually sought to deal with this problem—that is, through his conception of the subliminal region as stratified—but finds this conception “deficient in clearness.”

I will make just three comments in response to this complaint. First, Myers himself would certainly have agreed that his conception is “deficient in clearness” in the sense that much still needs to be done to identify more fully the number and character of these strata, or more generally to map out in greater detail the structural and functional organization of the subliminal region. Nevertheless, James seems to me to overstate somewhat the difficulties here. He may have been thinking of strata as essentially geological in character, rigid and static, whereas Myers was more inclined to think of them in terms of his image of imperfectly miscible fluids of varying density, “subject to currents and ebullitions which often bring to the surface a stream or a bubble from a stratum far below” (Myers, 1892b, p. 307). On this latter view the psyche is a dynamic system constantly in flux, with currents initiated in the deeper layers boiling toward the surface and, depending on their inherent energies, emerging there in forms varyingly intermingled with material derived from intermediate layers. Such a picture, metaphoric though it is, seems naturally to accommodate the frequent but by no means invariable “smothering” of supernormal phenomena in degenerative accompaniments that so troubled James. Myers also emphasized repeatedly that the character of final outcomes—evolutive or dissolutive—is determined in large part by what the supraliminal consciousness itself is able to do with the subliminal products it receives (see our Chapter 7). Finally, another issue lurking here for James, and barely touched upon by Myers, concerns the “depth” to which operations of the subliminal parts of the mind might map directly onto operations of the brain. This general issue—how Myers’s psychological theory can be reconciled with contemporary brain science—will be discussed in detail in a later section.

We move on now to the conceptual heart of Myers’s theory of the Subliminal Self, its postulation in all of us of a more comprehensive consciousness, indeed an all-inclusive consciousness embracing the entirety of our conscious mental activity both supraliminal and subliminal, evolutive and dissolutive. The primary alternative to such a view (at least among those prepared to recognize the reality of subliminal streams of awareness) is the family of “monadic” views exemplified in particular by McDougall (1911/1961, 1920) and Balfour (1935).7

McDougall’s monadic theory of personality has already been discussed in Chapter 5. The essence of such theories is that they picture everyday consciousness as emerging at the apex of a hierarchy of lesser integrations of lower-level individuals. Under normal conditions, on this view, the ordinary self or “dominant monad” thus represents the true and only self. Balfour (1935, p. 175) candidly states, speaking for many, that “my own instinctive conviction is that my own true self is ‘the me as I know myself.” This intuition certainly corresponds both with everyday experience and with all conventional mainstream theories of personality, but it cannot be presumed to be self-evidently reliable or self-validating. As Myers puts it (HP, vol. 1, p. 13):

This is, no doubt, the apparent dictum of consciousness, but it is nothing more. And the apparent dicta of consciousness have already been shown to need correction in so many ways which the ordinary observer could never have anticipated that we surely have no right to trust consciousness, so to say, a step further than we can feel it,—to hold that anything whatever—even a separate consciousness in our own organisms—can be proved not to exist by the mere fact that we—as we know ourselves—are not aware of it.

In Chapter 5 we described how James (1902/1958, p. 188) celebrated the discovery in 1886 of “an entirely unsuspected peculiarity in the constitution of human nature,” the transmarginal consciousness identified and explored by Myers. Balfour, by contrast, wishes to reject Myers’s conception for precisely that reason, complaining that “we are asked to believe that our true self is a self the very existence of which the vast majority of mankind have never even suspected” (p. 273). But this argument too is clearly unsound. For one thing, many peculiarities of the physical world had remained undiscovered for thousands of years, including rather momentous ones such as radioactivity (Schiller, 1905). Certainly no one now believes that we routinely have full access to the structure and content of our minds. Moreover, Myers-like conceptions of a larger consciousness latent within us have in fact emerged, and repeatedly, within the world’s mystical traditions (Chapter 8).

Human personalities, like biological organisms and even society itself, have a homeostatic aspect and must constantly strive for balance between growth and preservation. But the discomfort that many of us undoubtedly experience in seriously entertaining Myers’s conception is undermined by the widespread occurrence of experiences of psychological “expansion” or “opening” that appear to support it—whether these be spontaneous or produced by psychedelic agents, meditation, or other transformative practices. It is relevant and worth repeating here that Myers and James themselves displayed a strong affinity for the mystical that was in part intellectual but also derived in part from their own mystical-type experiences, including powerful experiences induced by nitrous oxide (Chapter 8).

Myers of course also adduced a great deal of empirical evidence directly contradicting commonsense intuitions as to the supremacy of the supraliminal in our mental life, including for example extreme manifestations of bodily control, secondary personalities whose capabilities exceed those of the everyday self, genius-level creativity, hypermnesia and calculating prodigies, OBEs/NDEs and mystical experiences, psi capacities linked to dreams and other automatisms, and all the rest. Both his taxonomy of relevant phenomena and his unifying generalizations—in particular that these “supernormal” phenomena take the form of psychological automatisms arising from deeper levels of the psyche, and manifest themselves in proportion to the abeyance of the supraliminal consciousness—have been strengthened at many points by subsequent research, as demonstrated in this book.

But now we come to what I think is the logical crux of the matter. Myers conceives the supraliminal consciousness as somehow functioning simultaneously both as itself and (possibly together with one or more subliminal streams of consciousness) as part of a larger, more comprehensive consciousness, the Subliminal Self, which provides for the overarching unity of the psyche or Individuality. Both McDougall and Balfour explicitly reject this core conception. In his review of HP, McDougall (1903, p. 518) simply jibes in passing that he finds it comparable in obscurity to that of the Christian Trinity. Balfour (pp. 270–271) explicitly recognizes its formal resemblance to Fechner’s conception of the integration or “compounding” of consciousness across individuals, and he acknowledges the appeal of that conception to James (1909/1971). Yet he too summarily dismisses it, on grounds that the theory of compounding itself “presents formidable logical difficulties” and that Fechner’s solution seems to him “frankly mystical.”

Although this difficult topic really deserves a much more thorough scholarly treatment in itself, I wish to argue at least briefly here against Balfour and McDougall and on behalf of Myers and James. Both Balfour and McDougall seem to me excessively committed, a priori, to everyday consciousness as the supreme psychological achievement. Neither has much use for anything “mystical,” and certainly McDougall devotes no chapter to that subject in his otherwise comprehensive Body and Mind. Neither seems fully to have grasped Myers’s conception, for neither distinguishes systematically between subliminal selves and the Subliminal Self. As we saw, both also seriously misrepresent, in different ways, the character of higher-order compounds or integrations of conscious experience as conceived by Fech-ner and James (Chapter 8, footnote 58).

The issues come to a head in a particularly relevant way in a brief discussion by McDougall (1911/1961, pp. 358–363), in which he attempts to repudiate the transmission theory as formulated by James (1898/1900) in favor of his own preferred form of animism, his psychophysical dualism or soul theory. Although this disagreement appears at first sight to involve a head-on collision between intellectual freight-trains, what actually happens proves more akin to a passing of great ships in the night. McDougall begins by asserting that the formulations of transmission theory by James and Bergson agree on the following “essential points”:

Both reject the claims of mechanism to rule in the organic world; both regard all psychical existence as of the form of consciousness only; both assume that consciousness exists independently of the physical world in some vast ocean or oceans of consciousness; both maintain that the consciousness or psychical life of each organism is a ray from this source; that the bodily organisation of each creature is that which determines individuality; that the brain is a mechanism which lets through, or brings into operation in the physical world, a stream of consciousness which is copious in proportion to the complexity of organisation of the brain, (p. 358n)

Two features of McDougall’s portrayal of transmission theory are especially relevant here: First, he treats it as depending essentially upon the doctrine of “mind-stuff,” the notion that consciousness exists ultimately in the form of “atoms” that can be combined into larger aggregates while retaining their individual identities. Second, he portrays the brain as the organ which assembles and disassembles such compounds, and hence takes it as a necessary corollary that “the brain is the ground of our psychic individuality” (p. 358).

This latter feature, however, had already been explicitly denied by James in a crucial clarification of his own original statement of the transmission theory. This clarification, added to the second edition in the form of a preface, is so important that I will quote from it at length.8 James begins by stating that he intends to remove an objection raised by many critics of his original formulation:

If our finite personality here below, the objectors say, be due to the transmission through the brain of portions of a preëxisting larger consciousness, all that can remain after the brain expires is the larger consciousness itself as such, with which we should thenceforth be perforce reconfounded, the only means of our existence in finite personal form having ceased.

But this, the critics continue, is the pantheistic idea of immortality, survival, namely, in the soul of the world; not the Christian idea of immortality, which means survival in strictly personal form.

In showing the possibility of a mental life after the brain’s death, they conclude, the lecture has thus at the same time shown the impossibility of its identity with the personal life, which is the brain’s function….

The plain truth is that one may conceive the mental world behind the veil in as individual form as one pleases, without any detriment to the general scheme by which the brain is represented as a transmissive organ.

If the extreme individualistic view were taken, one’s finite mundane consciousness would be an extract from one’s larger, truer personality, the latter having even now some sort of reality behind the scenes. And in transmitting it—to keep to our extremely mechanical metaphor, which confessedly throws no light on the actual modus operandi—one’s brain would also leave effects on the part remaining behind the veil; for when a thing is torn, both fragments feel the operation.

And just as (to use a very coarse figure) the stubs remain in a checkbook whenever a check is used, to register the transaction, so these impressions on the transcendent self might constitute so many vouchers of the finite experiences of which the brain had been the mediator; and ultimately they might form that collection within the larger self of memories of our earthly passage, which is all that, since Locke’s day, the continuance of our personal identity beyond the grave has by psychology been recognized to mean.

It is true that all this would seem to have affinities rather with preëxistence and with possible re-incarnations than with the Christian notion of immortality. But my concern in the lecture was not to discuss immortality in general. It was confined to showing it to be not incompatible with the brain-function theory of our present mundane consciousness. I hold that it is so compatible, and compatible moreover in fully individualized form. (James, 1898/1900, pp. v-viii)

The overall resemblance between the picture sketched here by James and Myers’s model of human personality is unmistakable.

The bulk of McDougall’s attack upon transmission theory is directed at the “mind-stuff” doctrine, and more specifically at James’s attempt in A Pluralistic Universe to defend the very sort of self-compounding of mental states that he himself had destructively criticized in the Principles. McDougall clearly thinks that in doing this he is attacking the transmission theory itself, but in this he is again off the mark, for what is primarily at stake in their disagreement is not the existence of complex mental states but alternative accounts of how they come into being. We can therefore bypass the tortuous details of these arguments (although I must comment in passing that like McDougall I find James’s revised treatment of “compounding” ultimately unconvincing) and proceed instead to what for our purposes is a more critical question. Does everyday consciousness represent the highest level of consciousness within us, as McDougall and Balfour and virtually all contemporary mainstream psychologists presume, or could there really be within many or all of us a more comprehensive consciousness of the sort postulated by Myers and James? McDougall correctly identifies the two main sources of evidence relied upon by James and Myers—psychological automatisms and related dissociative phenomena, and mystical experience—but he does not discuss this evidence at all, apparently thinking (mistakenly) that his theoretical arguments against the transmission theory have already discredited their view. I must now say a little more about this evidence.

James (1909/1971) clearly thought that phenomena of divided personality, hypnosis, automatic writing and speech, and trance mediumship collectively demonstrate the existence of inclusive or higher-order consciousness as a real psychological phenomenon:

For my own part I find in some of these abnormal or supernormal facts the strongest suggestions in favor of a superior coconsciousness being possible. I doubt whether we shall ever understand some of them without using the very letter of Fechner’s conception of a great reservoir in which the memories of earth’s inhabitants are pooled and preserved, and from which, when the threshold lowers or the valve opens, information ordinarily shut out leaks into the mind of exceptional individuals among us. (p. 264)

The main evidence from these sources for inclusive forms of co-consciousness has been summarized in Chapters 2 and 5 and need not be repeated here; I will only say again that I too find it convincing in that regard (but see Balfour, 1935, pp. 272–276, and Gauld, 1968, pp. 296–299 for different views).9

In the Conclusions chapter of A Pluralistic Universe, James turns to religious and mystical experience for additional evidence:

The sort of belief that religious experience of this type naturally engenders in those who have it is fully in accord with Fechner’s theories. To quote words which I have used elsewhere [i.e., in the Conclusions chapter of VRE], the believer finds that the tenderer parts of his personal life are continuous with a more of the same quality which is operative in the universe outside of him and which he can keep in working touch with, and in a fashion get on board of and save himself, when all his lower being has gone to pieces in the wreck. In a word, the believer is continuous, to his own consciousness, at any rate, with a wider self from which saving experiences flow in. Those who have such experiences distinctly enough and often enough to live in the light of them remain quite unmoved by criticism, from whatever quarter it may come, be it academic or scientific, or be it merely the voice of logical common sense. They have had their vision and they know—that is enough—that we inhabit an invisible spiritual environment from which help comes, our soul being mysteriously one with a larger soul whose instruments we are. (p. 267)

Mystical experience in its higher forms seems to me to strengthen Myers’s position in several important ways. First, it cannot be denied that the most relevant cases of multiple personality are not only rare but distinctly pathological in character, in that a more inclusive secondary personality often, though not always, experiences itself as distinct from, and even alien and hostile to, the primary personality. Balfour (1935) correctly points out that this is not what we should expect on Myers’s theory of the normal personality, for (ignoring Balfour’s incorrect terminology) “if the subliminal ‘phase’ of a man’s consciousness represented his true self, we might actually expect that, on ceasing to be subliminal, it would absorb into itself the supraliminal phase, and the two phases would be as one self” (pp. 273–274). But as James above suggests, and as we showed in greater detail in Chapter 8, something of just this expected sort does regularly happen in conjunction with profound mystical experiences, in which the everyday self opens up, widens or expands, and becomes at least temporarily identified with some sort of larger, wiser, and benign self hidden within. The supraliminal self is not condemned, obstructed, or obliterated but transcended, in a highly positive direction and with powerful transformative aftereffects that appear in many instances to be objectively measurable.

Evidence from the mystical domain also bears strongly on the generality issues discussed earlier. In the first place, there have certainly been thousands if not millions of deep mystical experiences in the course of human history, many involving quite ordinary and unprepared persons, and the mystical traditions are unanimous in believing that all of us are capable of achieving such experiences through appropriate sorts of transformative practice. Furthermore, although the occurrence of such an experience does not itself necessarily imply that the larger consciousness had been there all along, as Myers and James suppose, that is certainly the way most mystics have experienced and reported it—that is, as something already present within, which they had uncovered or found. Indeed, the course of the mystic vocation often involves a kind of oscillation between these concentric surface and depth poles of the psyche, as its center of gravity shifts toward the latter, and in more permanent states of deep mystical realization these dual foci may sometimes even be maintained simultaneously (Forman, 1999, chap. 9).

It also seems highly relevant, and psychologically plausible, that the deeper focus is typically characterized as a passive knower or witness, rather than as an actor in its own right; thus for example the Upanishads repeatedly invoke the metaphor of “two birds on the self-same tree, always companions, one of which looks on while the other eats the sweet fruit.” The same picture underlies Patanjali’s practical system of yoga and its theoretical companion, the Samkhya system of orthodox Hindu philosophy. In the normal situation, that is, the surface and depth foci are more or less concentric or in alignment, and only when the deeper consciousness with its more potent faculties and more comprehensive point of view finds the supraliminal getting out of alignment, so to speak, would it exert its influence through psychological automatisms of the sorts described by Myers and James—saving religious experiences, uprushes of genius, veridical apparitions, phenomena of extreme psychophysical influence, and so on.

The net status of Myers’s conception of the Subliminal Self seems to me presently as follows. The conception itself is admittedly counterintuitive and logically difficult. I find especially challenging, for example, its aspect of inclusiveness, and wonder whether the Subliminal Self might better be conceived as “more comprehensive” in some weaker sense.10 The evidence presently supporting Myers’s conception is also less than compelling, and certainly it falls far short of the form proposed by Gauld (1968) as necessary for a “conclusive” demonstration—specifically, “the bringing to light in a large number of people of a hidden stream of consciousness which could give a coherent and testable account of its own past history and actions” (p. 299). Nevertheless, it seems to me definitely possible and perhaps even probable, especially in light of the evidence flowing from mystical experiences, that Myers and James really have identified a more or less correct account of the overall structure and dynamics of the human psyche—one, furthermore, that is capable of accommodating in a natural way a far wider array of empirical observations than any of its rivals. In sum, although Myers’s theory of the Subliminal Self is by no means proven, it constitutes at minimum, in my estimation, a viable and useful working model capable of guiding further research.

Post-Mortem Survival

And now what about Myers’s most central concern—whether there is or is not personal survival of bodily death? Survival is not ruled out a priori and in general by filter or transmission models of mind and personality, as it is by all conventional production models. On the other hand, animistic or filter models themselves do not as a class necessarily entail survival, although they do render it in varying degrees less improbable.

Myers clearly regarded survival as an almost inevitable corollary of the specific type of personality theory that he elaborates in HP, and indeed to demonstrate this forms the central strategy and goal of his exposition (his “broad-canvas” approach; see our Chapters 2 and 4). At the same time, it should be recognized that the empirical case for survival does not depend on the correctness of this particular theory. I wish next to summarize the collective sense of our group as to the empirical status of this problem.

The basic issues have already been framed in Chapters 4 and 5. Briefly, detailed and specific information has sometimes come forward—under conditions which rule out “normal” explanations involving conscious or unconscious cheating, cryptomnesia, defects of memory or reporting, cold reading, and the like—which suggests the possible continued existence in some form of previously living persons. In the best such cases the potentially viable explanations appear reduced to two principal candidates, either survival itself or some sort of extreme supernormal (psi) process involving only living persons.

