TO MAKE A FILM IS ALSO TO CONSTRUCT A WORLD. AS VIEWERS, WE are invited to enter into this world, to share it with its maker(s) and with other viewers. When made, experienced, and understood as art, the virtual worlds of films, including all narrative ones, not only provide a form of experience that approaches in many ways our actual, embodied life experience but also mediates it in aesthetic ways, sometimes to powerful cognitive and affective ends.
Taking the multifaceted concept of the world of an artwork as its starting point and principal focus throughout, this book explores the nature of cinematic art from both filmmaking and film-viewing perspectives. To the degree possible, given the complex and historically variable character of the cinema throughout its history, it attempts to provide an overarching theoretical framework that captures and expands on the insights of a number of notable film theorists, critics, and filmmakers regarding the world-like structures and experiences of narrative films, including Gilles Deleuze’s contention that cinema “does not just present images, it surrounds them with a world.”1 Yet it will also consider the relevance to cinema of long-established views concerning the created worlds of art and literary works, such as, for instance, that espoused by the Shakespearean scholar A. C. Bradley, who in an oft-cited 1901 lecture proposed that “[an artwork’s] nature is to be not a part, nor yet a copy, of the real world (as we commonly understand that phrase) but to be a world by itself, independent, complete, autonomous; and to possess it fully you must enter that world, conform to its laws, and ignore for the time the beliefs, aims, and particular conditions which belong to you in the other world of reality.”2
I approach the subject of cinematic art by way of philosophical theories of the symbolic, phenomenological, and hermeneutic aspects of art in general, which all converge on important topics in classical and contemporary film theory. With reference to its goal to provide an alternative, general framework for reflecting on the artistic dimensions, and to some degree accomplishments, of films, much of this study may be described aptly as “metatheoretical.” It is as much if not more concerned with analyzing and evaluating relevant theories of cinema, or certain of their major aspects (and of philosophical approaches to art as related to these), than with analyzing and understanding specific works or the aims and achievements of particular filmmakers. I do hope, however, that some of the ideas, concepts, and terms introduced (or reintroduced, as the case may be) will be seen as worth taking up and applying in more detailed analyses of individual films, styles, and genres.
By way of introduction to the leading term and concept of this study, what I conceive of as a “film world,” in the artistic and aesthetic senses to be explained and discussed, is a singular, holistic, relational, and fundamentally referential reality. Not strictly identical with the film work that occasions and presents it, a film world possesses pronounced sensory, symbolic, and affective dimensions. It provides “virtual” and actual experiences that are at once cognitive and immersive and “sensuous.” Both the creation and experiencing of film worlds are marked by complex and world-constitutive dynamics of transformation and immersion; these processes are not only relationally codependent but, via the anticipations of filmmakers and tacit understandings and expectations of audience members, mutually reinforcing. The transformation in question relies heavily on the given properties of the preexisting realities out of which a film is more or less creatively and skillfully made, while the viewer’s immersion includes but is not confined to engaging with fictional characters and situations in a partly literally depicted, but still largely imagination-constructed, story-world. Taken to mean the full being or presence of a cinematic work of art as it is intentionally constructed, experienced, and interpreted, a film world also constitutes a historical, transsubjective event of artistic and cinematic truth, as it concerns both cinematic and noncinematic life experience.
Apart from this specific film-as-world model, some readers may consider that a general inquiry into the aesthetic character of cinema exclusively is outmoded, for any variety of reasons. To speak of a given film as art, however, is not to deny its status as a historical document, a more or less accurate mirror or apt commentary on the society and culture in which it is made and seen, and as an intended or unintended vehicle for the communication of all manner of normative and ideological messages.3 Addressing the matter with pithy eloquence and a dose of irony, noted critic Andrew Sarris has written that the “nature of the film medium” means “you always get more for your money than mere art.”4 Although other uses, forms, and values of cinema converge with specifically artistic or aesthetic ones, to understand the complex interactions among them as realized in any given work requires some understanding of any film’s most typical artistic features and functions.
In the venerable tradition of aesthetic inquiry, coupled, however, with due regard for contemporary, skeptical arguments concerning the supposed autonomy of aesthetics (on “ontological” or similar grounds),5 I assume that cinematic art may be theoretically and philosophically explored not in total isolation from surrounding historical, institutional, psychological, ethical, and other, nonartistic realities but instead by achieving a certain separation and distance from any or all of these, which, to borrow from the language of phenomenology, amounts to the attempt to “bracket them off,” even if only temporarily or provisionally. Indeed, if we can no longer accept that studies pertaining to the nature and value of art stand in splendid isolation from all other departments of knowledge, possessed of their own metaphysical charter, so to speak, there is perhaps an equal and more immediate, intellectual danger in various, current forms of reductionism across the humanities. I refer here to a failure to cede to artistic creation and aesthetic experience both independent cognitive status and value, and a fully unencumbered “cultural space,” in the fundamental sense that Joseph Margolis, for instance, has recently attempted to give to this phrase.6
Of course, there is always in practice some overlap between what Richard Dyer terms a “formal-aesthetic” approach to cinema, focused on the question of a film’s “intrinsic worth” as art, and a “socio-ideological” one, centered on any “film’s position as symptom or influence in social processes.”7 Since at least the early 1970s, however, and as tied to complex cultural, historical, and disciplinary developments (too many to be rehearsed here), the latter approach has predominated in film studies, not least (but also not only) as a result of its substantial convergence with cultural studies as an emerging academic discipline and many of its typical concerns.8
Concerning a notable deemphasis of the cinematic work qua artwork David Bordwell has suggested that as a result of the widespread academic focus on film as a means of conveying sociopolitical and cultural messages and values, the “artistic aspects of cinema” have “often been ignored” (together with the “particularity of how cinema works as a unique art”).9 While this is certainly true, the full artistic dimension of films (including what may be specific to cinema), as distinct, for instance, from the narrative, emotional, technical, or even specifically perceptual dimension, is likewise often neglected in other, differently oriented approaches to theorizing film. These include the more empirical, conceptual, and problem-solving (as well as so-called piecemeal) approaches of several prominent authors (sometimes including Bordwell),10 whose writings, I hasten to add, the present study draws on where relevant.
For instance, postclassical accounts of film narrative in its cognitive aspects have substantially enriched our understanding of how film stories are put together and understood in a dynamic, audiovisual medium.11 They have opened up whole new avenues for film scholarship and brought a welcome level of conceptual and methodological rigor to thinking about stories told in cinematic form. In the process, however, and as a number of recent commentators have suggested, many such narratological accounts of cinema, as rooted in concepts and methodologies originating in the study of literary forms, and adapted to the moving image (with varying degrees of plausibility), have risked losing sight of aspects of the concrete perceptual, affective, and experiential (or “phenomenological”) character of the film-viewing experience. But also and equally, it must be added, they have sometimes failed to acknowledge large domains of artistically relevant cognitive, symbolic, and inescapably “cultural” meaning, as I hope to make clear. While certainly not denied in the writings of theorists within this tradition, these areas of film art and experience, on which I will concentrate, are frequently sidelined, seemingly taken for granted, or assumed to fall within the provenance of film criticism exclusively.
Kristin Thompson’s and Bordwell’s shared conception of cinematic “excess,” for example, valuably identifies a class of nonnarrative, artistic features of films and perspicaciously describes important aspects of their apprehension alongside, and in attentional oscillation with, narrative ones. This conception of excess, however, appears to suggest that all that constitutes “meaning” in film is strictly confined to either items of narrative import or to items of an autonomous and self-referential “artistic” (here meaning formal) significance, existing “for their own sake,” as it were.12 Such a theoretical premise risks neglecting what falls between (and outside of) these poles of creation and attention and that at the same time binds them together, and endows both story and cinematic form and technique with a work-defining, artistic meaning and value otherwise absent from each. I mean to refer here to what may be conceived as the expansive realm of “symbolic” import in cinematic art, in its cognitive and expressive registers alike, and as cutting across any form-and-content dichotomy that may be usefully applied to cinema. On a related note, what Mark J. P. Wolf observes with reference to the imaginary worlds of narrative works of all kinds—that “what might appear to be ‘excess’ from a narrative-oriented point of view, may prove to be necessary from a world-oriented point of view”13—is equally, if not more true, of the artistic worlds of films as here conceived.