Myers was convinced by the evidence available to him—while acknowledging that it might not be as convincing to others (HP, vol. 2, p. 79)—that survival is a fact of nature: “It seems to me now that the evidence for communication with the spirits of identified deceased persons through the tranceutterances and writings of sensitives apparently controlled by those spirits is established beyond serious attack” (HP, vol. 1, p. 29). Myers’s acceptance of personal survival seemed to many of his colleagues at the time, and still seems to us, premature. This impression, however, may in part reflect the fact that much of what Myers himself regarded as his best evidence was either never published at all or could not be published in a manner that adequately conveys the impact of evidential details and their verisimilitude available privately to him. His well-known emotional interest in survival, in any event, seems unlikely to have biased his judgment, as he himself pointed out (HP, vol. 2, p. 294; see also our Chapter 2).

A considerable amount of additional evidence suggestive of survival has accumulated in the subsequent century, some of it of very high quality. Most of this evidence is of types already known to Myers, although acquired in larger amounts and with various methodological refinements, while some—such as cases of the reincarnation type, including those involving birthmarks and birth defects (Chapter 3)—is almost entirely new. The net result of this accumulation of evidence has been to bring the conflict between survival and “super-psi” interpretations into ever-sharper relief, as pro-survival researchers have sought to identify phenomena and testing procedures that increasingly strain the relative credibility of super-psi interpretations.

For example, it might initially seem plausible that a medium could acquire information sufficient to impersonate some deceased individual through telepathic interactions with sitters, especially if a single sitter is present who has exactly the relevant information. That plausibility may seem to diminish, however, when no such person is present, as in a “proxy” sitting; or in sittings when a “drop-in” communicator appears, unknown to anyone present but subsequently identified as a formerly living person; or when the necessary information is distributed across multiple individuals, some of whom are not present; or when some of that information is also contained in obscure documents not even known at that moment to exist. Conversely, survival seems to become more plausible to the degree that many sources of relevant information are potentially available, with some conflicting, yet the ostensible communicator delivers information circumscribed precisely to that which the deceased person himself would have known, in a manner demonstrably in accord with his intentions, and with his characteristic mannerisms, diction, humor, and the like.11

This brief and abstract description will serve, I hope, to illustrate the general flavor of these debates, which seem to many well-informed observers to have arrived at a logical impasse. The core problem hinges on the fact that information provided by an ostensibly surviving communicator can only be verified by reference to information which is known to some living person or persons, or objectively documented in some other fashion, and hence which is also in principle potentially accessible to some sort of psi process. It is therefore always possible to invent scenarios according to which apparent evidence of survival can be “explained” alternatively in terms of psi processes involving only living persons. Such scenarios may need to be fantastically complex, but psi has been shown in various experimental contexts to operate in a “goal-oriented” manner unaffected by the apparent “complexity” of its tasks (H. Schmidt, 1987), and consequently they cannot be decisively refuted. But note the real logical peculiarity here: It is not that we have positive knowledge that psi processes can accomplish the extraordinary things required by such explanations, but rather that we are presently unable to prove they cannot.12

Let me conclude this section with a few general observations on the net status of this debate. First, it involves a large body of relevant empirical evidence which at present is virtually unknown to the great majority of laypersons and scientists alike. Our Appendix provides many pointers into this literature, emphasizing sources which illustrate in cogent form properties of the sorts characterized above as particularly suggestive of survival. We insist that anyone who wishes to participate meaningfully in discussions of the survival question must study this literature, thoughtfully and with an open mind.

Second, the core issue of super-psi versus survival cannot be decisively resolved at the present time. Persons sufficiently determined to deny survival while accepting the reality of psi can continue to do so rationally, but provisional acceptance of the survival hypothesis is also rationally warranted by the evidence available. One might also choose, of course, to defer commitment either way, pending further information.

As a matter of historical fact, able and informed students such as Braude (2003), Broad (1962), Dodds (1934), Ducasse (1961, 1969), Gauld (1982), G. Murphy (1945), Price (1966), and Stevenson (e.g., 1977; 1997, chap. 26), among numerous others, have divided more or less equally, and for the most part narrowly, along the two sides of this divide. Some have remained undecided, and Stephen Braude, for many years a particularly determined defender of super-psi interpretations, has recently moved tentatively to a mildly pro-survival position much like our own.

Our general attitude toward super-psi explanations, in the first place, is essentially that of Ducasse (1969):

When Occam’s razor is alleged to shave off survival as a superfluous hypothesis, and to leave ESP as sufficient to account for all the facts in evidence, it turns out that ESP cannot do it without being arbitrarily endowed with an ad hoc “beard” consisting not of capacity for more far-reaching perception, but of capacity for reasoning, inventing, constructing, understanding, judging; i.e. for active thinking; and more specifically for the particular modes of such thinking which only the particular mind whose survival is in question is known to have been equipped with. (p. 41)

Secondly, the totality of the evidence now available seems to us to have tilted the balance somewhat further in favor of the survival hypothesis. Of particular significance in this regard, in our opinion, are mediumistic cases involving proxy sitters (E. W. Kelly, in press) and drop-in communicators (for references to this research, see Braude, 2003, chap. 2; and Gauld, 1982, chap. 5), cases of the reincarnation type (e.g., Stevenson, 1997, 2001), and NDEs occurring under extreme physiological conditions (our Chapter 6). The last may in the long run prove especially critical, for they arise from the very heart of mainstream biomedical science, and seem likely to become more numerous and compelling as our capacity to rescue physiologically monitored human beings from the borderland of death increases.

Finally, and perhaps most importantly, the broader theoretical setting that frames this debate is itself shifting, and in a manner that makes survival appear to us more likely. In Chapter 3 we highlighted the dynamic interplay between fact and theory in the specific context of phenomena of extreme psychophysical influence, showing how previously suspect empirical phenomena suddenly become acceptable once scientists find a theory that appears to permit them. We think a process of this sort is already underway in regard to the entire range of interrelated empirical phenomena discussed in this book and that this will ultimately vindicate Myers’s “broad-canvas” approach to the survival question itself.

More specifically, we think that if other things were anywhere near equal, most rational persons would conclude, on the basis of the available evidence, that survival in some form is at least possible, and perhaps even a demonstrated empirical reality. The problem, of course, is that “other things” seem to most scientists nowhere near equal, because of the seemingly overwhelming antecedent improbability of survival in the context of present-day mainstream science and philosophy. As G. Murphy and Dale (1961) had already remarked, “it is the biological and the philosophical difficulty with survival that holds us back, not really the unacceptability of the evidence as such” (p. 213). We believe, however, that these theoretical difficulties can be greatly attenuated or even removed, and in a way that potentially accommodates most or all of the rogue phenomena we have discussed, survival included.

We will attempt shortly to demonstrate this in some detail. Meanwhile, although we ourselves are collectively disposed to regard survival in some form as at minimum an empirical possibility, and perhaps even a probability, I hasten to add that we expressly disavow any more specific claims, at present, as to its incidence and nature. A wide range of possible forms can be discriminated (Broad, 1962, Epilogue), and there exists at least some evidence consistent with each of them. These range from mere transient persistence of at least a few memories, to persistence of something much like the earthly personality with evidence of thought, planning, conscious will, and so on (Ducasse, 1961, 1969), to merging into some sort of transpersonal field (G. Murphy, 1945). It may seem plausible to suppose like Myers that if anyone survives in personal form we all do, but in making this particular leap Myers was certainly too hasty, for survival could perfectly well occur in widely differing forms and durations for different persons, or not at all, depending on a host of factors we currently know nothing about.13

I will leave the matter there for present purposes. Whether or not readers are swayed by our assessment of the survival issue, we will be satisfied if we have convinced them of the difficulty and importance of the problem, and of the fact that it is amenable to empirical investigation. We also wish to emphasize in concluding this section that a choice must ultimately be made between super-psi and survival interpretations of the survival evidence. Both horns of this dilemma are in our view fatal to the current mainstream materialist synthesis, but the occurrence of survival in particular—of any form—would decisively resolve the conflict between production and transmission models of mind-brain relations in favor of some sort of transmission model.

Myers’s Generalized Concept of Evolution

As Chapters 2 and 7 have already indicated, the concept of evolution is central to Myers’s theory of personality (HP, vol. 1, p. 19). He accepted Darwin’s doctrine of natural selection as the basis of organic evolution, but sought to integrate it with his own conception of human personality as rooted in a hidden, wider environment that underlies and interpenetrates the world of ordinary experience, at bottom a spiritual or “metetherial” realm lying beyond the material as classically conceived.

The main novelty of this broadened conception of evolution is set forth in his chapter on genius (HP, vol. 1, pp. 93–98, 111–120). Like conventional evolutionary theorists, Myers recognizes that new capacities emerge in conjunction with the sorts of “protoplasmic” changes played upon by natural selection. Unlike such theorists, however, he thinks of these capacities as being not so much generated by the organic changes as released by them from the subliminal or metetherial realm, in which in some sense they already existed, latent but unrealized. Thus,

I hold, of course, that sports or variations occur, which are at present unpredictable, and which reveal in occasional offspring faculties which their parents showed no signs of possessing. But I differ from those who hold that the faculty itself thus manifested is now for the first time initiated in that stock by some chance combination of hereditary elements. I hold that it is not initiated, but only revealed; that the “sport” has not called a new faculty into being, but has merely raised an existing faculty above the threshold of supraliminal consciousness. (HP, vol. 1, p. 118)

Myers acknowledges that at most points his view is essentially indistinguishable from the conventional view:

No fresh mystery is in fact introduced. All human powers, to put the thing broadly, have somehow or other to be got into protoplasm and then got out again. You have to explain first how they became implicit in the earliest and lowest living thing, and then how they have become thus far explicit in the latest and highest. All the faculties of that highest being, I repeat, existed virtually in the lowest, and in so far as the admitted faculties are concerned the difference between my view and the ordinary view may be said to be little more than a difference as to the sense which that word virtually is here to assume. (HP, vol. 1, p. 118)

The real difference between the two conceptions becomes apparent, however, in regard to certain additional capacities—such as telepathy and telaesthesia—which Myers regards as inherently and necessarily beyond the reach of any explanation based on material factors alone. Inasmuch as capacities of this sort definitely do exist, less unusual ones can perhaps also be re-conceptualized in analogous fashion. On such a view, for example, one might even suppose with Myers that “the specialised forms of terrene perception were not real novelties in the universe, but imperfect adaptations of protoplasm to the manifestation of the indwelling general perceptive power” (HP, vol. 1, p. 118). To illustrate the hypothesized “release” of subliminal capacities by novelties of biological constitution, Myers appeals to the example of the calculating prodigy Dase, as described in our Chapter 7. But the central thrust of his argument is that our highest human attributes—including our capacities for music, art, poetry, beauty, pure mathematics, truth, and love—are of this sort, and not merely “sports” or “spandrels,” by-products of organic evolution itself. Myers thus conceives of evolution as having a “cosmical” as well as a “planetary” aspect, tending globally toward progressive release of these higher attributes and hence toward “constantly widening and deepening perception of an environment infinite in infinite ways” (HP, vol. 1, p. 96). On his view this does not happen according to any preset or inevitable plan, however; our evolutionary fate remains uncertain, and it is very much in our own hands.

Myers freely acknowledges that this generalized conception of evolution is a speculative hypothesis founded upon his more fundamental and empirically grounded conception of the subliminal realm. Yet this view, he insists,

is not one whit remoter or more speculative than the view which, faute de mieux, is often tacitly assumed by scientific writers. My supposed opponent and I are like two children who have looked through a keyhole at the first few moves in a game of chess,—of whose rules we are entirely ignorant. My companion urges that since we have only seen the pawns moved, it is probable that the game is played with the pawns alone; and that the major pieces seen confusedly behind the pawns are only a kind of fringe or ornament of the board. I reply that those pieces stand on the board like pawns; and that since they are larger and more varied than the pawns, it is probable that they are meant to play some even more important rôle in the game as it develops. We agree that we must wait and see whether the pieces are moved; and I now maintain that I have seen a piece moved [i.e., telepathy], although my companion has not noticed it.

The chessboard in this parable is the Cosmos; the pawns are those human faculties which make for the preservation and development on this planet of the individual and the race; the pieces are faculties which may either be the mere by-products of terrene evolution, or on the other hand may form an essential part of the faculty with which the human germ or the human spirit is originally equipped, for the purpose of self-development in a cosmical, as opposed to a merely planetary, environment. (HP, vol. 1, pp. 93–94)

Having briefly described Myers’s general conception of evolution, I must now attempt to evaluate it. To this end I shall begin with James (1901), who clearly acknowledges the significance of that conception, while not attempting to adjudicate as to its truth:

I feel sure that [it] is a hypothesis of first-rate philosophic importance. It is based, of course, on his conviction of the extent of the Subliminal, and will stand or fall as that is verified or not; but whether it stand or fall, it looks to me like one of those sweeping ideas by which the scientific researches of an entire generation are often molded, (p. 21)

I think we can go slightly further now, but I must preface the following brief remarks by saying that I intend to tread very lightly here, in part because of my own very limited acquaintance with evolutionary biology, and in part because of the super-heated cultural conflicts currently swirling around this topic.

I do think there has been a small net movement in the direction of Myers’s view. First, as the present book seeks to demonstrate, his general picture of mind and personality has in fact continued to accumulate various kinds of empirical support, even as theoretical and empirical difficulties and limitations have come to light in competing accounts of conventional materialist/reductionist sort, such as the CTM (Chapter 1). As James pointed out, this in itself tends to work in favor of Myers’s larger view.

Second, there has recently been some motion in this direction from within evolutionary biology itself. Let me speak very carefully here. Myers was certainly no creationist, nor even an “intelligent design” theorist unless in the most attenuated sense. All he requires is that there be some global creative tendency in the universe, however slight, that results over time in increasing richness and complexity of biological forms.14 But even some mainstream evolutionary biologists seem prepared to accept pictures of this sort. Commentator Robert Wright (1999), for example, while explicitly denying that evolution is directed specifically toward us—Homo sapiens—points out that the average complexity of species has in fact risen in general, driven by competitive pressures (“arms races”) within and between species, and that mammalian lineages in particular have tended toward increased “braininess.” Certain useful properties such as vision and flight have also been reinvented repeatedly during the course of evolution, and Wright explicitly proposes that similar built-in tendencies may exist with respect to higher-order properties, such as intelligence, altruism, and love, that are of course central to Myers’s vision. Similarly, both Wright himself and the evolutionary biologist Lumsden (1999) point to an increasing recognition among neo-Darwinian theorists that in humans the evolution of the genome has become strongly intertwined with the evolution of civilization itself, so that they cannot be thought of as proceeding independently on separate tracks. Lumsden even goes so far as to state flatly that “human creativity is the fire that drives gene-culture coevolution” (p. 160).15

Views of these latter sorts seem within range of rapprochement with Myers’s generalized concept of evolution. Modern neo-Darwinists certainly have achieved a greatly expanded mechanistic understanding of the material side of evolution, but I think Myers would unhesitatingly endorse that aspect of their science. The main residual difference lies rather in the presumption, shared by most evolutionary biologists with virtually all other contemporary mainstream scientists, that genius along with all other human mental functions can be fully and satisfactorily explained in terms of classical physicalist principles. This presumption was firmly rejected by both Myers and James, and the central theme of the present volume has been to substantiate that they were correct in doing so. Myers’s generalized picture of evolution, in sum, may yet prove closer to the truth.

Myers/James Filter Theory and Contemporary Science: Toward Reconciliation

Up to this point I have been arguing on behalf of the Myers/James picture as a purely psychological theory, urging its provisional acceptance as a useful working model of the overall structure and organization of the human psyche. I have also tentatively endorsed the reality of post-mortem survival as an empirical phenomenon, while reserving judgment on Myers’s generalized evolutionary doctrine pending further information.16

The appeal of Myers’s theory derives for me from two principal factors: First, it encompasses an enormous range of empirical phenomena, including a variety of phenomena which lie beyond the reach of mainstream materialist views. One aim of this book has been to show that many such “rogue” phenomena exist, as Myers and James both firmly believed, and that the evidence for them has in general become far stronger during the subsequent century. Furthermore, these empirical phenomena—both “normal” and “supernormal”—are interconnected in such a way that one cannot provide an empirically satisfactory treatment of any one of them without necessarily becoming entangled with others as well. One cannot deal adequately with psi phenomena, for example, without recognizing and somehow accommodating their deep associations with topics such as dreaming, genius, and mysticism. The power of Myers’s theory derives not so much from an incontrovertible superiority in explaining any of these phenomena individually as in providing a coherent and plausible scheme of interpretation for all of them at once. And this is a great virtue of Myers’s theory, as pointed out by Schiller (1905): “A synthesis which embraces such a multitude of facts does not rest solely on any one set of them, and in a sense grows independent of them all. That is, the mere coherence of the interpretation becomes a great point in its favour as against a variety of unconnected alternatives” (p. 70).