Bordwell has proposed four other sorts of art that, in addition to “narrative art,” the cinema may be seen to encompass: photographic, performing, pictorial, and audiovisual. In his view theoretical approaches may focus attention on one or more of these “conceptions of film art.” (Moreover, since cinema is also an “emotional art,” he also suggests that “it would be worthwhile to tease out the different sorts of emotion that each perspective tends to emphasize.”)14 While this all seems perfectly right, I believe emphasis should more squarely fall on the fact that every live-action narrative film, for instance, has all of these dimensions and interests simultaneously, even if some films may choose to foreground stylistic features relevant to one or more of these aspects, to the relative exclusion of others (as Bordwell also aptly notes). More generally, however, and as transcending these largely formal or medial categories, in speaking throughout this book of cinematic art, I do not, as will become clear, mean to refer to only medial, formal, perceptual or technical aspects of films nor to film style as more narrowly conceived. The artistic dimension of cinema, as here explored, encompasses the whole domain of the types of meaning and expression (i.e., feeling and emotive contents), as well as created forms and structures, which are traditionally and still frequently associated with artworks of every form, type, and period, and their experience. In other words, my intended reference is to the whole of what is or can make cinematic works not only nominal but genuine instances of art, in certain accepted, relatively unproblematic, and descriptive senses of the term—as distinct, that is, from their natures as sensory spectacles, pure entertainments, and visually rendered narrative fictions (alone).
More specifically, the concept of cinematic art pursued in this book, and following the views of the principal thinkers cited and discussed, regards narrative films as both representational—in the most general sense of affording us with symbolically constructed models of experience and “ways of knowing”—and presentational, as inseparably connected to aesthetic perception and appreciation (for all that this latter notion entails). Correspondingly, whereas in much contemporary (analytic) philosophy of art, the “aesthetic” as a category is often taken to refer to the formal and sensuous properties of works as conceived and experienced apart from their represented and interpreted (or interpretable) “content,” here it will be understood more broadly as applying to potentially all of a film work’s distinctly artistic forms, meanings, experiences, and values, in contrast with its first-order nonartistic ones.15
In presenting the following account of the worlds of films as artworks, no attempt will be made to elucidate a theory of the aesthetic as such or on a priori grounds. I will assume, however, the general, continuing viability of such concepts as “aesthetic experience,” the “aesthetic attitude,” “aesthetic judgment,” “aesthetic appreciation,” and so on, as these may continue to be subject to critical examination and revision.16 A somewhat more specific (although by no means exhaustive) notion of the aesthetic as a fundamental mode of human cultural experience and, to varying degrees, individual expression, with respect to cinema, will be developed and will emerge bit by bit, as it were, as we proceed. For the moment it is necessary to remind ourselves that the so-called aesthetic attitude is, properly speaking, a heterodox and complex affair in which a great deal of “cognitive” and “cultural” integration takes place and in which perception, intuition, imagination, reflection, and interpretation all play a part. As philosopher Alan Goldman has suggested, to be fully engaged with any artwork, including a film, is “not simply to pay close perceptual attention to formal detail and complex internal relations in the object’s structure, but also to bring to bear one’s cognitive grasp of those external and historical relations that inform one’s aesthetic experience, and to be receptive to the expressive qualities that emerge through this interaction. Knowledge that can inform one’s experience of a work includes that of the artist’s intentions, techniques, attitudes, problems overcome, and so on.”17
In this context it must be remembered that just as not all art is narrative, not all narratives are artistic in either intent or experience. Moreover, it is possible, and not uncommon, to engage with artworks that tell stories, including films, on a predominantly narrative level alone, which (whatever else) is clearly not to experience and appreciate their full meaning and values as artworks. From the descriptive, as distinct from evaluative or critical, standpoint that we will for the most part adopt, all fictional narrative films may be seen to have some artistic aspects, as cinema’s frequent designation as “popular art” or “mass art” implicitly assumes. Despite the suggestion of some past and present film theorists and philosophers of film, however, the easy or “natural” accessibility of the majority of films made today, or at any point in the past, to very large audiences, and their popular appeal, does not necessarily reflect some deep, fundamental truth about all cinematic art and the range of forms (relatively more or less demanding) it may take or allow for. Rather, as Noël Carroll has rightly stressed, it reflects on particular, relatively more accessible, uses of the medium and its now firmly established institutions.
Focused on films as artistically made and experienced “worlds,” many of the arguments I propose in this study may be taken to apply not only to both celluloid and digital productions but to potentially all types of narrative films of all periods—from classical Hollywood westerns and musicals, to European and Asian “art films,” from large-budget studio-backed films to small, independent productions. All may create and present worlds in the senses noted above insofar as they are aesthetically realized totalities possessed of sensory, expressive, thematic, and narrative dimensions (albeit, of course, with widely varying and unequal degrees of artistic ambition and success). Moreover, at least some of what is here maintained concerning cinematic world-making and experience is also applicable to nonnarrative and nonrepresentational films and cinevideo works as diverse as Norman McLaren’s Dots, Andy Warhol’s Empire, Stan Brakhage’s Dog Star Man, and Douglas Gordon’s 24 Hour Psycho. Documentary films, as well, can be readily seen to create worlds in our present sense (the fact that they attempt to show us aspects of the “real world” notwithstanding). With respect to so many of the techniques, materials, constraints, and artistic potentials of filmmaking, the worlds of films of these disparate kinds are all part of the same extended family, sharing more than just a common medium or media. Moreover, the proposed model underscores the necessity of conceiving cinematic art in a way that is not exclusively tied to the distinct features of celluloid (or “analog”) filmmaking—since, as will be shown, a cinematic work and its constructed world cannot be wholly assimilated to the pregiven properties of any specific moving-image medium or format and its technological basis.
As the above comments and initial definitions suggest, the concept of a “film world” represents an attempt to bring together and to unify the full cognitive-symbolic, affective, and hermeneutic dimensions of a narrative cinematic work of art, as these work in, through, and beyond perceptual (audiovisual) and fictional-narrative features and structures. Correspondingly, my tripartite account of a film work and world proceeds through (1) various related theories of symbolization, particularly that developed by Nelson Goodman in his analytical conception of artistic “world making” and the full referential nature of artworks; (2) phenomenological aesthetics, in the form of Mikel Dufrenne’s to some extent Kantian account of artistic feeling and expression; and (3) the hermeneutical approach to art of Hans-Georg Gadamer, as rooted in Heidegger’s critique of continental, post-Kantian sensationalism and formalism in aesthetics, and of a conception of art as an “event” of revealed truth.
Largely underrepresented in current film theory and the philosophy of film, these general approaches are by no means incompatible, as some readers familiar with one or more of them may assume. When taken together and to a degree synthesized with one another and related film theory and criticism, they aptly reflect film art’s simultaneous appeal to our senses, emotions, and intellects. That said, this book does not undertake the task of defending the several, so-called analytic and continental aesthetic theories and philosophies of art discussed but, rather, seeks to apply relevant parts of them to cinema. And it seeks to do so in such a way that will not only better illuminate the artistic and aesthetic aspects of films and their worlds but serve to recommend and encourage greater interest in the use of these frameworks of ideas in a film theory and philosophy of film context. From a wider perspective, if it is accepted that cinematic works (and the worlds they construct) are complex, heterogeneous, and multimodal in terms of their address in consciousness, then their more successful theoretical understanding and discussion may actually require a certain conceptual and methodological pluralism and eclecticism, cutting across established analytic and continental lines, as well as “cognitive” and semiotic ones, for example.
Apart from the above-mentioned authors, there is another prominent intellectual debt to be acknowledged, which may also help to orient the reader. As well as a critic, filmmaker, and cofounder of Paris’s renowned Cinémathèque française, Jean Mitry was one of the first scholars of film history and theory in a university context (teaching at the Institut des hautes études cinématographiques and the Université de Paris). His massively detailed Aesthetics and Psychology of Cinema (published in 1963, only translated into English in 1997) is arguably the last great theoretical work devoted to cinema as art, prior to the pronounced shift toward the investigation of the specifically social-ideological nature and use of cinema that occurred in film theory and some serious film criticism in France and elsewhere very shortly after its publication.18 An attempt to understand film art against the background of general aesthetic theory, Mitry’s book (which I have frequent occasion to cite) is also at least one (needed) bridge between and among symbol-centered and phenomenological accounts of art and film. Through its critical engagement with both classical formalist and realist film theory, and its balanced critique of mid-twentieth-century semiotic, structuralist, and poststructuralist approaches to cinema, it also clearly points forward to Deleuze’s highly influential philosophy of film, with which it has some clear and seldom-discussed affinities. Mitry is correct in a number of respects when he writes, for instance, that there is not just a gap but “a world between” the perceived space that actors and characters occupy on the screen and the space of viewers in watching it.19 Along with this cinematically created world structure and experience, I am interested in the nature and effects of the distance and separation in question, together with how (as Mitry also inquires) this is simultaneously a closeness, an association, and a participation on the part of viewers.