Myers’s theory also has predictive value, at least in the sense of directing our attention toward additional types of phenomena that might be expected both to exist and to be accessible to empirical investigation. Myers himself, for example, seems to have anticipated both NDEs in general (see our Chapter 6) and the “mindsight” phenomenon reported tentatively by Ring and Cooper (1997, 1999), in which congenitally blind persons undergoing NDEs report a kind of quasi-visual awareness of their physical surroundings (Myers, 1891c, pp. 126–127). The demonstrated association of psi with altered states such as dreaming, hypnagogia, and twilight states emerging under Ganzfeld conditions also is broadly consistent with his general principle that subliminal functions emerge in proportion to the abeyance of normal supraliminal functioning. Similarly, his concept of a “permeable” boundary between the supraliminal and subliminal regions implies that persons whose boundaries are demonstrably more permeable, as measured for example by the scales of Thalbourne (1998; Thalbourne & Delin, 1994) and Hartmann (1991), should show more evidence of subliminal functioning, such as creativity, psi, involuntary imagery and other automatisms, and recall of dreams and early childhood events, all of which have been at least tentatively confirmed. Another such implication, which is rumored to be true but to my knowledge has not yet been seriously investigated, is that psi phenomena should be prominently associated with dissociative disorders such as MPD/DID, and perhaps especially with those “alters” that are deepest or most comprehensive. Many other examples have been provided in earlier chapters, and more will be supplied below.

But are these considerations sufficient to justify Myers’s theory? The “correct” answer here ultimately depends on one’s answer to the prior philosophical question as to precisely what criteria are appropriate for justification of a psychological theory of this sort. This general and very difficult problem is the subject of ongoing discussion within our Esalen theory group, and I will certainly not attempt to resolve it here. However, the basic issues come into sharper focus in the context of a less favorable appraisal of Myers’s theory by Gauld (1992):

The broad framework is not one that can be used to derive the details of the phenomena that are used to support it. It may “make sense” of the phenomena, but it does not enable us unequivocally to predict any particular phenomenon. This situation obtains commonly enough in psychology, but it would generally be thought undesirable in the “hard” sciences and by philosophers. A partial parallel, however, is provided by the Darwinian theory of evolution. Here too we have a broad and abstract hypothesis which “makes sense” of a great mass of observations; yet it would be hard to maintain that the details of the data can be directly derived from the theory. Of course since Darwin’s time certain paths have been established which fill some of the space between the theory and particular features of the phenomena. Nothing similar has been accomplished in respect of Myers’s theory of the subliminal self [we]. If it had been, Myers would perhaps now be as famous as Darwin, (pp. 399–400)

I will make just two main comments on this relatively negative assessment. First, I think the demand for derivation of phenomena in all details is too strong a requirement for justification of large-scale psychological theories, although I will not attempt to argue this point here. I also think, as indicated above, that Myers’s theory does in fact have significant predictive value, albeit of a weaker sort than that characteristic of the “hard” sciences. Second, although Gauld certainly is correct in pointing to the subsequent “filling in” of Darwin’s theory as having contributed in major ways to its justification, I think he overstates the contrast between Darwin and Myers in this respect. In the first place, as indicated above, a good deal of descriptive filling-in has already occurred, in the sense of more and better documentation for phenomena already utilized by Myers himself in developing his scheme, and the discovery of additional phenomena consistent with it.

One major gap remains, however. It was specifically the rise of new scientific disciplines such as population genetics and molecular biology that did more than anything else to fill in and buttress the original Darwinian theory. Similarly, a psychological theory of the sort advanced by Myers and James cannot be sustained unless it can somehow be reconciled with the enormous advances of the ensuing century in what we know about the brain. The central task of this section, therefore, is to demonstrate that such reconciliation may in fact be possible.

We believe that the empirical evidence marshaled in this book is sufficient to falsify all forms of biological naturalism, the current physicalist consensus on mind-brain relations.17 The mind is “irreducible” in a stronger sense than that intended by epiphenomenalists, including Chalmers,18 or even by those like Searle who are at least committed to salvaging mind and consciousness as causal factors in behavior, but cannot explain how to do so in conventional physicalist terms. There is apparently at least one fundamental bifurcation in nature that cannot be accounted for in these terms, and we therefore seem driven toward some sort of animist or pluralist alternative.

Although the primary purpose and merit of our book consist in the marshaling of the evidence itself, we also think it is now possible to see at least dimly how a psychological “filter” theory of the Myers/James sort can be adapted to the framework of contemporary science, and we wish to provide at least in outline some more positive characterization of these possibilities. We emphasize at the outset that this account is necessarily provisional and very incomplete; our goal is simply to suggest a variety of potentially fruitful directions for further investigation. We also urge readers to bear in mind as they work through this section, as we have in developing it, the wise counsel of H. H. Price (1939): “We may safely predict that it will be the timidity of our hypotheses, and not their extravagance, which will provoke the derision of posterity” (p. 341).

We must begin by making clearer what we mean by “a psychological filter theory of the Myers/James sort.” In the first place, in lumping Myers and James together in this way we do not mean to imply that they hold identical views on all subjects, but only that their overall conceptions of the psyche are far more similar to each other than to any materialist/reductionist theory past or present.

We also need to specify more carefully our interpretation of James’s “transmission” or “filter” theory, originally introduced in Chapter 1 and recurring intermittently thereafter throughout this book.19 As invoked informally and loosely so far, this amounts only to a family of related but somewhat cloudy metaphors bearing a variety of unexamined connotations and implications regarding the role of the brain in our mental life. “Transmission,” for example, suggests faithful conveyance from one place to another, but this is certainly not what Myers had in mind with his theory of the Subliminal Self and its relations with the supraliminal self. The related term “filter,” which like Aldous Huxley’s “reducing valve” suggests selection, narrowing, and loss, is much more appropriate to that relationship, and for that reason we greatly prefer it as a shorthand description of Myers’s theory.

But how does this relate to the brain? Myers’s theory as he himself developed it is entirely psychological, not philosophical, and he also says extremely little about the brain. It is rather James, the psychologist and philosopher, who explicitly links these notions of transmission and filtering with the brain. James in fact suggests a variety of metaphors, but the one that has most commonly been seized upon by others is that of optical devices such as colored glass, lenses, and prisms. The common feature is that a beam of integral white light presented to such devices comes out the other side filtered, reduced, focused, redirected, or otherwise altered in some systematic fashion.

Subsequent advocates of transmission or filter models have tended naturally to update this basic picture with reference to emerging technologies such as radio and television. Thus for example we find Strassman (2001) comparing the brain to a TV receiver, and likening entry into the altered states produced by psychedelics to changing the channel. There are two generic problems with accounts of this sort, however, that we must attempt to avoid. First, all metaphors of the radio and TV variety clearly engender homunculus problems of the sorts described in Chapter 1; after all, who is it that is watching Strassman’s TV and changing the channels? More generally, we must not endow the “filter” with all the properties we are trying to account for in the mind itself—properties such as high-level thinking, memory, imagination, conceptual grasp, and so on.

The common feature of these metaphors, and the root of their conceptual problems, is the idea of passage through the filter. There is a way around this, however. Recall that the central goal of James’s original analysis was to show that even perfect correlation between brain events and mental events entails neither the impossibility of post-mortem survival nor the truth of the conventional materialist production theory of brain-mind relations. Those views derive from interpreting the admitted facts of functional dependence—mind-brain correlations—in one particular way. Other possibilities exist, however: “When we think of the law that thought is a function of the brain, we are not required to think of productive function only; we are entitled also to consider permissive or transmissive function. And this the ordinary psychophysiologist leaves out of his account” (James, 1898/1900, p. 15).

Most subsequent advocates of James’s analysis, as we have seen, have invoked its “transmission” thread, so much so that the whole picture is now widely known by that name alone. We think this unfortunate, because it is actually the other thread—permission—that is theoretically the more promising. More generally, we wish now to argue that by thinking of the brain as an organ which somehow constrains, regulates, restricts, limits, and enables or permits expression of the mind in its full generality, we can obtain an account of mind-brain relations which potentially reconciles Myers’s theory of the Subliminal Self with the observed correlations between mind and brain, while circumventing the conceptual difficulties identified above in transmission models. We in fact see a spectrum of potentially viable theoretical possibilities of this sort. We will next canvas these under two broad headings—non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist models and neutral-monist models—that seem to us to bracket the range.

Non-Cartesian Dualist-interactionist Models

When theories need to be changed in order to accommodate discordant observations, it usually makes sense, as a matter of scientific policy, to change them in ways that seem to do the least possible violence to the existing theories, while enabling us to explain those additional observations. This attitude leads in the present case to the family of what we are calling “non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist models,” and more specifically to a subset of such models corresponding to the psychological filter theory elaborated by Myers (Chapter 2) and carried forward by James (Chapter 8), which can be viewed as the most highly developed example so far among models of this sort.20 The driving idea is that associated with each human organism, a physical thing in the ordinary sense, is a second thing, a mind or psyche, which interacts in some way with that organism. Based upon the evidence summarized in this book, we will also presume for the sake of discussion that the psyche has the kind of internal organization and dynamics assigned to it by Myers and James, and that it may under various circumstances, including circumstances involving serious bodily injury or death, be able to function in some manner on its own. What we want to focus on here is how we can conceive of its normal interactions with the associated organism.

We will begin by briefly noting that there have been previous efforts along dualist lines by modern scientists, including some very distinguished 20th-century neuroscientists.21 One group includes Charles Sherrington and two of his students, John Eccles and Wilder Penfield. All three expressed the conviction that the properties of minds cannot be reduced to or identified with those of brains, and all attempted to support that conviction by reference to empirical data of various kinds. In all cases, however, the evidence marshaled, although readily interpretable within a dualist-interactionist framework, was insufficient to establish it, since alternative explanations based on the conventional viewpoint were nowhere decisively excluded. Popper and Eccles (1977) suffered the additional liability that their attacks were directed mainly at associationist-type theories that had already largely disappeared from cognitive psychology.22 In Eccles’s case it was also clear, as shown for example by his last (1994) book, that he had embraced dualism early in life and for largely non-scientific reasons (his Catholicism, possibly supplemented by an OBE), and had sought throughout his career simply to tell this unchanging dualist story in the most up-to-date neurophysiological language. The net result, in any case, was that the dualistic views of all three have largely been ignored by mainstream psychologists and neuroscientists.

Next comes another major neuroscientist, Roger Sperry (e.g., 1980, 1993), who also sought to salvage the mind but in a slightly different way, essentially by splitting the difference between mainstream physicalist views and an outright dualism. He undoubtedly took note of the hostile reception accorded his fellow Nobel prize winner Eccles, and hoped to avoid a similar fate. His compromise position, “monistic dualism,” holds that mind and consciousness “emerge” from brain processes when these processes reach a certain threshold of complexity. The emergent properties are said then to seize control of lower-level aspects of brain function, much as, for example, an eddy generated by the turbulent flow of a stream “enslaves” the leaves that circulate within it. The problem is that Sperry essentially stipulates the emergence without really accounting for it in physicalist terms; both the emergent and the enslaved phenomena are unambiguously physical in all his analogies.23 His emergent consciousness appears miraculously and then takes on a life of its own, so to speak; but this radical kind of emergence has been specifically rejected as incoherent by more consistent physicalists such as Searle (1992) and Kim (1998). McDougall (1911/1961) had also rejected such views, which already existed at the end of the 19th century, as “animism of the lowest or most meagre degree” (p. 357); they seemed to him to sacrifice the advantages of the mainstream materialist doctrine, and to introduce all the problems of dualism without any of its potentially compensating advantages. In sum, Sperry’s attempted compromise also failed to take hold.

Preceding chapters of this book have already shown that a much stronger empirical case for some sort of interactive dualism can now be made. But before attempting to move any further in this theoretical direction we must next deal with several conceptual issues that have seemed to many observers to constitute serious or even fatal a priori obstacles to doing so. To begin, we reject categorically the apparent presumption of most contemporary scientists and philosophers that any departure from the currently fashionable materialist monism is necessarily antiscientific, and that to move toward pluralism in any form is in and of itself inescapably tantamount to abandoning several centuries of scientific achievement, releasing the black flood of occultism, and reverting to primitive supernaturalist beliefs characteristic of bygone times. As John Searle (1992) correctly observes, only this prevailing terror of dualism can explain the mainstream’s willingness to put forward, and to tolerate, the various kinds of patently unsatisfactory materialist accounts of mind-brain relations that we have seen over the past hundred years. We agree with Searle’s diagnosis, of course, but not with his solution. We think, and will attempt to show, that Myers-like theories can be framed in ways that not only can potentially accommodate most or all of the relevant psychological and neurophysiological data, but also are fully compatible with front-line physical science itself.

We certainly do not advocate return to an unmodified Cartesianism. We can immediately abandon the most controversial parts of the Cartesian conceptual apparatus, including in particular the notion of mind and body as ontologically distinct “substances” with essential or criterial attributes of thinking and extension, respectively. A conceptual distinction can be made between mind and brain without presupposing this kind of ontological division, as recognized clearly by McDougall (1911/1961). The absolute dichotomy set up by Descartes between mind and body has been substantially undermined, historically. For one thing, the phenomenological solidity of matter has proved evanescent in the face of advances on the physical side. Furthermore, at least some forms of mental activity such as perception and visual imagery inherently have quasi-spatial phenomenological properties, as emphasized particularly by writers such as Brann (1991), Price (1953), Smythies (1994), and Velmans (1996). As Myers himself clearly recognized (Chapter 2), the Cartesian gulf has already narrowed and may be bridged, or bridgeable, by further advances from either or both sides; thus, “It is no longer safe to assume any sharply-defined distinction of mind and matter…. Our notions of mind and matter must pass through many a phase as yet unimagined” (Myers, 1886c, pp. 178–179). Myers himself anticipated the possible eventual discovery of a single common something, a Tertium Quid, that would bring the two poles together, while others have imagined a whole series of intermediate levels, still in some sense “physical,” that could serve as “vehicles of consciousness” (Poortman, 1954/1978).

These developments have immediate impact on the argument that has most commonly been made against interactive dualism, the causal argument. Once Descartes had made mind and body so utterly different, it is alleged, there is no longer any way for them to interact causally, and therefore dualism must be false. Searle (1992) takes this line. However, whatever force this argument ever had certainly has been diminished by the subsequent blurring of the supposed ontological divide between mind and body. Moreover, it is not apparent to us that the argument had any real force to begin with. Descartes himself took psychophysical interaction as a given, an explanatory primitive, and resisted attempts to construe it on the contact-interaction model of classical physical causation (Richardson, 1982). Causal relations are not necessarily transparent, and ever since Hume we have tended to interpret them in terms of consistent covariation. Hume’s argument has in fact recently been embraced by arch-skeptic Paul Edwards (1996, chap. 17) in support of his “brain-dependence” thesis—the claim that brain processes unilaterally generate conscious mental experience. But surely if causality can work in that direction, it might in principle work in the other as well (Broad, 1925/1960).

The other common argument against dualism appeals to energy conservation laws and their supposed violation by mental causation. As noted in Chapter 2 this was especially popular in the 19th century, the heyday of classical physics, but it is also implicit in many modern discussions and resurfaces explicitly in Dennett (1991). However, Broad (1925/1960, pp. 103109) had already shown that even in the context of classical physics, which Dennett mistakenly describes as “standard” physics, such arguments are inconclusive.

Even when the issues are framed in conventional physicalist terms, therefore, the main traditional arguments against interactive dualism appear to us less than compelling. Furthermore, and more fundamentally, it is no longer scientifically appropriate even to frame the issues in this way. Although a principle of causal closure of the physical world as classically conceived is assumed as the starting point of practically all contemporary scientific and philosophic discussions of mind-brain issues, it is hardly self-evident that this principle applies without restriction to a world that also contains minds. It assumes precisely what we are challenging, that classical physicalism is correct and complete, and can fully explain both brains and minds. But that classical conception of the physical world has long since been shattered by developments within physics itself, particularly by the advent of quantum theory in the early years of the 20th century.24

Among the small but growing number of systematic attempts to understand the implications of these developments for mind-brain theory, we regard as especially promising, and will summarize here, the work of quantum physicist Henry Stapp. There are several reasons for this choice. First, unlike many more popular writers Stapp knows the physics inside out. Second, he is consistently conservative and orthodox in his use of quantum theory, staying as close as possible to its empirically proven foundations and postulating no exotic quantum states or processes. Third, he is serious about establishing connections with mainline psychology and neuroscience. Finally, he has provided useful comments on a variety of related quantum-theoretic proposals (including those of Bohm, Eccles, and Penrose and Hameroff), which tend in broadly similar directions but are less satisfactory on various technical grounds (Stapp, 2005a, 2005b, in press a, in press b).

Few working psychologists and neuroscientists, let alone the public at large, have any conception of the fundamental significance of quantum theory. Classical concepts and approximations are often sufficient to support the concerns of the special physical sciences, and quantum mechanics is scarcely mentioned in the context of general education even at the college level. Yet it cannot be emphasized too strongly that the classical physics consensus that underwrites practically everything now going on in psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy of mind has in fact been completely undermined by this tectonic shift in the foundations of physics.

This is one of Stapp’s main points. He describes vividly how the founders of quantum mechanics discovered, to their extreme discomfiture, that the fundamental ideas of classical physics were not just limited but wrong, leading repeatedly to clear predictions that were falsified by experiment. The theory they were driven to in response, quantum theory, is a more fundamental and better physical theory that explains everything explainable in classical terms, and a vast number of additional things as well, often to extraordinary levels of accuracy. No experimental outcome predicted by it has ever been falsified.

Furthermore, it is crucial to appreciate that human consciousness, which had deliberately been excluded from the classical physics of the three preceding centuries, plays an essential role in this improved physical theory. Orthodox quantum theory is intrinsically a psychophysical theory, “a weaving of psychologically described realities into the framework of mathematical physics” (Stapp, 2005a). “The founders of quantum mechanics made the revolutionary move of bringing conscious human experiences into the basic physical theory in a fundamental way. In the words of Niels Bohr the key innovation was to recognize that ‘in the great drama of existence we ourselves are both actors and spectators’“ (Stapp, 2005a).25

Quantum theory also is necessarily relevant to brain science, for according to the principles of contemporary physics it must be used to explain the behaviors of all macroscopic systems that depend sensitively on the behavior of their atomic constituents, and brains are certainly systems of this kind.26 Stapp himself has identified and carefully analyzed one particular element of brain dynamics to which quantum theory certainly applies. This is the process of exocytosis, in which neurotransmitter molecules are released into the synaptic cleft. The release is triggered by arrival of calcium ions at critical sites in the transmitter storage areas, the vesicles. But as these small ions pass through their membrane channels (diameter circa 1 nanometer) their positions become nearly fixed; hence, by Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation, what happens next must be represented as a cloud of possible trajectories in the vicinity of the vesicle. This injection of a true quantum uncertainty—that is, an uncertainty involving more than incomplete knowledge of classically conceived details—goes on constantly at every one of the trillions of active synapses in the waking human brain, and this by itself is sufficient to establish that the brain is subject to quantum principles. This necessary entry of quantum uncertainties is also consistent with the findings of dynamic system theorists, who emphasize that in the waking state the brain operates continually on the edge of instability, with small changes in input potentially leading to large changes in overall behavior.27

Unfortunately, most brain researchers have not yet recognized the relevance of quantum-theoretic considerations to their science. A few others have considered the possibility but dismissed it out of hand for wholly inadequate reasons. For example, E. Roy John (2001) asserts that: “There is no evidence that quantum mechanical processes can apply to the slow processes which transpire in the brain in times on the order of milliseconds and involve many cubic centimeters of cells at body temperature” (p. 200). These statements are simply incorrect, as Stapp (2005a) explains. Body temperature has a negative bearing only on proposals which, unlike his own, postulate creation and maintenance of large-scale quantum coherence or other exotic physical states under the normal conditions of brain operation. Stapp’s proposal, moreover, is entirely consistent with the observed spatial and temporal scales of brain activity in relation to experience and behavior. Most fundamentally, in light of the demonstration that the behavior of low-level brain constituents is necessarily saturated with quantum effects, combined with the revolution that has occurred at the foundations of physics, the burden of proof here falls upon those who deny, not those who affirm, the relevance of quantum theory to brain science.

Stapp further argues that of the various formulations of quantum theory the one that most naturally applies to neuroscience, and indeed must be applied in that setting, is that of mathematician John von Neumann (1932/1955). The basic reason for this is straightforward: In the course of developing his rigorous formalization of quantum mechanics, von Neumann (1932/1955, chap. 6) proved that the separation originally introduced by the founders of quantum theory between a very small observed physical system described in mathematical language and an observing system described in empirical/phenomenal terms can be progressively shifted in such a way that the physical, mathematically described part ultimately includes the entire body and brain of an observing human agent, while the empirical/phenomenal part becomes that agent’s stream of conscious experience. In this restructured framework, identified by Wigner as the “orthodox” interpretation of quantum mechanics, the operations of the complete mind-brain system necessarily involve more than the deterministic, locally-acting, bottom-up mechanical processes described by classical physics. There continue to be bottom-up and locally-acting mechanical processes (which von Neumann calls Process 2), but these now take the form prescribed by quantum-mechanical generalizations of the laws of classical mechanics and incorporate all of the uncertainties entailed by the quantum principles. Operating alone, Process 2 would rapidly generate a vast proliferation of possible brain states, simultaneously existing in a state of “potentiality.” What actually happens, according to the quantum principles, is determined at least in part by a second process (Process 1) of fundamentally different character, which von Neumann (1932/1955) himself specifically characterized as arising from, or leading into, the human mind, “the intellectual inner life of the individual” (p. 418). These influences are entirely free, in the sense of not being determined by anything in the physics itself. Consciousness itself, in short, is needed to complete the quantum dynamics.

In Stapp’s minimal and physically justified elaboration of this basic scheme, the conscious mental activity of the observer is portrayed as operating top-down, and in an inherently non-local manner, to select or enforce large-scale, quasi-stable patterns of oscillatory brain activity from the multitude of possible patterns generated by Process 2. Note that these sorts of global activity patterns, expected in light of Stapp’s physics-based theory, correspond in a natural way to neural correlates of mental activity, as conventionally conceived.

For fuller explanations of all aspects of the theory, interested readers should consult the original sources. The net effect of these quantum-theoretic developments, we emphasize, is to bring consciousness back into both physical science and brain theory at the foundational level. As Stapp (2004a) remarks, his model “makes consciousness causally effective, yet it is compatible with all known laws of physics, including the law of conservation of energy” (p. 23). This totally deflates the main arguments, summarized above, that have routinely been advanced against interactive dualism. Indeed, far from ruling out dualism, as alleged by Dennett (1991) and numerous others, “Contemporary physical theory allows, and in its orthodox von Neumann form entails, an interactive dualism” (Stapp, 2005a, italics added).

Stapp’s theory as described so far remains abstract and mathematical, grounded most securely at the physics end. Certainly a great deal remains to be done to flesh it out in psychological and neuroscientific detail, particularly on the perceptual/cognitive (versus motor) side. Nevertheless, Stapp himself has already identified a variety of important psychological phenomena that he thinks his model can successfully explain, and in a manner uniquely consistent with these basic-physics considerations. The key factor here is the ability of Process 1 to hold a conscious mental intention in place despite the strong disruptive tendencies inherent in the mechanical Process 2. This is accomplished, in accordance with a well-studied physical phenomenon known as the quantum Zeno effect, by allowing the relevant Process 1 “intentions” or “permissions” to be issued repeatedly, as needed, but only up to some maximum possible rate. Stapp correctly points out the striking consistency between this picture and William James’s vivid phenomenological descriptions of attention as the essential phenomenon of will. The model also potentially explains in a natural way certain other characteristic features of conscious experience, such as the attentional “bottleneck” of Pashler (1998) and the properties of the “global workspace” as conceived by many contemporary brain theorists—broadly, the fact that a serial, integrated, and very limited stream of consciousness somehow emerges in association with a nervous system that is distributed, massively parallel, and of huge capacity (Baars, 1993). Top-down effects of the sort emphasized in Chapter 1 also fall directly and naturally out of such a model: “Quantum theory, unlike classical physics, can yield mathematically specified top-down effects of mind on brain that are not determined by the bottom-up local-deterministic process” (Stapp, 2005a).28 For examples of such top-down effects Stapp mainly relies upon recent clinical research on “self-directed neuroplasticity,” in which psychiatric patients are taught to modify, voluntarily, their maladaptive psychological (and neurophysiological) responses to emotionally challenging stimuli (J. Schwartz, Stapp, & Beauregard, 2003, 2005). Additional relevant studies would presumably include those showing that by voluntarily altering their perceptual interpretation of an ambiguous visual stimulus, subjects can systematically alter patterns of brain activity even as “early” as primary visual cortex (e.g., Kamitani & Tong, 2005).

We are sympathetic to these empirical arguments, but we doubt whether many psychologists and neuroscientists will find them compelling in themselves. Up to this point Stapp’s empirical case for his interactive-dualist model appears to us to suffer essentially the same liabilities as the evidence marshaled by Popper and Eccles (1977) in support of theirs. That is, his interpretations may well be correct, but none of the empirical phenomena he has adduced so far are clearly or decisively beyond the reach of more conventional types of explanation. In particular, the neurophysiological global workspace models of people such as Damasio, Dehaene, Edelman, Llinás, and others are as relentlessly conventional and classical as anything else in mainstream cognitive neuroscience; adherents of such models would certainly take the view that at least in principle they can explain all top-down effects, including the results on self-directed neuroplasticity, in terms of the dense reciprocal connections that are known to link cortical elements of the global workspace directly or indirectly to all other parts of the brain.

The situation changes, however, when Stapp’s theoretical model is combined with the kinds of “rogue” phenomena catalogued in the present book. We must first acknowledge that in making this move we are going beyond anything Stapp himself has yet suggested or embraced in his published work. He does not explicitly characterize the relationship he conceives as holding between the source of Process 1 events, the conscious mind of the individual, and the bodily processes with which it interacts, and it is not clear to what degree he himself regards them as actually or potentially separable. Nevertheless, we see no objection in principle to extending his basic model in this way, provided that the extension is empirically justified.

A natural starting point is provided by the phenomena of extreme psychophysical influence, such as geometric blisters and skin-writing, that we have shown cannot be produced directly by mechanisms under the control of the brain and nervous system (Chapter 3). Process 1 is inherently non-local, and therefore it can plausibly be imagined as enabling control of events in the skin that lie beyond the reach of mechanisms known to conventional present-day neuroscience. In this case the relevant events would also be quantum-level events of the same type as those Stapp has already shown are subject to quantum effects and fundamental to CNS dynamics—namely, that is, passage of calcium and other small ions through their membrane channels, resulting in a spatially patterned local release of inflammatory or vasoactive substances from structures in the skin and its vasculature. Learning to do this could be viewed as analogous, perhaps, to the situation in early development, which Stapp portrays as consisting in substantial part of the child’s gradually learning how to bring mental events or intentions into proper correspondence with environmental events by selecting the appropriate large-scale patterns of brain activity. Analogous special situations can perhaps also be identified in adult life, as for example in the conscious use of feedback signals to develop exquisitely detailed voluntary control of single motor units (Basmajian, 1977). It is interesting in this regard, and consistent with Stapp’s general outlook, that rare phenomena such as the formation of hypnotic blisters of specific geometric shape seem to occur mainly under conditions of extreme attention to, or preoccupation with, the relevant psychological material. The same sort of explanation might extend naturally to other phenomena of extreme psychophysical influence discussed in Chapters 3 and 8, including stigmata and allied phenomena, transitional phenomena such as the “maternal impression” cases, and perhaps even PK-type events occurring further outside one’s own body.29 We will give additional examples as we proceed.

To summarize the argument so far: Although many important issues clearly remain to be resolved, Stapp and his quantum-theoretic allies have already successfully undermined the basic-science foundations of present-day materialist-monist psychology and neuroscience. In so doing they also have opened a path toward alternative mind-brain theories of dualist-inter-actionist character that are more consistent both with fundamental science and with everyday experience, and that have the potential to explain at least some of the critical empirical phenomena catalogued in this book. Surely these are enormous theoretical virtues. There seems to be no insuperable obstacle to moving further in this direction, and we will now attempt to do so.

The basic pathway for reconciling the Myers/James filter theory with neuroscience seems clear enough in principle: Brain processes somehow shape the manner in which the associated psychic entity variably manifests its intrinsic properties and capabilities in the form of our ordinary or “supraliminal” conscious mental life. The “permeability” of the “membrane” that Myers conceptualized in psychological terms as modulating supraliminal expression of the Subliminal Self would thus have its neurophysiological counterpart in some aspect or aspects of brain activity. Effects of evolution, development, fatigue, fasting, psychedelics, meditation, thumps on the head, electrical brain stimulation, and the like all seem potentially inter-pretable in such terms.30 But the broad and abstract justification deriving from James’s (1898/1900) original argument (that such correlations can be interpreted in terms of permission or transmission rather than production theories) is not sufficient for our present purposes. We want now to get at least in outline a more detailed positive characterization of how such a mind-brain system might normally operate, and try to reconcile that with a broad range of existing neuroscientific data. The ultimate goal would be to explain in a quite specific way, for example, why it is that conscious experience of such-and-such types should be correlated with the patterns of brain activation revealed by functional neuroimaging studies, and why specific types of brain injury produce the kinds of alterations of mental functioning that they do. The following pages suggest possible elements of such a reconciliation.

We will start by rejecting the extreme localizationism characteristic of much recent research and theory in cognitive neuroscience. Functional neuroimaging and neuropsychological studies are commonly regarded, especially by cognitive psychologists, as providing conclusive and unqualified support for the view that the mind is entirely “modular” in its constitution and generated by corresponding structures and processes in the nervous system. The brain itself is typically conceived by such persons as a functionally complete system of “organs of computation” developed over the course of biological evolution for performance of particular, highly specialized, computational tasks. The postulated organs or modules thus represent the neurophysiological implementation of some cognitive model or models of the box-and-arrow variety, where the boxes represent supposed cognitive components and the arrows represent relations among them, directions of “information flow,” and the like (J. Fodor, 1983; Pinker, 1997; see Chapter 1). It is further presumed that brain activities portrayed in the model give rise to, or in some sense are, the associated mental activities and experiences.

The confidence that many scientists apparently have in such a picture, however, is quite unwarranted: In the first place, James’s (1898/1900) original argument does show that even if the correlations between brain activity and mental activity were as detailed, clear, and compelling as many people imagine them to be, that would not of itself be sufficient to establish the production model as against a permission or transmission model. Furthermore, things are in fact anything but that clear, and they become less so as we move toward the more central attributes of the mind.

The widely cited views of J. Fodor (1983) concerning “modularity” are much more subtle than most of those who casually cite him realize. Fodor himself attributed modularity (as defined by most or all of nine specific criteria) only to the hierarchically organized and relatively hardwired perceptual (and presumably motor) systems, and he in fact specifically denied that the central domains of the mental have these characteristics. For these more crucial general-purpose or “horizontal” capacities, such as memory, thinking, and imagination, the association with brain activity seemed to Fodor himself relatively global and nonspecific. Furthermore, in his judgment the failure of cognitive science to deal adequately with these capacities over decades of work had been “pretty nearly absolute” (p. 126)—indeed, so much so that he gloomily concluded: “The ghost has been pushed further back into the machine, but it has not been exorcised” (p. 127). Hardcore adherents of the CTM have of course berated Fodor for not attributing modularity to the mind itself (see, e.g., Cain, 2002, pp. 194–208), but his own more recent statements have become if anything even stronger. For example, in Fodor (2001) he explicitly repudiates the CTM in both its classical/symbolic and connectionist forms, and declares in conclusion: “So far, what our cognitive science has found out about the mind is mostly that we don’t know how it works” (p. 100).

Fodor’s original characterization remains largely applicable today, despite two further decades of work supported by the advent of the new functional neuroimaging technologies. In cognitive neuroscience generally and in functional neuroimaging studies in particular, the modularity doctrine has held up best with regard to early-stage sensory functions and the like, and relatively poorly with regard to the mind proper. This pessimistic view of the situation is argued forcefully in an important critical book by psychologist William Uttal (2001), which should be required reading for anyone interested in these issues.31 Most of the mind-imaging industry, Uttal argues, consists of attempts to correlate poorly defined psychological constructs with poorly defined and indirect measures of neural activity. On the psychological side, for example, there is theoretical chaos. Many workers have sought to identify “components” of the mind, supposedly distinct cognitive functions potentially identifiable with particular brain regions or structures. However, there is little or no evidence of progress toward agreement as to how many such components exist or what they do. The numbers of components proposed by different investigators mainly reflect their personal interests, industriousness, methodological commitments, and so on, and have ranged from a few to literally hundreds. Both Uttal (2001) and Pols (1998) argue for the contrasting view, which we share, that mind proper has a fundamentally unitary character underlying the diversity of its appearances as mind-in-action. That is, existing taxonomies of supposed mental “components” mainly reify aspects or properties of the mind that are brought into action under particular task conditions or circumstances.32

Things are hardly better on the neurophysiological side, despite the sophistication and elegance of the new functional neuroimaging technologies. The dramatic and modular-looking “brain activation” pictures now routinely displayed in fMRI/PET imaging articles in our journals and news media are often seriously misleading. The brain does not neatly decompose either anatomically or functionally, especially at the cortical level, into well-delineated structures or regions that are identifiable with specific components of mind and whose contributions to cognitive performances can be inserted or removed without influence on the rest of the system. The appearances of modularity in these images in fact result to a considerable and insufficiently appreciated degree from the complex processes involved in image acquisition and analysis itself.

Measuring brain “activation” is not a simple or standardized process like reading a meter on a physical instrument or performing routine assays of blood chemistry. The intrinsic resolution of the imaging hardware is compromised by preliminary data-conditioning operations such as spatial and temporal smoothing or filtering, and there are deep statistical issues, with no fully satisfactory solutions, related to control of Type 1 and Type 2 errors (false positives and false negatives) in final images that may still contain hundreds or even thousands of correlated elements. Small variations in a long sequence of analytical decisions can result in strikingly different-looking final maps, each portraying well-demarcated regions that ostensibly contain all the physiologically “significant” activation, from the same raw image data. Attempts to overcome the high variability of anatomical and functional organization across subjects by mapping their individual data onto standardized brains or coordinate systems can result in spurious “localizations” existing in none of them. The mechanisms of neurovascular coupling that underlie the measured responses are extremely complex and only partly understood, involve multiple layers of interdependent mechanism operating on different spatial and temporal scales, and may differ in detail from region to region and even across layers of the cortex. The measured responses themselves are spatially and temporally imprecise, relate only indirectly to the neural activity of primary interest, and correlate well only in limiting cases with more direct measures of neuroelectrical activity such as EEG and MEG (Huettell et al., 2004; Nunez & Silberstein, 2000; Wikswo et al., 1993). PET and fMRI also have little capacity at present to distinguish between excitatory and inhibitory neural activity within a given brain area or to track the rapidly changing patterns of functional interaction between areas. As pointed out in Chapter 4, the widely-used “subtraction” methodology (Kosslyn, 1994; Posner & Raichle, 1994) is both logically unsound and neurophysiologically implausible, and “double-dissociation” imaging studies suffer from logical problems similar to those previously identified in the context of neuropsychological investigations of the effects of brain injury (Shallice, 1988). Replicability of imaging results is also far lower than commonly assumed, and not only between but also within subjects. Many of these concerns, we must add, apply even in the realm of early-stage sensory processes, where the localizationist picture is most nearly correct.