Still on the subject of reference points and precedents: Dudley Andrew, an early champion and interpreter of Mitry in an English-language context (as well as of phenomenological approaches to cinema well before their current vogue), is one of the few scholars within disciplinary film studies to explicitly entertain the central idea of films as artistic worlds distinct from fictional story-worlds. He has done so with reference to some of the same theorists, philosophers, and traditions with whom I will engage, even if, as it must also be added, Andrew invokes these, together with the common backbone and unifying theoretical ground of our present study, in a comparatively brief and provisional way.20
All that remains to complete this introduction is a brief summary of the book’s structure and the sequence of its main arguments, some of which are cumulative in nature. The first chapter covers a good deal of necessary philosophical and theoretical ground and, as the reader should be aware, possesses a certain density of detail and argument, as a result. It forwards a series of interconnected observations and arguments concerning the need to make a fundamental distinction between the fictional world “in” a cinematic work and the more than fictional and narrative world “of” it, as including and enclosing the former (since, in aesthetic terms, worlds are not only the products of fiction and narratives in various media). This distinction, which is founded in recognition of both the representational and what may be termed “presentational” dimensions of films, is supported by critical consideration of significant philosophical and film-theoretical issues that cluster around existing logical and fictional, “heterocosmic,” narrative-diegetic, and phenomenological conceptions of films as created and experienced worlds. I will argue that these differently oriented world-conceptions, as shared by some philosophers and literary and film theorists, are highly instructive and useful but also seriously incomplete in aesthetic terms. Thus, in pursuing a more holistic, less reductive model of the artistic world-character of a narrative film, it is necessary to move beyond them in certain specified directions.
Chapter 2 focuses more directly on the term and concept of world itself. In any cultural context of reference, worlds (plural) are seen to necessarily entail forms of symbolic thought and representation. The discussion here relies on a post-Kantian tradition of thought on symbolization and experience that has been relatively neglected in aesthetics and the philosophy of art (from at least the second half of the twentieth century to the present), as well as being seldom discussed in contemporary film theory and the burgeoning philosophy of film. Insofar as certain ideas and relevant works of philosophers such as Ernst Cassirer and Susanne K. Langer have suffered decades of eclipse by other continental and analytic movements and schools of thought concerning symbolization, art, and expression that have been favored in aesthetics and film and art theory (and the humanities generally), the tradition in question may not be familiar to many contemporary readers. It is, however, one indispensable source and background to our present understandings of the full “cognitive” aspects of filmmaking and film viewing, together with at least some cinematic affect. This is indicated in Goodman’s powerful insight that “how an object or event functions as a work explains how, through certain modes of reference, what so functions may contribute to a vision of—and to the making of—a world.”21
In further making a case for the relevance of this general philosophical tradition to both cinematic art and film theory, chapter 3 teases out the multifaceted relations between its basic positions and Mitry’s and Pier Paolo Pasolini’s symbol-centered descriptions of (all) artistic filmmaking, as also overlapping with certain aspects of Deleuze’s. At issue is how the materials of a cinematic work (celluloid or digital), drawn from “natural” and cultural sources alike, and in the form of images and sounds both captured and constructed, are transformed into aesthetic features (or elements) in symbolic (and “virtual”), as well as physical-material, ways. In this process the original meanings and affects of these materials are typically both retained and surpassed for intended artistic purposes, in a fashion specific to cinema in at least some significant respects.