Despite the great promise of the new functional neuroimaging techniques, we are still on a steep learning curve and a long way from having them under full control. Meanwhile, the overall state of evidence supporting localizationist views of the mind is far less clear and compelling than typical journal articles and textbook accounts suggest. Chapter 4, for example, demonstrated in some detail that this generalization holds even in relation to the representation of linguistic functions, historically the primary inspiration for such views. Furthermore, what evidence remains for modularity often can be accounted for equally well by distributed network models that are potentially consistent with our more “global” view of mind-brain interaction (Farah, 1994; Plaut & Farah, 1990; Van Orden, Jansen op de Haar, & Bosman, 1997). Some additional imaging findings also seem conspicuously more consistent with such a view—for example, recent findings on binocular rivalry, switching of response patterns to ambiguous figures such as the Necker cube, and the work on self-directed neuroplasticity. The key feature common to these is that massive changes occur in the overall patterns of brain response to an unchanging stimulus, changes that reflect the subject’s altered perception or judgment.

Neurophysiological studies of the consequences of brain injury point, we think, in similar directions. It is certainly true that deficits resulting from similar injuries tend to be more alike, and in characteristic ways, than deficits resulting from very dissimilar ones, but this generalization again holds best for injuries to relatively peripheral parts of the sensory and motor systems. Although the whole subject is clouded by difficulties related to precise specification of the brain injuries that have actually occurred, together with their local and distant sequelae in space and time, the higher mental functions seem rarely if ever to be totally destroyed (short, that is, of death or permanent vegetative states), and there is enormous and largely unexplained variability both between and within individuals who have suffered serious injuries of any particular type. Indeed, as indicated in Chapter 4, in the relatively few cases in which the overall condition of such persons has been investigated or reported in adequate depth, it is hard not to be impressed by the degree to which the core of self and mind can sometimes be preserved, even in combination with catastrophic brain injuries including separation of the hemispheres (H. Gardner, 1976).33

In sum, far from supporting the idea that cognition is entirely and extremely modular in its organization, with patterns of brain activity directly reflecting that modularity, modern neuroimaging and neuropsychological studies have instead provided evidence that the association between conscious, effortful mental activity and brain activity is more global in character. The broad consensus that has recently emerged around the family of neurophysiological “global workspace” theories in part reflects an increasing recognition that this is the case.

The anatomical makeup of the global workspace varies to some extent dynamically, in accord with the demands imposed by ongoing activity, but it is noteworthy that by all accounts it invariably includes areas such as frontal cortex and posterior parietal cortex whose total volume has greatly increased in the course of mammalian evolution—that is, areas of “uncommitted,” “association,” or “intrinsic” cortex above and beyond those specifically dedicated to the more modular and hard-wired pathways and mechanisms associated with more peripheral parts of the sensory and motor systems. The functional architecture of this tissue is substantially uniform, with the same cell types, patterns of microconnectivity, neurotransmit-ter/receptor mechanisms, and columnar organization repeated everywhere (Edelman & Mountcastle, 1982). It seems clear that the normal supraliminal expression of mind proper depends strongly, in a manner like that suggested by global workspace theories, on the total amount and functional status of this more general-purpose tissue. General intelligence, for example, has long been known to correlate modestly (around .4) with overall brain size, and recent work has shown this relationship to be driven primarily by the volume of areas belonging to the global workspace, especially frontal cortex (Haier et al., 2004). In this respect, global workspace theories in fact match up rather well with the views of Myers and Bergson, who viewed the brain as predominantly a sensorimotor device, the “organ of attention to life,” an instrument adapted by evolution to enable the mind to gain information about, and to act upon, the everyday physical environment. Mainstream global-workspace theorists themselves of course invariably accept the more fundamental orthodox conception that the underlying brain activity itself, whatever its form, produces or in some sense is the corresponding mental activity. Rejection of that deeper view, however, we regard as necessitated by the other lines of evidence marshaled earlier in this book.

We think this modified-holist view of mind-brain relations is substantially correct.34 Before taking it further in a dualist-interactionist direction, however, we must first deal with another possible conceptual obstacle. At the time of the Principles William James (1890b) was very sympathetic to pictures of this general sort. In describing the generic dualist-interactionist or “soul” theory, the sort of view unhesitatingly endorsed both by virtually all ordinary persons and by the scholastic philosophers, he said:

If there be such entities… they may possibly be affected by the manifold occurrences that go on in the nervous centers. To the state of the entire brain at a given moment they may respond by inward modifications of their own. These changes of state may be pulses of consciousness, cognitive of objects few or many, simple or complex…. I confess, therefore, that to posit a soul influenced in some mysterious way by the brain-states and responding to them by conscious affections of its own, seems to me the line of least logical resistance, so far as we have yet attained, (vol. 1, p. 181)

Despite the appeal that such a theory clearly held for him, James declined to accept it, offering instead his famous doctrine of the stream of consciousness, according to which the only thinker that psychology needed to recognize became the thought itself. Only much later did James give full expression to the logical scruple that had prevented him from endorsing dualism, a difficulty whose seriousness is underscored by the fact that George Mandler (1978) made it the centerpiece of his hostile commentary on the dualism of Popper and Eccles (1977). Here is James’s (1909/1971) statement:

It is not for idle or fantastical reasons that the notion of the substantial soul, so freely used by common men and the more popular philosophies, has fallen upon such evil days, and has no prestige in the eyes of critical thinkers. It only shares the fate of other unrepresentable substances and principles. They are without exception all so barren that to sincere inquirers they appear as little more than names masquerading—Wo die Begriffe fehlen da stellt ein Wort zur rechten Zeit sick ein. You see no deeper into the fact that a hundred sensations get compounded or known together by thinking that a “soul” does the compounding than you see into a man’s living eighty years by thinking of him as an octogenarian, or into our having five fingers by calling us pentadactyls. Souls have worn out both themselves and their welcome, that is the plain truth. Philosophy ought to get the manifolds of experience unified on principles less empty. Like the word “cause,” the word “soul” is but a theoretic stopgap—it marks a place and claims it for a future explanation to occupy, (p. 221)

The problem is essentially that in taking a dualistic-interactionist position on the mind we may seem simply to be giving up, in effect moving things that we might have hoped to explain in terms of brain processes and the like into an inaccessible inner realm. We do not accept this objection, however: In the first place, it seems to us clear that the conventional physicalist approaches themselves are not adequate to the task, and that the richness of the conscious human mind simply cannot be explained by homunculus-free computational models or by classical mechanical brain-processes operating alone. Like McDougall (1911/1961, p. 362), who specifically rebuked James for giving up the idea of a psychic being or soul, we think that psychology must postulate minds or psyches to explain some of its most significant mental and behavioral phenomena (including “rogue” phenomena of the sorts catalogued in this book), just as physics postulates unobservable entities and processes to help explain its observable phenomena. The work of Henry Stapp and allied quantum theorists provides strong additional warrant for this attitude (and see also Braude, 2003, chap. 9).

The picture we are moving to is thus that the main dispositional properties or capabilities of the mind (J. Fodor, 1983) reside in the associated psychic entity, which is at least in part outside the brain as conventionally conceived. We normally experience these capabilities as they express themselves in conjunction with our organism, in a manner determined at least in part by its ongoing states and processes, as suggested above and discussed in greater detail below. The capabilities in question specifically include memory, thinking, and the cosmogonic imagination or “virtual-reality” system. More elaborate inventories of the attributes of mind have been presented by McDougall (1911/1961), Broad (1925/1960,1962), Stevenson (1981), and Pols (1998), along with a half-dozen or so of the psychologists and neuroscientists canvassed by Uttal (2001). Pols (1998), for example, building upon the inventory given by Descartes in book II of the Meditations, says:

Here, then, is a list of the mind’s functions, not perhaps as comprehensive as it could be, but more comprehensive than most such lists; mind knows, makes (that is, forms, produces, creates), understands, thinks, conceives, perceives, remembers, anticipates, believes, doubts, attends, intends, affirms, denies, wills, refuses, imagines, values, judges, and feels, (p. 98)

Pols emphasizes that these attributes, though distinguishable, are overlapping and interconnected rather than discrete or separable, and can be viewed for the most part as modes of operation of a more pervasive conscious unity. He is close to McDougall (1911/1961) in this, though much more detailed.

The normal mind-brain relationship is certainly one of peculiar mutual dependence and intimacy. That was very clear to Descartes himself: “Nature… teaches me by these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst, etc., that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am very closely united to it, and so to speak so intermingled with it that I seem to compose with it one whole” (Haldane & Ross, 1931, vol. 1, p. 192). This intimacy unfortunately disappeared from many later dualistic accounts including in particular that of Eccles, who often speaks in terms of a completely disembodied “self-conscious mind” that stands apart from and inspects or influences the activity of cortical columns, rather like an immaterial piano-player playing the keys of the bodily piano. That sort of picture is clearly no good, because except by way of very indirect technical arrangements we normally have no conscious contact whatsoever with low-level physiological events occurring in our brains. Eccles’s picture also seems inconsistent with many neuropsychological phenomena such as the confusion that typically accompanies hemineglect due to parietal-lobe injuries (Stapp, 2004a, p. 167).

Problems of this sort can probably be circumvented, however. Gauld (1968) points out that a person can be conceived as relating to his brain in more intimate fashion, perhaps in a manner somewhat analogous to that of a parasite to its host, and that such a picture could potentially accommodate many relevant facts of neuropsychology: “Malfunctioning of a host may cause malfunctioning of a parasite, and vice-versa; none the less, malfunctioning host and malfunctioning parasite might regain their health if they were separated. Similarly, could a person disengage himself from his damaged brain, he might once more function properly” (at least temporarily, we might add) (p. 348). Something very much like the latter in fact appears to happen in the case of NDEs occurring under conditions of cardiac arrest or general anesthesia (Chapter 6). Philosopher C. D. Broad (1925/1960, 1962) repeatedly invoked the somewhat similar metaphor of a chemical compound, which in some respects seems slightly better: In the formation of table salt from sodium and chlorine, for example, a unique entity, something distinctly new, emerges. The components may also give up something in forming the compound, but they retain their separate identities and the potential to revert to their previous dissociated state. That is, there is also a dynamic aspect, with the components able to exist either conjoined or apart, and a sort of “energy hump” in between so that they tend to do one or the other depending on whatever conditions are relevant.

The very biological-looking critical-period aspect of cases of the reincarnation type (Stevenson, 1997, 2001), in which pre-existing memories of a previous life seem to get progressively overlaid by the subsequent learning of the new personality, appears consistent with such a metaphor. Here it looks as though what otherwise might normally be a fast and automatic forgetting process is somehow getting interrupted or delayed. The high incidence in such cases of violent death in the previous personality is especially intriguing in this regard.35 More generally, the notion that we begin neonatal life with a great deal of our personality already in place is broadly consistent with recent trends in developmental psychology, and Stevenson (2000) has pointed out a variety of ways in which the reincarnation hypothesis could potentially explain residual variability not otherwise explainable in terms of “normal” genetic or environmental factors.

Taking the “entry” metaphor seriously requires us to predict that corresponding phenomena of “withdrawal” may sometimes occur. For example, in persons suffering from progressive senile dementias it may sometimes happen that the mind of the dying person becomes disengaged sufficiently from the diseased brain, near the point of death, that relatively normal functioning briefly reappears (provided that suitable expressive capacities are still available). Phenomena of this type were already being reported by early observers such as de Boismont (1859), Flournoy (1903), and Rush (1812), as mentioned in Chapter 6, and recent interactions between several of the authors of the present book and medical personnel at several hospices and clinics strongly suggest that such phenomena are still occurring and potentially accessible to systematic study. Severe Alzheimer-type neuropathology has also sometimes been found in autopsies of persons exhibiting normal or even above-normal pre-mortem mental function (Davis, Schmitt, Wekstein, & Markesberg, 1999). Mental revivals in the context of severe neurodegenerative disease clearly merit further research, not least because materialist critics such as Edwards (1996, chap. 17) have emphatically denied that they can occur.

The everyday or supraliminal self as we normally experience it comes into conscious action in conjunction with the associated brain, whenever that brain achieves some threshold level of overall activation or “arousal” characterized by the predominance of intrinsic electrical rhythms of roughly 8–12 Hz and higher. All the major proposals regarding neurophysiological correlates of normal conscious experience point to the importance of synchronous (or at least coherent) neural oscillations in the gamma frequency range, oscillations that link and perhaps somehow “bind” the electrical activity of widely distributed regions of the brain. In the context of the non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist model this suggests that there is normally some sort of mutually constraining or resonant linkage between this large-scale brain activity and the associated psyche which limits, focuses, funnels, unifies, and stabilizes the supraliminal mental life, while whatever additional strata of mental or psychic organization may be present, per Myers and James, remain active behind the scenes. The stabilization or mutual-constraint aspect is revealed, perhaps, by the fact that in NDE cases involving life-threatening injury, the subject often initially remains at least briefly in a more or less normal state of consciousness before beginning to experience the more drastic alterations associated with a full-blown NDE (Chapter 6). One can also readily imagine, as explicitly suggested by James (1898/1900), that the normal ongoing interactions between mind and brain might result in modifications on both sides, although the details of how this could work again remain obscure.

The patterns of brain activity accompanying normal conscious experience also seem to have an overall functional architecture that in a meaningful sense is parallel to, or isomorphic with, the characteristic perceiver/ perceived or knower/known phenomenological structure of that experience. At least two proposals from recent mainstream literature in neurophysiology are consistent with this basic idea. Crick and Koch (2003) explicitly acknowledge this universal phenomenological property, which they call the “homuncular” structure of experience, and suggest that it probably reflects some large-scale feature of brain organization. They themselves think it may reflect the fact that the front of the brain, more involved in executive functions and the like, is “looking at” activity in the back of the brain, which contains the main sensory systems. This rough and metaphorical way of formulating the basic idea seems broadly consistent with most current consciousness theories of the global workspace type. A more elaborate and neu-rophysiologically justified model, however, flows from the specific variant of workspace theory deriving from Penfield (1975), Newman and Baars (1993), and especially Llinás et al. (1998), which emphasizes the role of the extended reticular activating system and the massive reciprocal connections linking the thalamus with the cerebral cortex. Llinás’s group has discovered a thalamocortical “scanning” rhythm, in the neighborhood of 40 Hz, which sweeps repeatedly across the cortex in a front-to-back direction (Joliot, Ribary, & Llinás, 1994). They interpret this as a process by which a thalamus-driven readout mechanism periodically interrogates the cortex and synthesizes or binds the various processes going on there into the momentary global state. Apart from the physiological evidence directly supporting it, this proposal, unlike that of Crick and Koch (2003), is also consistent with a large body of clinical evidence showing that small lesions in the upper brainstem and thalamus completely abolish ordinary consciousness itself, whereas cortical lesions, even large ones, typically abolish or alter only relatively specific elements of its phenomenological content.

The Llinás model also maps fairly well onto a sizeable body of data regarding “the psychological moment” (Stroud, 1955). In simple reaction-time experiments, for example, the within-subject distribution across trials of the time it takes to press a button in response to a flash or tone turns out not to be continuous, as initially expected, but to consist instead of multiple discrete peaks separated by intervals of a few tens of milliseconds (Dehaene, 1993). Another example is provided by the “wagon-wheel” illusion often seen in movies, in which the wheels of the stagecoach seem to turn erratically, or even in the wrong direction. This previously had been thought due entirely to “aliasing” effects associated with the varying relations between the rate of rotation of the wheel and the fixed presentation rate of the movie frames, but it turns out to occur even with wheel-like visual objects that rotate continuously under continuous illumination (Purves, Paydartar, & Andrews, 1996). The conclusion appears inescapable that there is an inherent discreteness in sensorimotor activity, corresponding in a striking way to James’s notion of “pulses of consciousness.” Note also that effects of this sort, variable between individuals and tasks, are inherent in Stapp’s model, inasmuch as Process 1 in itself imposes a task-dependent framing on the otherwise continuous evolution of Process 2.36

Even when the normal, ongoing adult engagement of mind and brain is in force (whatever that relationship amounts to in detail), the mind appears to retain at least a limited ability to operate more independently, and potentially in very different ways, when that engagement is altered or ruptured in various ways by changes in the functional status of the brain. The dramatic and rapid within-subject fluctuations in mental status often observed in brain-damaged patients (H. Gardner, 1976), for example, might reflect corresponding fluctuations in patients’ capacities to interact normally with their malfunctioning brains. Sleep and dreams also can clearly be thought about in this way—a kind of regulated quasi-periodic “stretching” or other modification of the normal linkage—and certainly the lack of satisfactory progress on these subjects despite a century or so of serious scientific effort provides motivation to try thinking about them in a new and different way. Slow-wave sleep, for example, involves significant modifications in the overall level and pattern of brain activity, modifications that partially mimic those produced by general anesthesia, and these non-REM sleep states are already known to be accompanied by fragmentary mental activity very different in character from that of ordinary dreams (Foulkes, 1962). Vivid REM-sleep dreaming itself, interestingly, has recently been shown in both imaging (A. R. Braun et al., 1998) and neuropsychological (Solms, 1997) studies to be associated with reduced activity in prefrontal and occipital cortex, consistent with Myers’s principle that the subliminal is liberated by the abeyance of the supraliminal and its associated forms of outwardly directed activity. Recently identified phenomena of “paradoxical function facilitation,” in which previously unrecognized skills or abilities emerge following brain injury (Kapur, 1996; B. L. Miller et al., 1998), may in some cases merit a similar interpretation.

The “dreams” that are sometimes reported as occurring in connection with general anesthesia itself also deserve more careful study than they have received to date, to characterize more precisely their phenomenological properties and physiological conditions of occurrence. For these to occur at all under conditions of deep general anesthesia would conflict—like the occurrence of NDEs (Chapter 6)—with current neuroscientific opinion regarding conditions necessary for conscious experience. They would be expected, however, from the Myers/James point of view, and especially in persons open to subliminal influence, such as persons of high “transliminality,” with thin or permeable “boundaries.” An observation consistent with this expectation is provided by Hejja and Galloon (1975), who showed that “dreaming” in conjunction with ketamine anesthesia occurred overwhelmingly among patients who also recalled dreaming at home. A full 50 of their reported ketamine dreams occurred among the 68 patients who also reported dreaming at home, while only two others were reported by an additional 82 patients who did not.

The NDE literature (Chapter 6) further indicates that the normal linkage can sometimes be so severely stretched or otherwise modified that the mental system spontaneously begins to operate in radically different ways. It seems especially significant in this regard that NDEs involving subjectively enhanced cognitive functioning tend to occur more commonly in persons who in fact are closer to death physiologically (Owens et al., 1990). But NDEs can also occur in persons who are continuously and fully conscious, as for example in mountain climbers during serious falls, and similar experiences also can arise following ingestion of various psychedelic agents, and in connection with transformative practices such as meditation, where their physiological accompaniments are surely very different and can more readily be studied in detail and across time (Chapter 8). The sheer diversity of circumstances under which similar kinds of experience can occur itself suggests that their common cause may involve some overall alteration of the normal mind-brain relationship, rather than engagement of specific neurophysiological final common pathways or mechanisms.

The strength of mind-brain coupling may also vary systematically between persons in ways that could be measured, and that might again shed light on the nature of the coupling itself. Successful trance mediums like Mrs. Piper, for example, might be viewed (and were viewed by Myers) as persons in whom the coupling is unusually “loose,” permitting the psyche to disengage partially or wholly from its customary entanglements and thus to provide temporary access for potential “communicators.”37 Unfortunately, practically nothing of significance is presently known about the great trance mediums (or for that matter about exceptional psi subjects of any other kind) in terms of relevant characteristics of physiological function, personality, or cognitive style.

Our basic functional picture of the normal waking situation, like that of most neuroscientists including Crick and Koch (2003) in their discussion of “zombie modes,” is that mind and consciousness get involved in ongoing activity only to the extent they need to, while things that are simple, or fully learned or overlearned, can run on more or less automatically via brain processes. Such a division of labor can readily be accommodated within the basic framework of Stapp’s model, because to the degree that the proliferation of possible brain states by Process 2 is directly constrained by interactions between the organism and its environment, the need for Process 1 contributions would be correspondingly reduced. Such a picture is consistent not only with everyday experiences such as driving a car while carrying on a conversation, but also with neuroimaging results showing that the numerous and widely distributed brain territories initially engaged by a complex task massively deactivate and contract as the task is progressively mastered (e.g., Haier et al., 1992; John, 1976). Consistent with our modi-fied-holist view, this looks more like changing degrees of engagement of one large, common structure than all-or-none selective engagement/disengagement of highly localized and specific computational “modules.” Similarly, human cortical neurons involved in working-memory tasks have recently been shown to produce gamma-band EEG activity under all the task conditions, but in amounts proportional to the overall memory “load” associated with each task (Howard et al., 2003). Another relevant observation involves electrical stimulation of the small thalamic regions that produce petit mal epileptic “absences”; Penfield (1975, pp. 37–43) interpreted this as reversibly disrupting the connection of mind to brain and releasing the brain as a kind of sensorimotor automaton to operate temporarily on its own, for example in playing the piano or driving a car (both poorly, in the absence of the normal conscious fine-tuning).

We have now said about as much as we need to, or at this point usefully can, in terms of justifying the non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist model and fleshing it out in neurophysiological terms. Although we have perhaps made some progress in this regard, it is only candid to acknowledge that we ourselves remain less than fully satisfied with this approach. The traditional dualist problems regarding mental causation and energy conservation seem to be overcome, but there remain further deep problems with no good solutions in sight. We still have no real understanding of the ultimate nature of the relationship between brain processes and mental activity, and certainly no solution of Chalmers’s “hard problem”—why conscious experiences with their specific qualitative characteristics should arise at all in connection with the associated patterns of brain activity. It is not clear which aspects of the “cognitive unconscious” go with the brain, which with the associated psyche, and how their respective contributions get coordinated. We have talked about mind-brain relations primarily in relation to the functioning of an adult human, presuming the existence of an associated psyche, but where do these psyches come from in the course of individual human development, or in the evolution of species? Where and how, exactly, does consciousness enter the picture? These are difficult problems, to say the least (and see Griffin, 1997, chap. 3, for related discussion). Finally, we have said practically nothing about further difficult problems having to do with the properties of that adult psyche itself. We conceive that the psyche or at least some part of it may be capable of operating in some fashion on its own, independent of the brain, but what could be the character or mode of subsistence of such an entity? Broad (1962, Epilogue), who discusses this problem in considerable depth, ultimately adopts the conventional scientific view (disputed by Braude, 2003, pp. 294–301) that any dispositional properties of a mind must be grounded in or explained by minute structure and processes in some sort of material substrate. From this viewpoint, post-mortem survival of human personality or consciousness would necessarily occur in conjunction with some sort of “subtle” physical body or bodies, perhaps of the types conceived by the wisdom traditions and summarized by Poortman (1954/1978). Although such a picture does not seem to be ruled out by our present knowledge of physics, and deserves further investigation, we suspect that a more fundamentally novel way of approaching the problems may in the end yield a better solution. We turn next to this.

Neutral-Monist Models

The key to moving in this more radical direction is to recognize that our entire discussion of non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist models has implicitly, and perhaps mistakenly, taken the classical “matter” side of the Cartesian bifurcation for granted. To recapitulate: The body conceived conventionally as a physiological machine has proven unable to account for all the properties of minds, and so we must try to find a different theory that can better account for the empirical data. In a first attempt to do so we proceeded in what probably seems the most natural and conservative direction, at least to most persons reared like ourselves in the intellectual tradition of Western reductionist science. Specifically, following the main lead suggested by James (1898/1900), we left the Cartesian body in place but re-introduced the psyche, conceived as a second and distinct type of existent (itself possibly at least in part physical in some extended sense) with which that body is somehow associated. This approach, however, gave rise to difficulties analogous to those of the traditional Cartesian causal dilemma. In particular, we have struggled with only limited success to understand how and why these two species of existents normally interact in the production of conscious mental life. We want now to take a different approach, by examining more closely the body side of the mind-body relation.

We have all grown accustomed to the idea that the phenomenological table that we see and touch is not the “real” table, as described by physics. In this case we have no difficulty accepting that ordinary perceptual experience is not a reliable guide to the ultimate nature of things. Yet it is extremely difficult if not impossible for most of us to adopt that same attitude with respect to the phenomenological solidity, the felt presence, of our own bodies. They seem just inescapably there, brute facts, existing on their own as classical Cartesian objects. It is this intuition, however, that we will now challenge.38

To begin, consider the character of what we experience in dreams. Those of us who dream vividly encounter a phenomenological world similar in many salient respects to the world we all experience in the waking state. We experience ourselves as embodied, and we move purposefully among other solid, three-dimensional objects, including at times other persons, that seem to exist independently of ourselves and that also behave for the most part in more or less customary ways. Both we and the persons we encounter seem to have both an “outside” and an “inside.” If we smash violently into something, we may appear to bleed, and it usually hurts. Those other persons act as though they have their own thoughts and motivations, and they sometimes tell us things that we ourselves do not consciously know. Yet all this vivid dream-world experience, so like what we experience in ordinary waking life, occurs in the near-total absence of corresponding sensory input (Globus, 1987).

The seeming reality of the dream of course evaporates, for most of us anyway, when we awaken in the ordinary way to the phenomenologically similar world presented in everyday experience. This world seems to most of us unquestionably real, existing “out there” and independently of ourselves. Yet as we saw in Chapter 8, great mystics of all traditions have reported entering states of consciousness relative to which that everyday reality itself proves evanescent in the same way as a dream. The material world given in everyday experience, they declare, is not what it seems. Matter as we customarily experience it does not exist, at least not in the way we naively believe it to exist.

In our attempt to develop the non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist model we relied heavily on a first major consequence of quantum theory, that it brings consciousness back into physics at the foundational level and in a causally effective manner. There is a second major consequence, however, no less profound but even less widely appreciated. It is this: There is no such thing as matter as classically conceived. Physics is not ultimately about an independently existing objective world of classically conceived material entities, but rather about our knowledge, and about relationships among experiences. Thus our ontology, our conception of the basic “stuff” of which the universe is composed, also must undergo fundamental revision. Stapp (2004a) summarizes the situation this way:

The physical world thus becomes an evolving structure of information, and of propensities for experiences to occur, rather than a mechanically evolving mindless material structure. The new conception essentially fulfills the age-old philosophical idea that nature should be made out of a kind of stuff that combines in an integrated and natural way certain mindlike and matter-like qualities, without being reduced to either classically conceived mind or classically conceived matter, (p. 268)

Before proceeding further in this direction we will briefly digress, for reasons that are both historically and conceptually significant. We are acutely aware that many scientifically minded readers, even among those who have stayed with us to this point, may have gagged at our emphasis on the word “ontology.” Ontology is a branch of metaphysics, and scientists tend to pride themselves on having nothing to do with such arcane matters. William James himself clearly shared that attitude at the time he was writing the Principles; in his preface and elsewhere he declares that the proper business of psychology as a natural science consists simply in ascertaining the correlations that ordinarily hold between states of mind and brain-states, and that to attempt to explain these correlations in terms of anything more fundamental would be to trespass into metaphysics. But Myers (1891c), in his remarkable review of the Principles, chided James for taking this narrow view, and for failing to recognize the degree to which more penetrating empirical investigations of the mind-brain connection might be able to shed light on its ultimate character. Undoubtedly influenced in considerable part by Myers, James (1892) by the time of his Briefer Course had already abandoned the position adopted in the Principles and concluded that there can in fact be no such thing as a metaphysics-free science of psychology:

When, then, we talk of “psychology as a natural science” we must not assume that we mean a sort of psychology that stands at last on solid ground. It means just the reverse: it means a psychology particularly fragile, and into which the waters of metaphysical criticism leak at every joint, a psychology all of whose elementary assumptions and data must be reconsidered in wider connections and translated into other terms, (pp. 467–468)

So far we have “only the hope of a science,” and its actual state of development requires us “to understand how great is the darkness in which we grope, and never to forget that the natural-science assumptions with which we started are provisional and revisable things” (James, 1892, p. 468). In his Presidential Address to the American Psychological Association in December 1894 James again stated flatly: “I have become convinced… that no conventional restrictions can keep metaphysical and so-called epistemological inquiries out of the psychology-books” (James, 1895/1978, p. 88; see also E. Taylor, 1996, chap. 7). The real issue, in short, is not whether we will have metaphysics, but whether we will have good metaphysics or bad.

This of course marks the point at which behavioristically oriented historians of psychology characteristically portray James as ceasing to be a psychologist and becoming instead a “mere” philosopher. But there can be no doubt that James himself did not see things this way. We have already shown (Chapter 8) that much of James’s later work, especially The Varieties of Religious Experience (1902/1958) and A Pluralistic Universe (1909/1971), can be understood in considerable part as direct applications of Myers’s model of the psyche to problems in religion and philosophy. What we have not yet emphasized, however, is that there is a further dimension of James’s later work that connects directly with the matters now before us.

Our account of the non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist model rested directly upon the formulation of “transmission” theory by James (1898/1900). Yet even at that early date James was already searching for a way to get beyond dualism. In a crucial footnote he remarks:

The philosophically instructed reader will notice that I have all along been placing myself at the ordinary dualistic point of view of natural science and of common sense. From this point of view mental facts like feelings are made of one kind of stuff or substance, physical facts of another. An absolute phenomenalism, not believing such a dualism to be ultimate, may possibly end by solving some of the problems that are insoluble when propounded in dualist terms, (pp. 50—51)

This brief statement encapsulates and foreshadows the doctrine of “radical empiricism” that James was systematically developing during the last years of his life. This involved far more than the methodological principle (which he also endorsed) that we must be willing to look at all relevant data in approaching any scientific problem. Rather, James was driving toward a comprehensive metaphysical system grounded wholly and directly in actual human experience, experience of all forms up to and including mystical experience (see Perry, 1935, vol. 2, Part 6).

James’s ambitious program remained unfinished at his death in 1910, but it was subsequently taken up and integrated with emerging developments in physics by the Anglo-American mathematician, philosopher of science, and metaphysician Alfred North Whitehead. It is no accident, in this light, that in his last book Whitehead (1938/1968, p. 2) identified James as one of the four greatest thinkers of the Western tradition, along with Plato, Aristotle, and Leibniz. But Whitehead also had a profound understanding of emerging developments in physics and clearly recognized their ontological implications. His work in fact represents the most systematic effort to date to elaborate a comprehensive metaphysical system specifically intended to be compatible both with the new basic science and with all available facts of human experience.39

Whitehead’s system is provisional, unfinished, open-ended, and vast in scope, but altogether naturalistic in spirit and character. It is far too complex and difficult to present here in any detail, but we can quickly summarize its central, driving ideas. The root cause of our present mind-brain difficulties, Whitehead argues, is the ontological bifurcation originally imposed on nature by Descartes and his 17th-century supernaturalist allies. Classical physics, as it evolved over subsequent centuries in the work of Galileo, Newton, Laplace, and their successors, dealt only with the “matter” side of this Cartesian ontology. But its core concept of lifeless mechanical matter has now proven to be a vicious abstraction, vitiated by what was left out at the very beginning. Modern physical theory invites us instead to conceive of nature as in some sense alive throughout, with even its lowest-level constituents having both exterior/objective and interior/subjective aspects. The fundamental stuff of the universe, on this view, is not lifeless bits of classically conceived matter moving in fields of force, but “occasions of experience.” These occasions, from the point of view of other such occasions, appear as “events.” But Whitehead’s analysis of events suggests that every event to some degree “feels” causes from the past, “imagines” possibilities for the future, and “makes decisions” as to what it will become.40 Thus the definiteness and particularity that distinguish each event from all others are precisely a result of its “mental pole,” however rudimentary.

Whitehead’s fundamental move is thus to re-situate mind in matter as the fundamental factor by which determinate events emerge out of a background of possibilities. The behavior of the lowest or most matter-like occasions is determined almost completely by efficient causes from the past; such an event is influenced by or “feels” its past but engages in an absolute minimum of “imagination” or “decision.” There is, however, a creative evolutionary drive inherent in nature which leads to the progressive elaboration, across time, of more complex events associated with correspondingly more complex, sophisticated, and self-determining experiential interiors. Events are interdependent, moreover, in ways more subtle and complex than those contemplated by Descartes and his modern successors. The classical conception of matter arose predominantly in association with the most recently evolved forms of perceptual experience, especially vision and hearing, but these are secondary or derivative acquisitions that do not fully disclose the nature of the ways in which events can potentially affect each other. They in fact conceal a profound continuity between ourselves and lower forms of organization in terms of more primitive forms of interrelatedness and experience which reflect a global interconnectedness that is fundamental to nature: “Any local agitation shakes the whole universe. The distant effects are minute, but they are there” (Whitehead, 1938/1968, p. 138).41 The fundamental concepts in this “organismic” view of nature are process, activity, transition, and change, all orchestrated in service of “creative advance.”42

It would carry us far beyond the purposes and scope of the present book to present or discuss Whitehead’s views here in greater depth. We certainly do not mean to endorse his views wholesale, but we do wish to record here our collective sense that he was moving in a direction that is both theoretically promising and fundamentally consistent with the ontological implications of quantum theory. The latter is perhaps especially surprising and impressive in that Whitehead apparently arrived at his ontological ideas mainly by generalizing from his own earlier work on relativity theory and foundational concepts of physics such as space, time, motion, and causality, rather than by way of quantum theory itself. He was certainly familiar with emerging developments in quantum theory, but he apparently saw these primarily as illustrating or confirming ideas that he had arrived at on his own and from a different direction (V. Lowe, 1951, p. 90). Many quantum physicists including Henry Stapp (2004b) apparently agree with this judgment, finding Whitehead’s general outlook intuitively appealing and at least potentially compatible with their understanding of the physics. There also appears to be growing interest among such physicists in exploring and deepening these connections, through a process of cross-fertilization and mutual adjustment in which Whitehead’s original philosophical system is being progressively “modernized” in light of continuing developments in physics, while serving as a fruitful source of suggestions toward rounding out the ontological side of quantum theory itself (Shimony, 1993; Eastman & Keeton, 2004).43

In addition to being deeply compatible with basic science, a Whitehead-like neutral-monist outlook seems to afford new possibilities for progress on substantive issues relevant to mind-brain relations. First, as argued in particular by Griffin (1997, chap. 3; 1998) one can readily appreciate at least in principle how a neutral-monist solution might overcome the unresolved problems—common to both materialism and dualism as traditionally conceived, and probably unresolvable in those terms—of accounting for the emergence of mind and consciousness in the course of biological evolution and individual human development. Griffin (1993, 1994, 1997, 1998, 2000) has also made serious and generally well-received efforts to accommodate the data of psychical research, including survival data, within his basically Whiteheadian framework.44 We ourselves can also glimpse at least in general terms how such a framework might ultimately provide viable explanations of allied phenomena such as NDEs occurring under conditions of general anesthesia and cardiac arrest (Chapter 6) and the various still-unexplained properties of human memory (Chapter 4).45