Chapters 4 and 5 represent what is, as far as I am aware, the first more systematic and wide-ranging attempt to apply Goodman’s symbolic account of art and world-making to cinema. In chapter 4 I propose to show how film theory and criticism may make productive use of the five distinct processes for consciously constructing new worlds out of older ones that are identified and described by the American philosopher, given how these processes map onto recognizable stylistic features of films, and filmmaking techniques, that contribute to the creation of cinematic worlds. Goodman’s related classification of types and functions of symbolic reference relations (assumed in his chronologically later account of artworks as exercises in world-making) is the jumping-off point, in chapter 5, for a consideration of the types of literal and, especially, figurative symbolization to be found in film art. Primary here is Goodman’s groundbreaking recognition of the full and crucial role of symbolic “exemplification” in art, as a form of targeted self-reference on the part of works in all forms. Properly understood (and with some additions and changes of emphases in comparison with Goodman’s original account), exemplification is considered central to a film’s artistic presence, meaning, and interpretation. I will also argue (although more provisionally) that it provides a basis for a new, alternative model of (self-)reflexivity, as a prominent feature of many artistically significant narrative films. Finally, this explication of multiple kinds of reference at work in art is brought to bear on the identification and classification of artistic styles in cinema. Here I offer in condensed fashion the ideas of what I term a film’s constitutive “world-markers,” together with the sort of stylistic categories of film worlds (“film-world types”) that may be regarded as following from these.
Turning to the film-viewing experience, under the umbrella heading of cinematic affect as “expression,” in chapter 6 I offer qualified support for certain models and theories of film-produced feeling and emotion that have been proposed recently, especially within cognitive film theory and the philosophy of film. These are presented, however, as but one important part of the total artistic picture with respect to the major affective dimension of films. In an attempt to sketch a more complete map of film “feeling,” I propose a four-part typology of characteristic forms of cinematic expression, consisting of what I call “local” sensory-affective, cognitive-diegetic, and formal-artistic types, alongside a more “global” aesthetic one. Aspects of these forms of affective expression are argued to clearly correspond to ways in which the film viewer may be engaged with, and immersed in, a cinematic work in pronounced fashion. The discussion here is in some ways a microcosm of this study as a whole. Insofar, that is to say, that it attempts to show that whereas no current, single theoretical or methodological approach or paradigm in film theory (or the philosophy of film) is a sufficient conceptual lens through which to view the entirety of a narrative film as a singular work of art—affectively or otherwise—a number of them appropriately put together and applied to it may facilitate our understandings of certain constitutive levels or aspects of it.
As discussed in more detail in chapter 7, which also addresses the topics of time and rhythm in film worlds, the several forms of cinematic expression and immersion include what can be seen as a distinctly aesthetic form of cinematic affect that I call a film work’s total (or global) cine aesthetic world-feeling. In accordance with Dufrenne’s more general arguments concerning all aesthetic objects (and with its Kantian reference points), this fourth category of cinematic affect, expression, and immersion, largely heretofore unrecognized (at least in any more detailed, theoretical fashion) is conceived as bound to the so-called lived or felt time of a film (as well as an overall cinematic rhythm). The particular connection between this complex aesthetic and experiential constellation of feeling and temporality, and the filmmaker in his or her role as artistic “world creator,” is explored through the critical juxtaposition of the concept of cinematic world-feeling with a number of well-known and overlapping auteur and expression-centered views of film art.
The final chapter reflects the aforementioned shift to a hermeneutic frame of reference. In full acknowledgment that a more detailed and comprehensive hermeneutics of film worlds must await further development, I argue that along with being objectively accessible symbolic and artistic objects (or, more precisely, proposed symbol schemes), and “private,” first-person aesthetic experiences, film worlds are also public, historical, and intersubjectively accessible events. As such, they may be conceived as the occasions for the disclosure of artistic truth that Gadamer (following Heidegger’s reflections on art) articulates in his major work Truth and Method and other writings, wherein he maintains that the very presence of the artwork places a demand to be understood on its beholder. This is a communicative demand that is only met and fulfilled in an active participation, negotiation, and “dialogue” with the work in the context of cultural and artistic (and here, cinematic) tradition. Building on this existential hermeneutic account of the character and function of the artwork as transposed to cinema, and following in the hallowed critical footsteps of François Truffaut, I will maintain that film worlds possess, and are capable of conveying, two distinct, if also often overlapping, forms of knowledge and enlightenment, as pertaining, respectively, to “life” and to “cinema” (i.e., as art). Such truth, as a product of both film form and content, and at once revealed (or “disclosed”) and interpreted, is claimed to be a major aspect of a cinematic work’s interest and value, both cognitive and aesthetic.