Whitehead’s original theory has problems of its own, however. Some of his most central technical notions and terms, such as “prehension” and “concrescence,” remain for us extremely difficult and obscure. The precise manner in which lower-grade “actual entities” combine to form higher-grade entities with new, emergent properties seems particularly in need of further explication, and the importance of this can readily be appreciated from a testy exchange between Searle and Chalmers recorded in Searle (1997). Chalmers (1996) had unwisely mused at length regarding the possible mental life of thermostats, but Searle ridiculed these “panpsychist” speculations on grounds that thermostats lack the kind of biological organization that he thinks we know to be necessary for any form of conscious experience. This kind of attempted reductio ad absurdum has been a common response to the views of Whitehead and the other neutral monists, but as emphasized especially by Griffin (1998, chap. 9) it ignores a long tradition, extending from Leibniz to Whitehead, Hartshorne, and Griffin himself, that attempts to distinguish systematically between mere “aggregates” (such as rocks and thermostats) and “compounds” (such as earthworms and ourselves) in terms of their respective levels and types of organization. Clearly, to the degree that these distinctions can be grounded in an adequate understanding of the process of composition, the Searle-type reductio can be circumvented. Previous philosophic attempts to accomplish this, however, including Griffin’s, seem to us mainly descriptive rather than explanatory.46

Even if the composition problem can be successfully resolved, further difficulties are already in sight. For example, it is not clear to us at present whether neutral monism is truly distinguishable from an interactive dualism of the sort sketched earlier. This is the central theme of Lovejoy’s (1930/1960) examination of the doctrines advanced by Russell and Whitehead, and Griffin’s descriptive term for his own position, “nondualist interactionism,” seems perilously close to an oxymoron. In addition, Whitehead’s theory as described so far is a purely bottom-up theory in which our normal, supraliminal consciousness emerges at the apex of a hierarchy of lesser integrations. This picture is similar to the monadic theories of McDougall and Balfour, and we have already argued that such theories deal poorly with the fully-developed phenomena of psychological automatism and secondary personality, as well as genius and mysticism (Chapters 5, 7, 8). More generally, they cannot easily accommodate any of the evidence assembled by Myers, James, and their colleagues for the existence in all or at least some of us of normally hidden levels of psychic organization characterized by increasing scope, precision, speed, and complexity of mental function. It appears possible in principle, however, to accommodate such phenomena, while remaining within the basic neutral-monist framework, by incorporating elements of a complementary top-down tradition (represented in the West by historical figures such as Plato, Plotinus, and the German idealists, and in the East by the higher schools of Hindu philosophy and the wisdom traditions) that sees consciousness itself as the fundamental reality in nature, flowing outward or downward to its most matter-like aspects, and then back up again in the course of cosmic evolution (Poortman, 1954/1978). Whitehead’s own system in its full development incorporates such ideas in a form having much in common with James’s vision of an unfinished pluralistic universe (see our Chapter 8). It is also worth mentioning, perhaps, that considerable sympathy for views of this general type has been expressed by theoretical physicists such as Schrödinger (1959, Epilogue), d’Espagnat (1976), and Haag (1996).

Within such a top-down neutral-monist framework, human personality would be pictured as a complex system made up of the same kind of “stuff” throughout. The system consists of a hierarchy of levels or strata of the types recognized in particular by Myers, James, and the wisdom traditions. Each level is characterized by its own form of psychophysical organization and has both interior and exterior aspects that allow it to participate in some form of experienced world appropriate to itself. The activities of these different strata are somehow interconnected, and coordinated in greater or lesser degree, by something like Myers’s Subliminal Self, or by a consciousness that somehow underlies or pervades the whole structure. The fundamental cleavage in nature suggested in particular by the survival evidence would on such a view be interpreted not ontologically, as the separation of an entire “psyche” from its associated “body,” but functionally, as a shift within that complex system, following dissolution of its outermost psychophysical shell, to a different mode of operation based on whatever levels remain. Such a picture would be theoretically attractive in that it incorporates both of the fundamental insights of quantum theory and overcomes the residual dualism of the non-Cartesian dualist-interactionist model, while also potentially accommodating all of the relevant empirical data. To what degree it is actually correct, and can be fleshed out in both empirical and theoretical detail, remains to be seen.

To recapitulate: Both Myers and James believed that the only way we can get consciousness out of a theory is to build it into the theory somewhere at the beginning.47 The neutral-monist options identified here—strictly bottom-up, strictly top-down, or possibly some higher-level integration of the two—seem to bracket the possible ways of doing so. Our own collective sympathies tend currently, but less than unanimously, toward the last of these somewhat dizzying abstractions, which clearly has a great deal in common with the views held by Myers and James. We will not attempt to develop them further or adjudicate among them at the present time, however, for to do so is the central goal of our ongoing Esalen discussions and the expected subject of our next book.

Meanwhile, what we think will ultimately prove most helpful in catalyzing further theoretical progress will be thoroughgoing application—determined and disciplined, but also sympathetic and flexible—of Western-style scientific imagination to the phenomenological realities revealed by the great contemplative traditions, both East and West. We need to chart more fully and accurately the natural history of these “higher” or “deeper” subliminal realms. How many meaningfully distinguishable states or levels of consciousness actually or potentially exist within us, with what properties and what relationships to each other? Under what sorts of conditions do they occur, and what sorts of consequences do they have? Can we harness the benefits of potentially useful states by developing improved means of facilitating their occurrence? Partial or preliminary answers to some of these questions may be obtainable through careful and scientifically informed comparative study of the existing literature of the wisdom traditions themselves, but what will contribute most in the long run, in our opinion, is intensified experimental and phenomenological investigation of altered states of consciousness of all types, whether spontaneously occurring or induced by meditation, psychedelics, hypnosis, or other means. Only in this way, if ever, will we finally get to the bottom of what James called “Myers’s problem.” There are many lifetimes’ worth of exciting and important science to be done here, work unlikely to be undertaken by persons immured in the current mainstream consensus.

Summary and Prospectus

For an enlarged scientific picture of human mind and personality to emerge, two things need to happen: First, it must be demonstrated that the currently dominant physicalist theories of mind-brain relations are inadequate in principle; and second, an alternative theory must be found that remedies these defects.

The present volume has sought mainly to address the first of these tasks, by assembling in one place large amounts of credible evidence for a wide variety of empirical phenomena that appear difficult or impossible to explain in conventional physicalist terms. We find this evidence cumulatively overwhelming, and expect to have persuaded many open-minded readers that this is the case. At the same time, we are also acutely aware that the continuing scientific resistance to many of these phenomena derives in large part from their apparent conflict with current physicalist orthodoxy. Nothing would do more to hasten their wider recognition and acceptance, we believe, than identification of an alternative theoretical outlook that is scientifically defensible and that would permit and perhaps ultimately even explain them. In this concluding chapter, therefore, we have attempted to show at least in a provisional way that such theoretical expansion appears possible.

Our theoretical reconnaissance proceeded at two primary levels. In the first half of the chapter we argued that the psychological theory advanced by Myers and developed further by James in his late period has been considerably strengthened by many related scientific findings of the subsequent century. We ourselves strongly suspect that they were already approaching a more or less correct overall picture of the structure of the human psyche, but at the very least they provided a useful working model which brings the entire range of relevant empirical phenomena into intelligible relationship within a coherent descriptive framework, and which suggests a variety of potentially fruitful directions for further research.

This theory was not disproven but simply displaced, forgotten—a casualty of the changes wrought in scientific psychology by the advent of behaviorism. Its near-total absence from contemporary discussions of consciousness seems to us the worst yet among many unfortunate examples of scientific amnesia (Draaisma, 2000; Harrington, 1987; Koch & Leary, 1985), and to help overcome this amnesia has been one of the central objectives of our book.

In the second half of the chapter we attempted to go further by showing in a provisional way that more comprehensive psychological theories of the Myers/James type are also potentially reconcilable with the relevant aspects of present-day science. In this first stage of an ongoing theoretical effort we have attempted only to sketch out the main directions in which further progress seems possible, and is urgently needed. Theories of the types indicated share several major advantages relative to those that currently dominate mainstream science and philosophy: In particular, they are more deeply compatible with leading-edge physical science itself; they appear potentially capable of explaining most and perhaps all of the “rogue” empirical phenomena catalogued in this book; and they ratify, rather than reject, our everyday experience of ourselves as purposeful, causally effective, conscious agents. We wish here to underscore this last point, because it brings out in perhaps the most dramatic and humanly relevant way the stark contrast between the sorts of theory we are advocating and those that dominate the current scene.

The self was absolutely central to the psychology of William James (Leary, 1990). In the Principles (1890b) he says: “The universal conscious fact is not ‘feelings and thoughts exist’ but T think’ and T feel’. No psychology… can question the existence of personal selves. The worst a psychology can do is so to interpret the nature of these selves as to rob them of their worth” (vol. 1, p. 226). The self is something the presence of which we can feel almost constantly at the innermost subjective pole of our experience. Its ultimate origins remain mysterious, and as we saw in Chapter 8 James himself traced them into the recesses of the subliminal consciousness, and even to the hypothesis of a World-Soul as the ultimate foundation and root of our individualized conscious selves. But however it arises, the self is the active element in the stream of consciousness, expressing the dispositional basis of our conscious mental life:

It is what welcomes or rejects. It presides over the perception of sensations, and by giving or withholding its assent it influences the movements they tend to arouse. It is the home of interest,—not the pleasant or the painful, nor even pleasure or pain as such, but that within us to which pleasure and pain, the pleasant and the painful, speak. It is the source of effort and attention, and the place from which appear to emanate the fiats of the will, (vol. 1, pp. 297–298)

This is essentially James’s answer to Hume, who had famously declared that upon looking within he could only find particular sensations, images, feelings, and thoughts, and never his “self.” But the dominant position in contemporary psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy derives from Hume, not from James. Particularly with the recent rise of connectionism and dynamic systems theory (Chapter 1), our experience of ourselves as causally effective agents has come increasingly to be portrayed as mere illusion, with consciousness itself at best a causally ineffectual by-product of the grinding of our neural machinery. There is in reality nobody in charge, no executive. We are nothing but self-organizing packs of neurons. “Sub-jectless processes” do all the work. Pronouncements of this general type abound, for example, in recent books and papers by prominent figures such as the Churchlands, Francis Crick, Daniel Dennett, Jean-Pierre Dupuy, Gerald Edelman, Walter Freeman, Douglas Hofstadter, Steven Pinker, and numerous others.

Possibly the most extreme specimen to date of this genre is the book by Harvard psychologist Daniel Wegner (2002). Having identified Dennett in his preface as a primary intellectual influence, and having then quoted on page 1 Laplace’s 1814 description of the mechanical clockwork universe as an epitome of the scientifically proper view of things, Wegner proceeds with no apparent sense of irony or paradox to generate some 400 pages of argument in support of Thomas Huxley’s original claim that our experience of conscious will as causally efficacious is entirely illusory. Nothing could more aptly summarize our own estimation of such views than the caustic remark by Whitehead (1929/1958) that “scientists animated by the purpose of proving themselves purposeless constitute an interesting subject for study” (p. 16). Could anything possibly be more remote from the views of William James, for whom conscious will was a living and undeniable reality, and the active regulation of our conscious mental life its essential manifestation?48

We believe that these extraordinary mainstream conclusions, so deeply at odds with the most fundamental deliverances of everyday experience, result from correctly perceiving what are in fact necessary consequences of the classical materialist-monist premises from which practically all of contemporary psychology, neuroscience, and philosophy derive. We further contend that disastrous consequences of this magnitude ought to be recognized by everybody for what they really are, a reductio ad absurdum of those materialist-monist premises themselves. The only possible justification for clinging to results so monstrous must be the belief that there is no alternative, no scientifically legitimate way of avoiding them. But we have clearly shown, we submit, that this belief is mistaken.

In sum, then, to move in the theoretical directions outlined here seems to us both necessitated by a wide range of empirical data and scientifically justified at the foundational level of physics itself. Which of the main types of theory we have distinguished will ultimately prove most satisfactory, and indeed whether they are in the end meaningfully different types of theory, remains to be seen. But something along these lines seems to us sure to emerge, however long this may take, and we predict with high confidence that psychology will not end up, as many have feared, being cannibalized either by neurophysiology or by sociology.

Our theoretical suggestions are responsive to Chomsky’s repeated pleas for “unification” between an empirically adequate psychology and a deepened conception of its physical basis (Introduction), and they restore the most mature concerns of our most luminous predecessor, William James—which have been systematically ignored by mainstream psychology for over a century—to the place which he himself believed they should rightfully occupy at the center of our science. In effect we seem to have come full circle, to a view of human nature much like that advanced by Myers, James, and their colleagues. But we emphatically do not see this as a matter of going backward to something already fully formed, already completed and perfected at their hands and ready to be adopted as is. It would be more accurate to say that we have reached the corresponding point on the next higher turn of a spiral. For their basic picture of the human psyche can now be anchored to physical science at a much deeper level, and the further development of that picture can surely capitalize on the tremendous methodological and technical advances that have been achieved in the intervening century.

The expanded scientific psychology that would result from such efforts can potentially overcome the great historical divisions within psychology, while also strengthening its principal domains individually. In general terms we can readily foresee, for example, a deepened cognitive mainstream in which the present elevation of the physical or physiological at the expense of consciousness and the mental has been essentially inverted. Computational modeling in all its forms would be downgraded from a general theory of the mind to a useful but limited applications technology (Searle, 1992). Consciousness would be more widely recognized as the constitutive problem of the field (G. A. Miller, 1985), and far greater resources and effort would be allocated than at present to research focused upon relationships between unusual states of consciousness and brain processes, as for example in psychophysiological and neuroimaging studies of OBEs and NDEs, psychedelics, meditation and related transformative practices, mystical experience, and other altered states. More penetrating investigations of psychophysical influence and psychological automatisms along lines suggested in Chapters 3 and 5 are surely in order, and there would also be greatly increased emphasis on currently unsolved problems in cognitive and personality theory—in particular, unsolved problems in regard to intentionality, meaning, symbolism, memory, personal identity, selfhood, and volition—that are deeply intertwined and central to our concerns as human beings.

We can also imagine a revitalization of dynamic psychiatry, complementary to the current vogue in biological psychiatry, that would result in development of new and potentially more effective forms of dynamic therapy, fuller exploration of the “mythopoetic” dimensions of human personality (Ellenberger, 1970), and more satisfactory approaches to socially and personally vital issues such as end-of-life care. Transpersonal psychology, similarly, can certainly be brought into better relationship with the mainstream, with its central impulses and concerns grounded primarily in real empirical knowledge rather than faith in the wisdom traditions. We also anticipate the development of a new generation of improved transformative practices, tools for refashioning ourselves in accordance with the enlarged psychology, that will enable many more of us to draw more efficiently and systematically upon normally inaccessible interior resources of imagination, creativity, and spirituality.

The key to this fundamentally optimistic vision, we repeat, is to build upon the foundation prepared by Myers and James. No other system of psychology has seriously rivaled its unique combination of unremitting commitment to empirical rigor with courage to embrace the supernormal and transpersonal phenomena that are essential to a fuller understanding of human mind and personality. Not that it should be regarded as a finished product, of course—surely the last thing either of them would have imagined or wished. It is rather a working guide, a provisional map of the territory, to be fleshed out and further improved by the labors of coming generations. Indeed, we can do no better here, in concluding both this chapter and our book as a whole, than to appropriate one last statement from Myers himself, as relevant today as when he first wrote it:

The research on which my friends and I are engaged is not the mere hobby of a few enthusiasts. Our opinions, of course, are individual and disputable; but the facts presented here and in the S.P.R. Proceedings are a very different matter. Neither the religious nor the scientific reader can longer afford to ignore them, to pass them by. They must be met, they must be understood, unless Science and Religion alike are to sink into mere obscurantism. And the one and only way to understand them is to learn more of them; to collect more evidence, to try more experiments, to bring to bear on this study a far more potent effort of the human mind than the small group who have thus far been at work can possibly furnish. Judged by this standard, the needed help has still to come. Never was there a harvest so plenteous with labourers so few. (HP, vol. 2, p. 80)

 

1. See Chapter 2. McDougall continued throughout his career to misrepresent Myers in these ways, as can be seen for example in his Outline of Abnormal Psychology (McDougall, 1926, p. 523).

2. To assist modern readers, we have provided on our digital version of HP translations of all non-English passages.

3. In fact, in reviews of two annual volumes of L’année psychologique published shortly before his death Myers had already begun to lament the direction that scientific psychology was taking toward limited and ultimately trivial experimental studies (see our Chapter 2).

4. At the University of Virginia, for example, 836 cases of NDEs and 1,200 cases of young children who claim to remember a previous life have been entered into such computerized databases.

5. Parenthetically, the 20th-century contraction of “psychical research” to its desiccated modern descendant, “parapsychology,” was if anything even more extreme than that experienced by psychology generally. At the hands of J. B. Rhine, the field suffered a kind of “identification with the aggressor”—that is, with the experimental behaviorism of the early-to-mid 20th century—and confined itself in large part not merely to experimental and statistical methods but to methods of an unnecessarily primitive and limited sort (Burdick & Kelly, 1977). Although this has begun to change in recent decades, parapsychology still falls far short of what the founders of psychical research envisioned, as reflected in particular by the tendency of many modern parapsychologists to treat psi phenomena as free-floating “anomalies” rather than trying, like Myers, to incorporate them within a larger framework of interrelated psychological phenomena.

6. It has been overlooked that Myers’s colleague Edmund Gurney had apparently arrived at closely similar views, and for reasons at least partly independent of Myers, prior to his untimely death in 1888. In Gurney et al. (1886) he first points out that phenomena of hypnosis and secondary personality render it difficult “to measure human existence by the limits of the phenomenal self.” Moreover, he goes on, “the very nature of this difficulty cannot but suggest a deeper solution than the mere connection of various streams of psychic life in a single organism. It suggests that a single individuality may have its psychical being, so to speak, on different planes; that the strong fragments of ‘unconscious intelligence,’ and the alternating selves of ‘double consciousness,’ belong really to a more fundamental unity, which finds in what we call life very imperfect conditions of manifestation; and that the self which ordinary men habitually regard as their proper individuality may after all be only a partial emergence” (vol. 1, p. 231).

For philosophic elaboration and justification of such a conception Gurney also appeals to Du Prel (1889/1976). Recall here too that Braude (1995) independently reached a similar position based on his philosophical analysis of multiple personality disorder (see our Chapter 5).

7. The analysis of Myers’s theory by Balfour, a philosopher, is the most serious and sustained attempt known to me to grapple directly with its central conceptual difficulties. Balfour undertook this effort in conjunction with his intensive study of communications delivered by the trance medium “Mrs. Willett” from the ostensibly surviving personalities of Myers and Gurney. If nothing else this material illustrates, on Balfour’s view, the automatic production of intellectual activity outstripping the known capacities of the medium in her ordinary state, as in the case of Patience Worth (Balfour, 1935, p. 300).

8. Parenthetically, it seems very unlikely that McDougall would not have been aware of this clarification. It had long been in the literature when McDougall was writing Body and Mind, and in his memorial address McDougall (1911) describes James as having been “for many years the largest influence affecting my intellectual life” (p. 12). We can be sure in any case that this clarification would have been one of the first points James brought to McDougall’s attention, had they ever discussed the subject.

9. Even McDougall (1911/1961) himself seems at times to verge on acceptance of the Myers/ James view. For example, he accepts the existence of inclusive memory in multiple personality cases such as that of Miss Beauchamp (p. 369), and at one point he even suggests that “by conceiving the animating principle of each organism as but relatively individual, as a bud from the tree of life, it seems possible dimly to foreshadow a synthesis of the Animism of James and Bergson with the hypothesis [his soul-theory] discussed in these concluding paragraphs” (P- 377).

10. The central and very obscure difficulty here, also recognized by McDougall, is that the activity of a mind involves more than its occurrent aspect, the stream of consciousness, with specific isolable contents such as particular images, thoughts, and the like. Knowing, for example, that someone has in mind the image of an elderly bearded man would tell you very little of what is actually going on in that person’s mind. For the Subliminal Self to be fully inclusive of the supraliminal self, it would have to be somehow inclusive of its hidden dispositional properties and point of view as well. Much more is involved in “inclusiveness,” that is, than merely treating the Subliminal Self or Individuality as a large set of discrete “elements of personality,” some subset of which can be told off into the supraliminal self or personality and shared by both (see also Braude, 1979).

11. See the Appendix. Another interesting kind of survival evidence involves the display not only of appropriate information but of high-level skills such as the linguistic skills involved in “responsive xenoglossy,” the capacity to speak fluently a foreign language not learned by normal means. Stevenson, for example, has documented extensively the case of Sharada, in which a secondary personality in a young Hindu woman spoke and wrote an archaic form of Bengali appropriate to the life she claimed to have led some 150 years earlier. She also provided factual details about that life that Stevenson was able to verify, but only by means of an extremely laborious investigation of obscure historical records (Stevenson, 1984; Stevenson & Pasricha, 1979; see also Braude, 2003, chap. 4).

12. The survival hypothesis itself, of course, must also invoke psi processes of some sort to account for information flows between mediums and communicators.

13. The same comment applies, of course, in relation to the evidence for reincarnation.

14. Parenthetically, major 20th-century philosophers such as Alexander, Bergson, and Whitehead, in addition to James, maintained generically similar views.

15. I find it especially ironic that sophisticated evolutionary biologists like Lumsden find fault with “Darwinian” creativity models of the sorts proposed by psychologists such as D. T. Campbell (1960), Perkins (1995), and Simonton (1995) on grounds that biological evolution itself is not as simplistically mechanistic as they appear to think. I agree, together with diverse critics from Hadamard (1949) to Koestler (1964), Boden (1991), and Eysenck (1995), that any conception which takes random variation as the basis of real human creativity is fundamentally flawed—a bad metaphor and little else.

16. This applies especially to a part of his doctrine I did not discuss—namely, his conviction that individual human personalities may continue to develop or “evolve” in the postmortem state. To my knowledge, there is presently little or no credible evidence for such a view.

17. From here on I will speak more consistently in the first person plural, reflecting the fact that what follows is to a much greater extent the product of very extensive discussions involving all authors of the present book and many additional parties as well. The opinions stated are in all cases strong majority positions, but I am primarily responsible for details of their formulation, and not all of us are in full accord on all points. We are, however, unanimous in regard to certain more general attitudes, including in particular an admiration for Myers and his synoptic naturalism, skepticism about the current received wisdom in psychology and neuroscience, openness to unorthodox findings where properly evidenced, and a conviction that the world is at bottom a much more puzzling place than contemporary mainstream science admits. Individual authors are of course responsible for opinions expressed in their own chapters.

18. That Chalmers is an epiphenomenalist follows from his arguments for the conceiv-ability of “zombies,” creatures that lack consciousness but nonetheless are equivalent to us cognitively. We reject both the epiphenomenalism and his endorsement of strong artificial intelligence.

19. There is a strangely incomplete or asymmetric pattern of connections among James, Myers, Schiller, and Bergson—all early advocates of filter-type theories—which invites further historical investigation. James (1898/1900) is usually given primary credit for formulating the transmission theory, yet he himself acknowledged that Schiller (1891/1894) had already worked it out in greater detail. James’s formulation relies heavily on Fechner’s concept of the psychophysical threshold or limen, but he does not point out the close parallel with Myers’s ideas, invoking Myers only as an investigator of supernormal phenomena. Myers, meanwhile, makes no explicit reference to transmission theory as formulated by either James, Schiller, or Bergson, and references Schiller and Bergson only in regard to a single case study each. Nonetheless Schiller (1905, p. 66) explicitly identifies Myers’s general theory as a splendid example of transmission theory and laments that Myers himself did not describe it in those terms. Yet James corresponded extensively with both Myers and Schiller around the time of the Ingersoll lecture, and with Bergson later on (Perry, 1935), and all four were members of the SPR.

20. In an unpublished essay on Myers that he was still developing at the time of his death, C. D. Broad concluded that this was Myers’s own philosophic position. This unfinished essay, “The Life and Work of F. W. H. Myers,” can be found among Broad’s papers in the archives of Trinity College, Cambridge.

21. There has recently been a modest revival of interest in dualism among philosophers as well; see for example J. Foster (1991), E. J. Lowe (1996), Madell (1988), and Smythies and Beloff (1989). Unfortunately, these philosophic discussions often fail to make contact with relevant empirical literature; in Corcoran (2001), for example, the possibility of post-mortem survival is assessed almost exclusively in light of the apparent a priori viability of philosophical theories that seem to permit it, and without reference to the available empirical evidence.

22. See Mandler (1978). Of course associationist theories have subsequently revived in the form of “connectionism,” as described in Chapter 1. Note the irony here that the anti-asso-ciationist arguments of Popper and Eccles, as well as those of William James and numerous other early critics including in particular the Gestalt psychologists, have once again become relevant. See also J. Fodor (2001).

23. Note that similar analogies are regularly invoked by dynamic systems theorists such as W. J. Freeman (1999, 2000).

24. For authoritative but readable surveys see for example Capek (1961), Whitehead (1925/1953, 1938/1968), and Stapp (2004a, 2005a).

25. Eugene Wigner (1962, p. 285) similarly remarked that the laws of quantum mechanics cannot be formulated consistently without recourse to the concept of consciousness. Although Wigner himself subsequently retreated from this position, Stapp (2004a) shows that his reasons for doing so are not compelling.

26. Physicist and brain theorist Paul Nunez (1995) remarks that “an appreciation of the grand conceptual leap required in the transition from classical to quantum systems may give us some vague feeling for how far from current views neuroscience may eventually lead. Such humbling recognition will perhaps make us especially skeptical of attempts to ‘explain away’ (that is with tautology) data that do not merge with common notions about consciousness, such as multiple conscious entities in a single brain, hypnosis, and so on” (p. 158).

27. Eccles had originally proposed that this dynamic instability might be exploited by “triggering” certain “critically poised” neurons, using the quantum indeterminacy associated with neurotransmitter molecules in the synaptic cleft itself to effect the triggering without violation of conservation laws. It soon became evident, however, that these molecules are too large, and the distances too long. Eccles himself subsequently settled on the exocytosis mechanism as a critical site (Beck & Eccles, 1992; Eccles, 1994).

28. We note in passing that the received causal doctrine of conventional neuroscience, that system-level properties of the brain are produced by bottom-up local interactions of its constituent microentities, is the one-dimensional historical residue of a much richer causal doctrine dating back to the Greeks, one that specifically incorporates downward mental or “ontic” causation. For a sustained philosophic argument in support of ontic causation, informed by modern developments in cognitive neuroscience, see Pols (1998).

29. Clearly on this view the occurrence of such phenomena depends partly on conditions within the mind or consciousness of the agent, partly on conditions having to do with the character of the targeted physical system itself, and partly, perhaps, on the availability of appropriate feedback. This invites further work, both theoretical and experimental, to delineate more precisely what the relevant conditions are, and how they can be instantiated or exploited experimentally. We also note in passing that this sort of view seems to us preferable to the view apparently held by Myers (HP, vol. 2, pp. 505–554), according to which the Subliminal Self consciously manipulates all necessary low-level details of the neural and biochemical machinery in order to produce the targeted effects.

30. Following Myers, we presume that the intelligence which determines precisely what products of subliminal activity achieve supraliminal expression under particular brain conditions is itself subliminal

31. We refer here especially to Uttal’s discussion of experimental and logical issues in neuroimaging research; better introductions to the imaging techniques themselves can be found elsewhere. Related diatribes regarding problems in neuroimaging research can be found at http://www.human-brain.org.

32. Analogous comments certainly apply to our presently impoverished means for describing and differentiating states of consciousness in general. Similar positions as to the unitary character of mind were staked out much earlier by commentators such as James (1890b), McDougall (1911/1961), and Broad (1925/1960). Uttal himself concludes that we should fall back to a more sophisticated form of behaviorism (p. 206); however, his working list of the great questions of scientific psychology (his Appendix A) suggests that he may also be open to more radical theoretical options of the sort we are advocating here, at least if they are forced upon us by data (as we believe they are).

33. James (1890b, vol. 1, pp. 141–142) went so far as to suggest that the preserved concept of a lost or diminished mental function may somehow participate directly in the recovery of that function through appropriate repairs or modifications of the associated brain activity. We think this idea has merit, as did Myers (1891c, p. 116), but Myers was also certainly correct in cautioning as to the practical difficulties in evaluating it (see also Finger, LeVere, Almli, & Stein, 1988).

34. “Holism,” according to which the brain acts as an undifferentiated whole, goes back to antiquity and has waned and waxed and waned again in popularity across the history of modern neuroscience. The 19th century witnessed an upsurge of localization driven by the early discoveries of people like Fritsch and Hitzig, Broca, and Wernicke, but this produced an extreme holistic backlash in the 20th at the hands of Pierre Marie, Kurt Goldstein, Henry Head, and Karl Lashley. Lashley’s famously unsuccessful effort to locate “engrams” (memory traces) in animal brains was particularly influential in American psychology during the behaviorist period, but localizationists regained the ascendancy during the cognitive revolution. Current global workspace theories thus represent a compromise position, with partial reversion toward holism.

35. See especially Stevenson (1997). There may also be a parallel here with trance medium-ship, in that a number of the really successful communicators such as “G.P.” (see Gauld, 1968, 1982) have also suffered violent or sudden death. Perhaps “unfinished business” is somehow conducive to remembering, as in the well-known “Zeigarnik” effect.

36. Another possible manifestation of this “framing” process is the EEG “microstates” discovered by Dietrich Lehmann and colleagues (Lehmann, Ozaki, & Pal, 1987; Pascual-Mar-qui, Michel, & Lehmann, 1995). These are brief episodes of relatively stable topography in the scalp-recorded potential field, lasting on the order of 50–150 milliseconds and separated by sharp transitions. The manner and degree to which such segmentation of scalp potential fields corresponds to the rapidly changing structure of conscious experience remains to be determined, however.

37. Conversely, aphasia-like phenomena which often accompany the emergence of a new communicator (such as difficulties in speaking or writing the right words) might be viewed as expressions of the difficulties that psyche encounters in “operating” a partly unfamiliar organism. See Myers (HP, vol. 2, p. 254) for some interesting remarks on this subject.

38. For additional help in this regard, see the all-out assault on this everyday intuition by Harrison (1989).

39. Just as we have not taken Henry Stapp to be any sort of final or ultimate authority but rather as the primary representative of a group of quantum theorists whom we see as moving in broadly similar directions in regard to mind-brain relations, we are here taking Whitehead as representative of a larger group of “process” theorists working in what we are calling the neutral-monist tradition. Among these we include (in addition to Leibniz, the later James, and Whitehead himself in his Harvard period) major figures such as Charles Sanders Peirce, Henri Bergson, Bertrand Russell, Charles Hartshorne, and David Ray Griffin. We thank Eric Weiss for particularly helpful comments on this section.

40. The scare quotes in this sentence are meant to emphasize that the mentalistic terms employed here are being used broadly and metaphorically, and not as they would normally apply to the mental activity of a conscious human being. How far down nature can plausibly be viewed as manifesting such “mentalistic” properties remains an open question, but the threshold, if one exists, is undoubtedly much further down than most of us commonly assume. McDougall (1911/1969, pp. 258–260) found signs of unified and purposive behavior even in one-celled organisms such as the Amoeba and the Paramecium, and Seager (1998) has advanced somewhat similar arguments in regard to elemental units of inanimate nature itself.

41. Recall that very similar ideas in regard to “panaesthesia” as a more fundamental or primitive capacity for experience were expressed by Myers (Chapter 2).

42. Whitehead’s magnum opus, Process and Reality (1929/1978), is an extremely difficult book, but an excellent and readable introduction to his main ideas can be found in his last book (Whitehead, 1938/1968), especially Chapters 7 and 8. Griffin (1997, 1998, 2000) and Hosinski (1993) provide accurate and readable secondary sources, and G. R. Lucas (1989) and Griffin, Cobb, Ford, Gunter, and Ochs (1993) situate his work within the larger philosophic tradition.

43. See Eastman and Keeton’s on-line resource guide to physics and Whitehead, which is available at http://www.ctr4process.org/publications/PSS. It is also worth noting here that a similar neutral-monist position has tentatively been reached, from still another direction, by Chalmers (1996); see also his and other contributions to Shear (1998). Chalmers hardly mentions Whitehead at all, anchoring his neutral-monist sympathies instead in the work of Russell (1927). For critical comparative analysis of the neutral monisms of Russell and Whitehead, see Lovejoy (1930/1960) and G. R. Lucas (1989, chap. 7).

44. Parenthetically, physicist Oliver Lodge (1929) was probably the first to recognize the relevance of Whitehead’s metaphysics to the survival problem. Affinities between psi phenomena and the picture of “entangled” reality revealed by quantum theory have been carefully drawn out by Radin (2006), and Stapp (in press a), in his discussion of the Libet experiments, provides a potential solution for Griffin’s problems concerning precognition.

45. Related suggestions regarding NDEs and memory have recently been offered by Romijn (1997), who draws upon the generically similar quantum-mechanical theory of consciousness developed by David Bohm in his later years. Bohm himself attempted to use that same theory to explain psi phenomena, which he evidently took seriously (Bohm, 1986), and his neutral-monist conception of the “implicate order” has also been enlisted by Karl Pribram (1979, 1986,1991) in support of “holonomic” explanations of brain function, perception, and (receptive) psi, though with only limited success (Braude, 1979; Draaisma, 2000; see also Stapp, in press a, in press b, regarding technical problems in Bohm’s quantum mechanics).

46. A possible way forward is suggested by physicist and philosopher of science Abner Shi-mony in his critical response to Roger Penrose (1997) from the point of view of a “modernized Whiteheadianism” which “applies the framework of quantum theory to an ontology that is ab initio mentalistic” (Shimony, 1997, p. 154). Shimony portrays the emergence of conscious states from an ensemble of neurons, for example, as due to large-scale quantum entanglement, analogous to the demonstrated emergence in relatively small quantum systems of novel properties transcending those of their constituents. Quantum theory, that is, already encompasses a mode of composition that has no analogue in classical physics. Penrose himself subsequently endorsed these suggestions, stating that “although I had not explicitly asserted, in either Emperor or Shadows, the need for mentality to be ‘ontologically fundamental in the universe’, I think that something of this nature is indeed necessary” (1997, pp. 175–176). See also Seager (1998).

47. James (1890b) remarks that “if evolution is to work smoothly, consciousness in some shape must have been present at the very origin of things” (vol. 1, p. 149). See also the critique by Griffin (1998) of conventional accounts by Dennett, Humphrey, and others of the supposed incremental “emergence” of consciousness in the course of evolution.

48. This is not to say, of course, that all of our actions are fully under conscious supraliminal control. Both Myers and James recognized that aspects of experience and behavior are sometimes controlled in part or in whole by transmarginal influences of various kinds, whether automatic or “infrared” processes originating in the organism or “ultraviolet” influences exerted by a wider subliminal consciousness.